Penultimate draft, please cite from published version only
(2018) Res Philosophica Vol. 95, No.4, 663-692
Fine-Tuned of Necessity?1
Abstract
This paper seeks to explicate and analyse an alternative response to fine-tuning arguments
from those that are typically given, namely, design or brute contingency. The response I
explore is based on necessity, the necessitarian response. After showing how necessity blocks
the argument, I explicate the reply I claim necessitarians can give, and suggest how its three
requirements can be met. Firstly that laws are metaphysically necessary, secondly that
constants are metaphysically necessary, and thirdly that the fundamental properties which
determine the laws and constants are necessary. After discussing each in turn, I end the paper
by assessing how the response fares when running the fine-tuning argument in two ways, as
an inference to best explanation and as a Bayesian argument.
Fine-tuning arguments for theism generally run as follows.2 First, we are told that in order for
life to exist, very precise laws of nature, constants of nature, and initial conditions are
required,3 without which life would be impossible.4 Advocates then contend that design is the
best explanation or most likely hypothesis for these requirements being met as opposed to
alternatives. Collins, the most prominent contemporary advocate, canvasses one alternative,
brute contingency, where this answer takes two forms, either a “naturalistic single-universe
hypothesis … the existence of which is an unexplained, brute given”, or the “naturalistic
1
I wish to acknowledge a number of people who have aided me in producing this paper, both through reading
earlier drafts and in conversation. As such I wish to thank, in no particular order, Martin Smith, William Mander,
Ralph Walker, Alastair Wilson, Gregory Stacey, Martin Pickup, Anna Marmodoro, Matthew Tugby, Sophie Allen,
Calum Miller, Max Baker-Hytch, Yoaav Isaacs, and the reviewers of this journal.
2
Note from the outset that, following standard practice, I do not mean to imply any kind of deliberative action
on behalf of an agent by the language of ‘fine-tuning’.
3
For a detailed explication of what I mean by ‘precise’ see: (Hawthorne & Isaacs, 2018).
4
Collins (2009, 211-222) gives examples of laws, constants and initial conditions as evidence of fine-tuning,
whilst Swinburne (2004, 172) only uses laws and initial conditions, and Hawthorne and Isaacs (2018) only
constants.
1
multiverse hypothesis” (2009, 204).5 I would like to avoid brute contingency responses to the
argument and have nothing further to say about them here; rather the aim is to explicate and
assess an alternative reply based on necessity, the necessitarian response.6
For the purpose of introduction, the necessitarian response, put simply, says the laws and
constants of nature are metaphysically necessary, such that they do not vary across possible
worlds.7 Yet since the fine-tuning argument requires contingency, given necessitarianism, the
argument fails. Van Inwagen has recently suggested that this reply is “much more interesting
than the [brute contingency option]” (2015, 206), yet ultimately he finds it wholly
unpersuasive. (2017, 207) Oppy also gives it briefly as an option for blocking the argument if
one “supposes that every possible world ‘shares an initial part’ with the actual world” (2013a,
27; 2016, 33). Given that Oppy appears to hold this, that every possible world shares an initial
part (2013b, 47), we can take him to think necessitarianism persuasively causes problems for
the fine-tuning argument.8 Despite this and given the increasing interest of necessitarianism
within the metaphysics of science, the response has never been sufficiently explored and this
is something I seek to rectify here.
Before outlining the structure of the paper, I must first note that I will only deal with two
aspects of fine-tuning, laws and constants, therefore neglecting initial conditions. I do this for
three reasons: firstly, because Bird (2014, 285-289) has recently given a necessitarian account
of these conditions; secondly, in order to account for this data my proposal would require
extra elements that need defending which I am unable to do here9; and finally, since some
have questioned whether initial conditions should be thought of as distinct from laws (Sklar,
1984; 1990; Frisch, 2004). The response therefore only explicitly attempts to deal with the
data of fine-tuning related to the laws and constants of nature.
In order to lay out fully and assess the necessitarian response, the structure of the paper will
be as follows. I start by showing why fine-tuning requires contingency, and why necessity
might be thought to block the argument. Subsequently I formulate the response
necessitarians can give, suggesting that three requirements need to be met: firstly that laws
are metaphysically necessary, secondly that constants are metaphysically necessary, and
thirdly that the fundamental properties which determine the laws and constants are
necessary. I discuss each of these elements in turn, suggesting how one might argue for them,
5
Swinburne (2004, 153-191) does likewise, whilst Leslie (1989) gives necessitarianism an extremely brief
mention.
6
The necessitarian response could also come in a multi-verse variety, and this may cause distinct problems for
the argument not addressed here since I focus on a single-universe account.
7
They are therefore necessary in a de re rather than de dicto sense.
8
Oppy (2013a; 2013b) thinks a similar move can be made against certain cosmological arguments, see Leftow
(2017) for a reply; some of the comments made by Leftow would also be applicable to the necessitarian picture
examined in this paper.
9
Namely the necessity of the initial quantity and place of properties.
2
before ending the paper by assessing how the response fares when running the fine-tuning
argument in two ways, as an inference to the best explanation and as a Bayesian argument.
1. The Requirement of Contingency for Fine-Tuning
A major assumption behind fine-tuning arguments is that finely-tuned aspects of nature could
have been otherwise; that is the laws and constants of nature, at least those related to finetuning, are contingent.10 This assumption is one that typical respondents who advocate
design and brute contingency usually take for granted. Those who advocate the design
hypothesis presumably think the instantiated design of nature could have been otherwise,
and similarly those adopting a brute contingency position, be that of a single universe or
multiverse, allow for the possibility that a different brute contingent could have been
instantiated. The necessitarian, by contrast, denies this initial assumption, claiming it isn’t
possible that the laws and constants have been otherwise; they are necessary.11
Before spelling out why this blocks the other responses, it is important to understand the
types of necessity used throughout this paper. First is narrow logical necessity, where the
“truths of propositional logic and first order quantification theory” (Plantinga, 1974, 1) are
what is necessary in this sense. Next is broad logical necessity or metaphysical necessity,
which Fine (2005, 236) characterises as “the sense of necessity that obtains in virtue of the
identity of things”.12 Kripke provides some examples of this type of necessity when he claims
Hesperus is necessarily identical with Phosphorous (1980, 108-110), and Gold necessarily has
the atomic number 79 (1980, 123-125). It is thus because of what Hesperus is that it is
necessarily identical to Phosphorus, with the same being said for Gold and its atomic number
79. Metaphysical necessity then, concerns “being and its modes, whereas logic [and thereby
logical necessity], properly understood, does not concern being in general but rather, the
formal properties of and relations between propositions”. (Lowe, 1999, 10)13 Finally, there is
nomic or physical necessity, which holds in virtue of the laws of nature. However, unlike the
10
Perhaps a different type of argument to theism could be run without assuming this, that is where the laws
and constants are necessary. I suggest one below but note that it is far weaker than the standard fine-tuning
argument.
11
That they are necessary may not mean that there is no sense in which we can say the laws and constants are
fine-tuned. For instance, suppose we found out, perhaps due to computer modelling, that the range of laws and
constants that are life permitting is very small, and then also found out that the laws and constants that hold in
this world hold in every possible world. There is still a sense in which the life permitting range of laws and
constants is small, and therefore fine-tuned, even though it is impossible that any other laws or constants hold.
However, this paper in no way relies upon this point, and if one thinks the language of fine-tuning no longer
should be used when the laws and constants are necessary then one can re-word what I say at various points
without loss of content.
12
For more on the distinction between logical and metaphysical necessity see: Kripke (1980); Plantinga (1974,
1-9); Lowe (1999, 8-22); Leftow (2012, 33-38); Fine (2005).
13
However, despite what is said here, and the examples of metaphysical necessity given, as Gendler and
Hawthorne (2002, 4) write the notion “is standardly taken to be primitive.”
3
prior necessities this necessity is relativized from world to world, since it is assumed that
different possible worlds could have different laws. For the rest of the paper the necessity
that will most concern us is broadly logical/metaphysical necessity, and unless otherwise
stated this is what I will refer to.14
How then does necessity block the argument? The fine-tuning argument asks for either an
explanation or most likely hypothesis behind the fine-tuning data, where all the data is
assumed contingent, that is could have been otherwise. But if the fine-tuning is necessary
then it cannot vary across metaphysically possible worlds. The laws and constants would
never vary and hence aren’t contingent.15 The necessitarian therefore denies the contingency
claim inherent in the argument and replies that the laws and constants are metaphysically
necessary; nothing further is needed.16
I think many theists should think this response less terrible than many previously have, even
if they ultimately think it unsuccessful. The reason for this change of heart is that the response
mirrors many theistic answers concerning explanations of God’s existence. Paralleling the
necessitarian, who holds that the laws and constants are broadly logically/metaphysically
necessary, “most analytic philosophers hold that if God exists, He exists with broad logical
necessity.” (Leftow, 2010, 141) More importantly, theists who suppose God exists with this
type of necessity also typically claim that appealing to metaphysical necessity is sufficient for
ending explanatory chains, evidenced in responses to questions such as ‘what explains God’s
existence?’ For instance, Plantinga writes,
“perhaps a necessary being may be characterized as (a) a being such that some
statement referring to it can properly serve as a final answer in this sort of question
and answer series, an answer which puts an end to the series. … such a being must be
one about which the question "Why does it exist?" does not arise or cannot sensibly
be asked. A necessary being, therefore, may be further characterized as (b) a being
about which one cannot sensibly ask why it exists. When the theist, therefore, asserts
that God is the necessary being, we may construe his remark in the following way. He
14
Craig (2008, 161-164) thinks the necessity necessitarians will appeal to is physical necessity. Perhaps a
necessitarian could respond in this way, however I think targeting metaphysical necessity is the best option. The
reason for this is that since I take physical necessity to hold in virtue of the laws of nature, I cannot claim the
laws of nature themselves are necessary in this sense. Perhaps one could claim that the constants and initial
conditions are determined by the laws of nature and therefore hold with this type of necessity, but I do not opt
for this view here. The second reason I opt for metaphysical necessity is that it falls out of certain positions taken
in modal metaphysics.
15
An objection might immediately present itself, namely that I can conceive that the laws and constants are
different and therefore it is possible that they are different. This is perhaps the most important objection to the
view and will be discussed once the response is set out more fully.
16
Van Inwagen (2015, 208) seems to agree that this is sufficient for blocking the argument.
4
is pointing out that we cannot sensibly ask, "Why is it that God exists?"” (1967, 181182)
The necessitarian follows Plantinga in all he says, but substitutes laws and constants for God.
If the laws and constants are necessary then it is difficult to see any explanatory differences
between the two, and hence necessity, if plausible, undercuts the argument; or at least
theists who endorse the move made above by Plantinga should think so.
2. The Proposal
But you are likely thinking, this is all well and good, necessity might block the argument, but
the real question is whether it is plausible.17 It therefore seems time to start providing some
reasons for thinking that it is. Briefly the necessitarian proposal I explicate says, the laws of
nature are metaphysically necessary, as too are the constants, and that the instantiation of
the properties that determine these laws and constants is also necessary. This final
component is especially important since one could think both the laws and constants are
metaphysically necessary, and yet also that they could have been different.18 Before looking
at the elements of the proposal in detail, I should note that the view of laws and constants I
set out will require that the world is composed of dispositional properties,19 a view that has
received much attention in recent years (Bird, 2007; Marmodoro, 2010; Groff & Greco, 2013;
Jacobs, 2017).
Dispositions/powers/potencies/capacities are entities that have their causal role essentially
such that they cannot vary across possible worlds. For instance, take the dispositional
property being negatively charged. As a dispositional property the identity of this property is
defined in terms of its causal role, for instance repelling other negatively charged entities.
Given this, one could not have the dispositional property negative charge, and have it attract
other negatively charged entities. A property that did this would just be a different one, not
17
A reviewer suggests that merely establishing the possibility of necessitarianism is enough to cause problems
for fine-tuning arguments, since the burden of proof will be on the proponent of fine-tuning arguments to refute
necessitarianism. This may be correct, although the possibility to be established will need to be the metaphysical
rather than epistemic possibility. However, in the literature it is the lack of plausibility of the view that seems to
be the concern regarding necessitarianism, rather than its impossibility. As such, here I try to suggest why one
might think it is plausible, but if one wishes to follow the reviewers thought, then one may read the remainder
of the paper as my trying to merely show that necessitarianism is possible.
18
How one could think this I hope will become clearer as the paper proceeds, but put briefly, if a properties
identity determines what laws and constants are then it is metaphysically necessary that given the existence of
these properties there are these laws and constants. As such the laws and constants are metaphysically
necessary given the properties that exist, but it is a further question whether the existence of the properties
themselves are metaphysically necessary. This is why necessary instantiation is also required for the
necessitarian response I give.
19
Perhaps necessitarianism does not require this, but my version will.
5
the disposition negative charge. This contrasts the other popular conception of properties,
categoricalism, which rejects the link between a property’s causal role and its identity, instead
thinking a property’s nature is “self-contained, [and] distinct from the powers that they
bestow.” (Armstrong, 1997, 69) Thus, unlike dispositions, categorical properties have a causal
role that varies across possible worlds, and as such requires quidditism, where each property
has a primitive identity that enables it to have different causal roles across possible worlds
whilst retaining its identity. Given this, reusing our property of negative charge, a
categoricalist would claim that this property has a quiddity which provides it with a primitive
identity such that negative charge could take on radically different causal roles in other
possible worlds, for instance attracting other negatively charged entities, smelling of roses,
or tasting of chocolate. The necessitarian view I explicate will rely upon the assumption that
all worldly causal efficacy is in some way due to dispositions, and hence dispositions will play
a key role in the account of laws and constants.20 I don’t try to defend a realist view of
dispositions and their universal scope here, since this is a task that has been undertaken
elsewhere, and given this my reliance on dispositions should not be seen as an ad hoc
postulate.
2. 1 Necessary Laws of Nature
Turning to the necessitarian view, the dispositionalist account holds that laws are
metaphysically necessary.21 However, other accounts of the metaphysics of laws endow laws
with differing modal status. The easiest way of showing why dispositionalists think laws are
necessary is by contrasting them with full contingency accounts (Humean) and partial
contingency accounts (strong external governing laws).
The Humean empiricist position, following the traditional reading of Hume, holds that there
are no connections in nature and that laws merely describe the regularities observable in the
world. Nothing determines that something does X or Y, rather X or Y happens and laws simply
describe those regularities. As such, no necessity is involved in laws. Everything is contingent
and everything could have been otherwise. Thus, fine-tuning arguments presumably work on
Humeanism since it appears that different regularities could have occurred, some leading to
life-prohibiting worlds and others to life-permitting. Despite this, Humeans might shrug their
shoulders at fine-tuning data, saying ‘there is no explanation of the data.’ They can say this
because given empiricism we need not think there is an explanation as to why the laws are as
they are since thinking this is an import of rationalism and is therefore something many
empiricists won’t accept. Hence the fine-tuning argument only works on Humeanism if one
also has a little bit of rationalistic blood.22 Realists about dispositions have had much to say
20
Thus, one could hold a dualist, dual-aspect or monistic view concerning dispositional properties.
At least nearly all of those I know of who are realists about dispositions as fundamental properties do. I will
state what this claim entails shortly.
22
This is only an escape for Humeans, since the other positions are rationalistic enough.
21
6
about Humeanism recently and ultimately reject it since they think laws are more than mere
descriptions of regularities,23 instead thinking that laws act with some type of necessity
(Mumford, 2004; Ellis, 2001).
The second view of laws is associated with Dretske-Tooley-Armstrong (Dretske, 1977; Tooley,
1977; Armstrong, 1983) and the anti-reductionist positions of Carroll (1994) and Lange
(2000),24 what I call the strong-external-governing conception. Briefly put laws are necessary
connections within this world, either between universals or tropes, but this necessity does
not carry across possible worlds. One reason for adopting this type of necessity is due to a
thought experiment which in its simplest form asks us to imagine a world with all the same
properties but different laws. For instance, take ‘water/H2O’, either as a universal or trope,
and assume in this world it is nomically linked with the universal or trope ‘boils at 100°C’. The
idea behind the thought experiment is that it is merely a contingent fact that ‘water’ is linked
with ‘boils at 100°C’, since we can imagine that ‘water’ could have been linked with ‘boils at
112°C’ or ‘boils at 58°C’. Different possible worlds will have different boiling points of water,
not because the normal conditions are different, but because the nomic link is different. If we
can imagine something like this, the thought continues, then laws and properties are distinct.
As a result, the laws could have been different and the properties the same, the properties
different and the laws the same, or both could have been different.25
The thought experiment is supposed to motivate one into rejecting Humean contingency but
doesn’t force full-blown necessity. Rather it suggests a distinct type of necessity, what
Armstrong (2010, 41) calls “an intermediate necessity, indeterminate between Humean
contingency and necessity … ‘nomic necessity’”. Although notoriously difficult to work out
exactly what this kind of necessity is (Lewis, 1983, 366), this account of laws also allows the
fine-tuning argument to run without issue since the laws could have been different. For
instance, different possible worlds will have different boiling points for water, not because
the conditions are different, but because the nomic link is different. The defender of the finetuning argument to theism can then extrapolate this to instances of fine-tuning they are
interested in and the argument is off and running.
Dispositionalists also reject this view since they find categorical properties, which this position
seems to require, objectionable and therefore think the thought experiment given above
which motivates this position, does not describe a genuine possibility.26 Instead they hold that
each causal property has a dispositional essence, something the property is necessarily
23
Simpson (2017) argues against those who try to combine Humeanism and a realist view of dispositions.
Carroll and Lange think laws are metaphysically contingent in the way I describe, but they don’t explicate the
necessary connection since they are anti-reductionists.
25
For further elaboration on this thought experiment see: Tooley (1977); Carroll (1994, 77-85).
26
For further critical discussion see: Mumford (2004); Ellis (2001); Bird (2007).
24
7
directed towards, where this gives a property its identity.27 Thus, if one tried to rip the
directionality out of a disposition, the rupture would be so great that the property itself would
no longer exist. Its identity would have fundamentally changed, with a different property
coming to exist instead. Due to this, unlike the previous views, dispositionalists think that if
you had the same properties instantiated across possible worlds the laws would be identical.
Only with different properties do you get different laws.
Nonetheless, this shouldn’t concern the fine-tuning argument because even if laws are
metaphysically necessary given the properties in the world, the instantiation of those
dispositional properties is not, and this fact enables the argument to get going. Contingency
has found another opening, with Schmass possibly being instantiated rather than mass. A
further distinction therefore is needed between weak and strong necessitarianism. The weak
necessitarian thinks “Laws concern properties. Properties may or may not exist in different
possible worlds. … the law L(P) concerning property P is necessary, and that this requires only
that L(P) holds in all possible worlds where P exists.” (Bird, 2004, 257) By contrast strong
necessitarianism says “there is no difference between possible worlds as regards their laws;
nomologically, they are identical.” (Bird, 2004, 259) Since the dispositionalist position I have
explicated doesn’t decide between these positions, we must decide ourselves. In the section
concerning the necessity of instantiation I suggest how one might argue for strong
necessitarianism, as it is this which is required for the necessitarian response to fine-tuning.
2.2 Necessary Constants
Having seen why we could think that laws are metaphysically necessary, we must move onto
constants. However, before proceeding I should note that there is often a terminological
difference between physicists and philosophers here that can be confusing. In my reading in
philosophy of science one rarely reads about the constants of nature as distinct from laws,28
but this distinction often appears in discussions of fine-tuning and physics. Philosopher of
physics Wallace is informative in explaining how we should understand this difference
between the disciplines writing,
“for most philosophers of science, a law of nature is something like the inverse-square
law, including the gravitational constant. However, physicists usually regard the
constants as parameters that can be set within the laws, leading to the distinction
between constants and laws. But that doesn’t in itself commit to the constants having
any contingent status. I think it’s best – when thinking about current physics, at any
rate – to think of the constants as having the same nomic status as the laws.”29
27
Some think of this directedness as relational in terms of an essential relation, whilst others think of it as nonrelational. Either notion is acceptable for the necessitarian.
28
One notable exception is Collins (2005, 388-391).
29
David Wallace in personal correspondence.
8
If this is correct, then perhaps many of those philosophers of science who embrace
dispositionalism might also think the constants of nature possess the same type of necessity
as the laws, since constants are contained within laws. This would be a quick and easy way to
argue that the constants are metaphysically necessary, merely in virtue of the laws being
metaphysically necessary. However, it is not one I suspect all will agree with, for instance
Collins (2005, 388-389), and therefore I attempt to spell out the metaphysics as to why
dispositionalists might think constants are necessary, something yet to be done in the
literature.
When explaining why the laws are metaphysically necessary on dispositionalism, I relied upon
the essential directionality inherent in dispositions. In order to explain the constants, I rely
upon another aspect of dispositions I take to be essential, their intensity (Manley &
Wasserman, 2007; Vetter, 2015, ch.3).30 It is clear that different dispositions have different
intensities, for example different acids have different pH levels and different types of glass
shatter more or less easily. Further, we can give parallel reasons for intensity being an
essential aspect of dispositions as those we gave for directionality, particularly since “the
degree or intensity of a power [disposition] is clearly a causally relevant matter” (Mumford &
Anjum, 2011, 26). Intensity, then, plays a key role in determining a property’s identity, such
that if the intensity of a property changed it would be a different property. For instance, if the
pH level of a property changed it would no longer be the same specific property because it
would have a different dispositional essence.31 Thus, just as directionality is essential to
dispositional properties, so too is intensity, such that the same property cannot vary in its
directionality or intensity across possible worlds.
Given this, what are the constants of nature on a dispositionalist viewpoint?32 The
gravitational constant, for example, is the intensity of the relation between acceleration and
mass. The same determinate mass accelerates at the same rate every time it is instantiated,
but were the constant to change, this rate would be different. This relationship is fixed as a
matter of necessity for mass and acceleration. The result of this is that wherever mass and
acceleration are instantiated, we will have the same gravitational constant. That is, the
gravitational constant will not have any contingent value, but rather a metaphysically
necessary value given the dispositional natures of mass and acceleration. The only way for
30
Just as with directedness (note 27), how intensity is related to dispositions is disputed. If one thinks of it
externally, then since I later adopt holism this shouldn’t cause any problems, given necessary instantiation.
Alternatively, if one thinks intensity is intrinsic to dispositions, where this is how much effect a disposition has,
one need not adopt holism.
31
We might be able to say it is a similar property to be before since it might still have the pH level such that it is
still acidic, however different acids have different properties.
32
I owe the proceeding thought to Allen who comes close to explicitly endorsing this view elsewhere (2007,
113).
9
the constant to change would be if Schmass were instantiated, since then the ratios between
acceleration and Schmass would be different to those between acceleration and mass.
Constants, then, on this view are therefore nothing other than ratios of intensities between
dispositional properties.33
Assuming this way of linking a disposition’s intensity with the constants of nature, the
constants turn out to be metaphysically necessary. Nonetheless, just like the dispositionalist
position concerning laws of nature, the way to interpret the necessity of these constants
comes in two varieties, weak and strong necessitarianism.34 As before, strong
necessitarianism, and hence necessary instantiation is required, and it is to this we now turn.
2.3 Necessary Property Instantiation
Dispositionalism gives us at least weak necessitarianism, but strong necessitarianism is
required for a necessitarian response. That is, we need it to be the case that not only given
certain properties certain laws and constants necessarily obtain, but also that the properties
that determine the fundamental laws and constants are necessarily instantiated. As such,
strong necessitarianism seems to require necessary property instantiation. Therefore, I here
suggest how one might make the case for this aspect of the strong necessitarian position,
given that this is a view that is embraced and defended by a number of contemporary
thinkers.35
One argument some have made in favour of strong necessitarianism has been based on
adopting a Platonic conception of properties. Thus, Bird writes, “we should think of properties
as themselves being necessary existents, as would be appropriate on the Platonic (ante rem)
conception of universals ... If that is the case then … every possible property exists in every
possible world, and so every possible law holds in every possible world.” (2014, 285) What
should we think of this type of reason? Whilst it seems Platonism happily accounts for laws
and constants being the same in every possible world, it doesn’t entail that the same worldly
properties are instantiated in every possible world. The type of strong necessitarianism I
require needs the further claim that a certain subset of the world’s properties are necessarily
instantiated. Platonism therefore gets us only halfway, providing necessary properties but
33
Livanios (2014) critically discusses some problems for a dispositionalist view of constants but does not think
of them as I suggest here.
34
Dispositionalists may be asked further questions concerning the relationship between determinate and
determinable laws and constants. This is something I bracket here but note that dispositionalists have sought to
address this concern elsewhere (Tugby, manuscript).
35
For instance: Bird (2004; 2007, 50-59; 2014); Wilson (2013; manuscript); Bostock (2003); Oppy (2013b, 47);
Smith (2001). The following list of scholars might also hold to strong necessitarianism, but their work leaves their
adherence ambiguous: Leeds (2001; 2007); Edgington (2004); Vetter (2015).
10
not necessary instantiation, where reasons for adopting this missing element will be given
shortly.
Another argument others have proposed for strong necessitarianism makes use of current
debates over modal truthmakers. In recent years a new position has emerged which some
have termed ‘hardcore actualism’ (Contessa, 2010). This theory is actualist rather than
possibilist but distinguishes itself from ‘softcore actualism’ in that its modal truthmakers are
natural objects rather than abstracta, such as states of affairs or propositions. Because of this,
the view is often characterised as Aristotelian rather than Platonic, where the dispositionalist
version has it that the dispositions instantiated in this world provide the truthmakers of all
metaphysical possibilities.36 On this view, what makes it true that I could have been a
professional tennis player is that a whole complex array of dispositions in the actual world
could have manifested in a way that brought this about. However, due to the Aristotelian
nature of this view, those alien properties that are unable to be brought about by the
manifestation of worldly instantiated dispositions, what Vetter (2015, 269) calls ‘super-alien
properties’, are deemed impossible. Thus, if the actual world contains dispositions that if
manifested would produce a unicorn, then unicorns are possible. However, if the dispositions
of this world are unable to bring about such a thing, then being a unicorn is a super-alien
property and impossible. Some will no doubt be unhappy with such a consequence since they
wish to allow for such super-alien possibilities, and thereby a greater range of metaphysical
possibilities (Tugby, 2015). Yet why should we allow for them? As Borghini and Williams write,
“The objection being raised is that dispositionalism is somehow inadequate as an
account of metaphysical possibility because it does not treat S as possible [for instance
the thought experiment those advocating the strong-external-governing conception
of laws appeal too]. But why should it? Not every logically possible state of affairs will
turn out to be metaphysically possible. The space of actual dispositional properties
divides the set of all logically possible states of affairs into two groups: those that are
metaphysically possible and those that are not. … speaking of the possibilities we
‘need’ is very odd indeed. This implies that we know what is metaphysically possible,
and that it is the task of an ontologically motivated account like dispositionalism to
provide the truthmakers for that set of possibilities. This puts the cart before the
horse.” (2008, 37)
Additionally, many dispositionalists are unconcerned by the reduction of the modal
landscape, since they claim that in order to adequately account for super-alien properties and
be an actualist, one must employ abstracta to account for certain modal truths. Thus Vetter
writes, “it is not too hard to bite the bullet here, since the bullet is part of an attractive picture
of properties … [rather than] appeal to Platonist universals or propositions” (2015, 270). The
36
For further explication of this view see: Jacobs (2010); Borghini & Williams (2008); Vetter (2015); Pawl (2017).
11
super-alien properties complaint, therefore, does not seem to me to be an overwhelming
worry,37 although providing arguments to the effect that these properties are impossible
would certainly strengthen the hardcore-actualist cause.38
Nonetheless, just as Platonism was incomplete in providing a strong necessitarian account so
too is hardcore actualism. Platonism required the extra thesis of necessary instantiation,
because even though all properties exist across all possible worlds, the properties that are
instantiated could vary. Hardcore actualism needs something similar since presumably there
could have been fewer properties in the world,39 and this might cause a problem for a strong
necessitarian solution.40 Therefore we need some positive reasons for adopting a principle of
necessary instantiation for those fundamental properties that determine nature’s laws and
constants.
One reason is due to the following thought. Suppose you think there should be a reason that
these specific properties, and hence these particular laws and constants, are instantiated. It
seems that holding that they are necessary gives a satisfactory answer to this question. The
reason for this parallels the thought as to why necessity is an adequate response to the finetuning argument, namely because necessity is able to stop explanatory chains whilst positing
brute contingents is not. Thus, if the instantiation of these properties is necessary, then asking
why these properties exist is just like asking why God exists when He is metaphysically
necessary. If, however, one were to adopt weak necessitarianism, the reason that these
properties rather than others exist would be contingent, as if the reason were necessary it
would make everything else within this chain of reasoning necessary.41 But then we would be
left with a brute contingent fact as to why these laws hold and not others. A theistic weak
necessitarian might have an easy answer here if one grants that libertarian free acts can be
explanation stoppers, since they might hold that it is in virtue of God’s free decision that these
properties are instantiated rather than others.42 But non-theistic weak necessitarians, in
order to avoid strong necessitarianism, will have to remain content with brute contingent
instantiation.
Given that I’m trying to provide a response not based on brute contingency, necessary
instantiation looks preferable if we think there should be a reason why these properties
rather than others are instantiated. As Bird writes, strong necessitarianism provides “an
explanation of sorts. Being necessary, the fundamental laws could not have been otherwise
37
Dorr (2008, 47) makes a similar point for nominalists.
Armstrong (1989) in the past tried to make an argument like this.
39
Although Pawl (2017, 118-120) suggests this is questionable.
40
Unless the properties remaining provide a very high probability for permitting life. Yet this provides a slightly
different type of response to fine-tuning than the necessitarian one.
41
Parallel to a common objection to the principle of sufficient reason (van Inwagen, 1983, 202-204).
42
For a defence of this see: Pruss (2006, 126-159).
38
12
… we cannot ask for an explanation of the usual kind at all, for the comparative question, ‘why
do we have these laws as opposed to some other set?’, assumes what is false, that some other
set is possible.” (2007, 59) Many theists should be on board with everything said here, other
than the conclusion, since the motivation behind thinking properties are necessary is very
similar to the motivation behind postulating God as an explanation of everything. Theists
often complain about those who refuse to look for deeper explanations and instead posit
contingent primitive brute facts. As such they should welcome Bird’s insistence that we dig
towards deeper explanations. Further, since it is the principle of sufficient reason (PSR) that
is doing the work in this argument, with this being something theists regularly rely upon, they
should also look favourably upon this.
A second reason one might adopt necessary instantiation is based on another consideration
prized by some theists and many contemporary metaphysicians, namely simplicity or
parsimony.43 Strong necessitarianism is a simple view, particularly when considering the
ontology of laws and constants, as only dispositions are needed. Further, as I will discuss
below, if holism is true then it may be that only one dispositional property needs to be
necessary since it will necessarily bring with it all the other properties, and as such there need
only one necessary being, much like the monotheists necessary God.44 There is also no need
for differing types of necessity on strong necessitarianism because there is no longer any
physical or nomic necessity, and unlike weak necessitarianism no contingency related to the
instantiation of those properties related to laws and constants. Thus, if simplicity is seen as
virtuous then strong necessitarianism is on solid grounds.45
A third reason for adopting necessary instantiation is that some think it avoids the notorious
difficulties that plague modal epistemology.46 Thus Wilson writes, for the strong necessitarian
“modal epistemology is continuous with ordinary epistemology. … Far from presenting a
problem for modal [strong] necessitarianism, the unification of modal epistemology with
general scientific epistemology that it involves is one of the strongest points in its favour.
Modal [strong] necessitarians require no special epistemology for modal truths, and they
need not rely on the problematic conceivability-possibility link.” (2013, 665) Given this virtue,
For instance, Schaffer (2015, 644) writes “Do not multiply entities without necessity! Few principles are as
pervasive in contemporary metaphysics.” In theistic debates Swinburne (2004) is perhaps the greatest advocate
of simplicity. I suggest the reason ontological parsimony is prized so highly is so to avoid postulating many brutes.
44
Perhaps this goes someway to block Leftow’s (2017, 328-332) thought that theists still have the advantage
over the number and nature of fundamental entities when considering parsimony. For on both accounts there
is only one in number and one in nature, with everything else being derivative on both accounts, e.g. God’s
thoughts might be many and of a different nature to God but they are not fundamental. Nonetheless, it should
be acknowledged that whilst adding holism to the account isn’t a significant cost, it nonetheless has some cost.
45
Wilson (2013, 660-661) argues that strong necessitarianism also has the virtue of simplicity when addressing
the argument from sustaining counterfactuals, since the answer why the counterfactually nearest worlds tend
to have the same laws as the actual world is simply because all worlds have the same laws.
46
For elaboration of some of these difficulties see: van Inwagen (1998).
43
13
we have another reason for preferring the strong necessitarian position to its weak
necessitarian rival.
Holism also could provide one with grounds for thinking that if one fundamental property is
necessary then all fundamental properties will be due to the interdependence of properties.
For as Schaffer writes, “If everything is internallyessential related … Everything will be
interdependent in a very strong sense — if one thing were to fail to exist, then everything
would fail to exist.” (2010a, 349) The position I spell out here doesn’t require that everything
is interdependent, but only that those things involved within the causal realm are—those
things which account for the laws and constants of nature. I will have more to say about
holism later, but for now it should be noted that holism fits incredibly well with a
dispositionalist theory of things, and therefore this appeal should not be seen in any way as
ad hoc.47 Thus, for strong necessitarianism to work one might only need to think that one
property is necessarily instantiated, perhaps space-time (Dasgupta, 2016, 398), with holism
carrying all the other required properties with it.
Given all this, necessary instantiation, and therefore strong necessitarianism, has a number
of arguments in its favour, relying on considerations based on the principle of sufficient
reason, simplicity, modal epistemology, and holism. Maybe there are further reasons one
could give for this view, and this is something I think deserves further investigation.48
However, what should be noted here is that there are some sensible reasons for holding to
necessary instantiation and therefore strong necessitarianism. As such, strong
necessitarianism seems to be a plausible option concerning the modal status of the laws and
constants of nature.
2.4 The Proposal Summarised
Summarising, the proposal holds that the world is dispositional, at least in its causal aspects,
and as such the laws and constants of nature are metaphysically necessary. Further, since we
have seen that reasonable grounds can be given for adopting necessary instantiation we
arrive at strong necessitarianism. This leads us to an alternative response to the fine-tuning
argument. That is, despite its initial appearances the fine-tuning data couldn’t have been
otherwise because they are necessary, and as such the fine-tuning argument cannot get going
given its reliance on contingency.
47
There are many dispositionalists who are advocates of holism, for example see: Mumford (2004, 182-184);
Williams (2010, 94-101).
48
Wilson (manuscript) has argued for strong necessitarianism based on the many-worlds interpretation of
quantum mechanics and Vetter’s (2015, 276) view also seems to lead to strong necessitarianism.
14
3. Inference to Best Explanation Fine-Tuning Arguments
How then does this response fare when a fine-tuning argument is formulated in terms of
inference to the best explanation? Craig (2008, 161; 2003, 175) provides us with an example
of a skeleton structure of this type of argument, which he formulates as follows:49
1. The fine-tuning of the universe is due to either necessity, chance, or design.
2. It is not due to necessity or chance.
3. Therefore, it is due to design.
If the necessitarian response is successful then contra Craig, the best explanation will be
necessity rather than design. I have already given some reasons for thinking necessity a good
explanation, but no doubt others will give opposing reasons as to why design is better.
Perhaps one reason for thinking design better is due to objections that can be raised against
the necessity explanation. I now look at some of these.
One major objection to this view will be, ‘but couldn’t things have been otherwise?’ The first
thing to say is, yes things could have been otherwise given strong necessitarianism, although
perhaps not as otherwise as many would like. If we adopt a libertarian view of freedom that
endorses the principle of alternative possibilities, then it seems the world could have turned
out different from how it has.50 Sure, all the laws and constants would be the same, but the
choices made by free agents would produce a different world. Further, certain non-superalien properties could have manifested: those that could arise from the set of necessarily
instantiated properties.51 Yet despite this, strong necessitarians should have no hesitation in
admitting that possibilities are radically reduced on their view. However, it seems we can
conceive of possible worlds where the laws or constants of nature are different. What should
be said in response to this?
Note that Craig inserts ‘physical’ before necessity in his construction, I have removed this since I’m interested
in metaphysical necessity rather than physical.
50
Another way one might get this result would be through adopting quantum indeterminism concerning laws,
which Wilson (2013, 661) takes to be the best form of strong necessitarianism. There are broadly two
indeterminist pictures one might give. One is a type of multiverse, perhaps given a many worlds interpretation
of quantum mechanics, which is the type of strong necessitarianism Wilson thinks best (manuscript). The other
view thinks indeterminism does not give one a multiverse, but rather actuality just traces one of the many
indeterminist branches that is possible. This latter view however may not be sufficient to block the fine-tuning
argument, unless the argument is formed that the laws possibly give a life permitting universe rather than
actually do. This is because the indeterminism of the laws might result in the non-life permitting possibilities of
the laws, rather than the life permitting possibilities, being realised.
51
Perhaps one could get further permutations by employing Vetter’s (2015) degreed notion of potentialities and
formalism.
49
15
Firstly, as the discussion over the differing metaphysics of laws of nature showed, there is
radical diversity amongst philosophers over what can and can’t be conceived of, and hence
the range of possibilities there are. For instance, Humeans thought anything could follow
anything.52 Advocates of the strong external governing approach, by contrast, thought one
could have the same properties with different laws, whilst dispositionalists rejected both of
these thoughts since a property’s identity doesn’t vary across possible worlds. Ultimately all
these views cannot be correct, and thus the conclusion to be drawn is that we can’t always
conceive what we think we can.
Second, we can draw a distinction between types of conceivability as Chalmers has done, such
that some things are conceivable in some respects but not others. Thus, he distinguishes
between primary and secondary conceivability, so that it is possible to say “there is a sense
in which ‘Hesperus is not Phosphorus’ is conceivable, and a sense in which it is not. The first
of these senses corresponds to primary conceivability, the second to secondary
conceivability.” (2002, 157) The former of these two, primary conceivability, concerns
epistemic possibilities, and therefore we can say that it is primary conceivable that the laws
and constants have been different, just as it is conceivable that Water is not H2O.
Nonetheless, secondary conceivability is different because it is based on the idea that we hold
the character of the actual world fixed and “we consider and evaluate counterfactual
possibilities in the subjunctive mood.” (2002, 158) When conceiving in this way we come to
see as Kripke did, that “there is no coherently imaginable situation, considered as
counterfactual, that verifies ‘Hesperus is not Phosphorus’” (2002, 159), and as such this
possibility it is not secondarily conceivable. It is in this latter respect that dispositionalists
contend that the laws of nature and constants could not be conceivably different from what
they are. Thus, there is still a sense in which strong necessitarians can claim the laws and
constants are conceivably different, but another sense in which they are not.
Nevertheless, some still might contend that it is secondarily conceivable that the laws and
constants are different. Here it will need to be pointed out that we are often mistaken over
what we think is conceivable, with one reason for this reason being that isolating our
conceptions in order to assess them is extremely difficult. For instance, Hume’s idea that he
could imagine something coming into existence without a cause needs to be isolated from
other seemingly possible scenarios, such as being teleported or transported, and doing so
seems extremely difficult.53 Alternatively, it might be the converse that trips us up, in that we
fail to see things holistically enough so as to see where essential dependencies lie. Our
conceptual powers also seem in some way dependent upon our knowledge, and hence
contradictions once hidden become obvious. For example, perhaps we thought that we could
conceive of a mechanical wave, like a sound wave, being able to travel through a vacuum, but
52
53
Although this does not include logically contradictory anythings.
See Anscombe (1981a; 1981b) for further elaboration of this thought regrading Hume.
16
after receiving further information we come to see a hidden contradiction between
mechanical waves and vacuums. Maybe then we think we conceive of the fact that no waves
can travel through a vacuum, but upon further information we find out there is some type of
contradiction here too, since electromagnetic waves can.54 Conception then, is always open
to hidden contradictions coming to light at some further time. All of this is to say that our
powers of conception are by no means infallible, but actually highly fallible. Wilson makes this
point well, writing, “whether it is conceivable that like charges attract depends on us, and on
our conceptual apparatus. Whether the relation between properties and their powers is
necessary depends not at all on us or on our conceptual apparatus, but on properties and
powers themselves.” (2013, 664) Put simply, modality neither knows nor cares about our
conceptual powers, or our seemings.55
This can be seen forcefully in Heil’s remarks about the apparent contingency of the world. He
writes, “what is it to ‘appear contingent’? What does contingency look like? … [If] all the
worldly truths [were] absolutely necessary, everything would appear just as it does now. How
[then] could appearances provide any sort of indication of contingency?” (2013, 171) Thus,
how things actually are depends not at all on our conceptual apparatus and intuitions, since
conceivability is a function of how we think. Presumably if we had a different psychological
make up, or mental powers, we would conceive of things somewhat differently, and perhaps
end up thinking the world less contingent than many do today. Therefore, if we wanted to
find out what is truly possible, we would have to overcome the limits of our conceptual
faculties, somehow transcending them, endowing ourselves with a God-like power. Clearly
this isn’t possible. But then the question over whether things could have been otherwise, that
is whether there could have been different dispositions and hence different laws and
constants, turns out to be one over whether we ought to believe that there could have been,
the ‘ought’ here being the ‘ought’ of epistemological justification.56 The strong necessitarian
has given reasons for thinking we ought not think there could have been other laws and
constants, based on dispositional properties, the principle of sufficient reason, simplicity, and
modal epistemology. Those who propose design must do likewise, that is give epistemological
grounds for thinking we, with conceptual powers, are correct in thinking the laws and
constants of nature are contingent, rather than just assuming it.57 Given that many
acknowledge that conceivability is unreliable in assessing possibilities (Hill, 2016), this
objection doesn’t seem to me to be an easy knockout against strong necessitarianism.
54
Other more metaphysical examples could no doubt be given.
Gendler and Hawthorne (2002, 6) put it like this, “on the face of it, the idea that conceivability is a guide to
metaphysical possibility is extremely problematic.”
56
Thanks to Ralph Walker for this point.
57
Heil makes a similar point, “Why imagine that the idea that the laws could vary requires no defense? The fact,
if it is a fact, that the laws would have been different, had things been different at the Big Bang, does not imply
that the laws could have been anything at all.” (2013, 176)
55
17
Further, we can follow Bird and hypothesise a plausible reason as to why our powers of
conception are unreliable. He writes, the “link between imagination and possibility is
explained by the adaptive benefits of such a link … [and given this we] have no reason to
suppose that such a link should be reliable in delivering accurate judgements when applied
to esoteric cases such as the contingency or necessity of laws.” (2004, 274 & 273-275) This
suggestion seems parallel to the one Plantinga (2011, 307-350) makes in his evolutionary
argument against naturalism. Plantinga solves the problem by suggesting God has made us in
such a way that our faculties are aimed at truth, but for the many who don’t think God exists
or has done this, we might think that this provides us with a further, albeit weak reason, to
think we are not reliable adjudicators of possibility through conception.
Theists should also be sympathetic to this thought, that we are not reliable adjudicators of
possibility, since it is something they also emphasise. For instance, many theists think a
universe consisting of sentient beings who forever suffer horribly and pointlessly against their
wills is impossible. Yet as Leftow notes, this “makes perfect sense. So it seems to describe a
genuine possibility.” (2012, 120) But if God necessarily exists and is necessarily omnipotent,
omniscient, and perfectly good, then this is no genuine possibility, and the same will be true
for countless other prima facie possibilities given God’s necessary existence. Given this, many
theists should have little to complain about with the strong necessitarian’s insistence that
conceivability isn’t a reliable guide to possibility.
Another way to respond to this objection would be to adopt holism, and think everything is
interdependent (Schaffer, 2010a, 341-376; Williams, 2010). This allows one to reject the
thought that alternative modal possibilities can arise from free recombination (Armstrong,
1989). As Schaffer puts it, “A disconnected pluralistic heap should be amenable to free
recombination; failure of free recombination is thus the modal signature of an interconnected
… cosmos.” (2010a, 350) Since dispositions are usually thought of as interconnected and
holistic,58 holism might be seen as a natural consequence of dispositionalism, and therefore
this way of restricting the modal landscape shouldn’t be seen as costly to dispositionalists,
but rather exactly what they should expect (Ellis, 2001, 249 & 287; Schaffer, 2010a, 362-365).
However, one might be concerned that this holistic response leads to monism, the view that
there is only one substance. Suppose this implication is right; should it be considered
problematic? I think not. One reason is that Schaffer (2009; 2010b; 2010c) has provided some
plausible arguments to think Monism a viable option. But secondly, many theists shouldn’t
take monism, at least as Schaffer conceives of it, as problematic since they too make similar
moves. We can see this by looking at what both mean by substance, and the consequences
of these definitions. Schaffer defines a substance as “a fundamental and integrated thing.
[Where] a thing is fundamental if and only if it depends on nothing further, and a thing is
58
See note 47.
18
integrated if and only if it is not an arbitrary gerrymander but displays natural unity” (2013,
68). Descartes defines substance as, “a thing which exists in such a way as to depend on no
other thing for its existence.” (Principles I. 51 – Cottingham, Stoothoff, & Murdoch, 1988, 177)
Given these definitions Schaffer concludes that only the cosmos is a substance, whilst
Descartes deduces there to be “only one substance which can be understood to depend on
no other thing whatsoever, namely God.” (Principles I. 51 – Cottingham, Stoothoff, &
Murdoch, 1988, 177) Thus, when one reads that “exactly one substance—one fundamental
and integrated thing—exists … [where this is] compatible with the existence of any number
of dependent things” (Schaffer, 2013, 80), theists might be forgiven for thinking their position
is being described, when in fact it is the entailment of Schaffer’s monist conclusion. Hence,
both accounts give us only one substance, the cosmos or God.
Nonetheless, both attempt to overcome the implausibility of this conclusion, with Descartes
allowing for other substances by producing a watered-down notion of substance, writing, “In
the case of all other substances, we perceive that they can exist only with the help of God’s
concurrence.” (Principles I. 51 – Cottingham, Stoothoff, & Murdoch, 1988, 177) Schaffer
makes a similar move, suggesting that for ordinary objects we “replace substance with thing,
where a thing is a bearer rather than a property, surface rather than paint. A substance is a
thing that just happens to have some special features, namely fundamentality and
integration.” (2013, 81)59 As such, both theists and monists seem to hold a similar position
concerning substances, and give similar answers to its unwanted consequences. Given this,
some theists need different arguments against the monistic conclusion if they wish to attack
holism, as they too rely upon similar reasoning when claiming God is the one and only
fundamental entity. Monism, then, is perhaps not such an easy target.
One might object to strong necessitarianism on other grounds, namely that if the laws and
constants are metaphysically necessary then scientific methodology of observation and
experiment might seem unnecessary, with this thought to be an absurd consequence.
However, the necessitarian will dispute this consequence. The reason for this is that the
essences of dispositions which account for both the laws and constants are a posteriori
necessary, and as such empirical investigation is vital to uncovering their nature. Finding out
the exact nature of a dispositional property is extremely difficult, and so much experiment
and observation is required in order to do this. Further, it has been argued by some that
uncovering dispositional properties is what modern science is most suited to do (Cartwright
& Pemberton, 2013). As such, science is still required and metaphysical theorising from the
armchair is insufficient.60
Schaffer does this to get rid of the substance category altogether, but one needn’t follow him in that.
In addition to this most of those who advocate strong necessitarianism are philosophers who are very
informed of, and interested in, accounting for scientific data and its methodology.
59
60
19
Another objection against strong necessitarianism is based upon arguing that necessity is not
the type of thing that can be attached to property instantiation. One reason often given as to
why God can be necessary whilst the universe not, is that God can exist in worlds where
nothing physical exists, since He is incorporeal. By contrast, necessary instantiation, in my
case, requires that at least some natural dispositional properties are instantiated in every
world. Perhaps not many properties will be required, especially if there is a reduction of
current physics into something simpler. Nevertheless, it does seem that some of these
properties, if they are to explain the laws and constants, must be physical and yet exist
necessarily. Thus, if there are metaphysically possible worlds where there are no physical
properties, then the type of properties I require to be necessary cannot be.
Unless the strong necessitarian can come up with an alternative response to this problem,
they will simply have to bite the bullet, and hold that all possible worlds contain something
physical.61 Or put another way, there are no metaphysically possible non-physical worlds.
However, this objection might be less worrying if we make a distinction between atheistic
strong necessitarianism and theistic strong necessitarianism.62 On the atheistic view, a bullet
will be bitten, but on the theistic view it need not be. Before explaining why, I answer a worry
some might have, namely why I am invoking God whilst at the same time critiquing an
argument to His existence. One shouldn’t be concerned by this since one can object to an
argument to X even though they think X exists. Indeed, it might even be that because X exists
and exists in a certain way that they to object to the argument, with this being exactly the
case here. For the strong necessitarian theist, much like Leibniz and Spinoza, the world and
its structural features are necessary due to something in the nature of God. Perhaps this
something is due to His simplicity, or perfection?63 This move should make it clear why I am
not concerned by an ‘opportunistic theist’ availing the PSR for himself in order to argue for
God’s existence.64 The reason is simple: the paper is merely questioning whether the finetuning argument is a good one, not whether God exists.65 Given God, the theist can claim that
there is possibly a non-physical world, but that is only because there is a possible world where
61
Heil (2013, 174-176) notes that it is hard for us to imagine a world without space, yet space seems to have
physical attributes, thus perhaps this bullet isn’t as bad as it might first appear. Further, it might be that orthodox
first-order logic, which assumes that at least one thing exists, can also come to the aid of those holding this view.
62
However, combining theism with strong necessitarianism severely limits the modal powers attributable to
God, such as many of those Leftow (2012) ascribes to God in the most comprehensive study of God’s relation to
modality.
63
Perhaps the most influential work on this topic is: Rowe (2004).
64
Although non-theistic strong necessitarians might want to reject PSR-based reasoning since it might come to
a theists aid. I should note that only Bird, of the strong necessitarians in the literature, argues for the view based
on PSR, whilst all others think there are other independent grounds good enough to endorse the view.
65
Della Rocca (2010) has argued quite persuasively that the PSR leads one to a theistic necessitarianism.
20
God does not create.66 If God creates, however, then what He creates will necessarily be
exactly the same dispositional properties that determine the laws and constants of our world.
This response is also useful in answering another objection alleged against the strong
necessitarian response, namely that it might seem to provide an answer to the question
behind the Leibnizian cosmological argument, ‘why is there something rather than nothing?’
This was not my intention, yet the fact that certain properties are necessarily instantiated
might provide a reply to this argument as well. The theistic strong necessitarian can once
again claim that the necessity here is conditional on God’s creating, such that the fine-tuned
laws and constants couldn’t be different from what they are at all, but there could have been
a world just with God. Hence the Leibnizian question still remains. The other response one
could give, open to the atheistic or theistic view, is to distinguish between the possibility of
there being other possible worlds, and the possibility of there being no possible worlds. The
thought here is that while it is true for strong necessitarians that in every possible world
certain properties necessarily exist, there is still the possibility of nothing at all existing, where
this is the possibility of there being no possible worlds. If either of these are correct then the
Leibnizian question remains. Therefore, strong necessitarians would still have further work to
do in replying to Leibniz.
A final concern one might raise against the necessitarian view as the best explanation is due
to thinking that necessities should not be thought of as good explanation stoppers (Leftow,
2012, 51-54). The worry here is that these necessities seem brute, and some take brute
necessities to be bad (Dorr, 2004, 2008; Cameron, 2010). For instance, it is thought that asking
of something that is necessary, why it couldn’t have been otherwise, is not a terrible one
(Jubien, 2009, 74-75). If a theistic strong necessitarian account is correct then we can see that
there could be an answer as to why these laws and constants are necessary, namely because
they bring about the best world and God can only bring about the best. Yet on the atheistic
account there will be no further explanation as to why necessities hold, rather they are brute.
However, theists who embrace the design conclusion but also object to the necessitarian
response on these grounds may find themselves in a predicament. For Chalmers (2002, 189)
takes it that the necessity of God’s existence is a paradigm case of brute necessity, which
Plantinga’s (1967, 181-182) earlier comments would seem to bear out. Therefore, those
theists who follow Plantinga appear to endorse brute necessities, and insofar as they find
these sufficient explanation stoppers they too should find the strong necessitarian answer
sufficient also to stop questions of explanation. Otherwise they will be guilty of double
standards. Alternatively, some have sought to explain God’s necessity, so that it isn’t brute
(Leftow, 2012, 495-496).67 These explanations, such as God is necessarily a perfect being,
66
Although this rests on a controversial assumption that God might not create, and this too has been questioned
by some theists. For instance, see: Kretzmann (1988); O’Connor (2008, 111-129).
67
However, Leftow (2017, 328-329) does think there is a sense in which God is brute, namely that God is perfect.
Yet he thinks that God is less brute than naturalism.
21
unfortunately don’t seem applicable to necessary dispositions. As a result, an atheistic strong
necessitarian must either deny that brute necessities are worrisome,68 as many do, or find a
way to explain their necessity further. By contrast the theistic strong necessitarian can either
explain the necessity so that it is no longer brute or follow the atheistic response.
Nevertheless, since any form of strong necessitarianism is enough to block the argument this
worry can be adverted.69
As a result, I think the explanation of strong necessitarianism could plausibly be taken by some
to be the best explanation in inference to the best explanation versions of the fine-tuning
argument. I would favour the theistic version out of the two types, atheistic and theistic, but
could understand why someone might favour the atheistic version, particularly if they have
what they think are strong independent reasons for thinking God doesn’t exist. I therefore
suggest it isn’t cut and dried that design is the best explanation here and that necessity, if it
is a good explanation stopper, seems a viable contender, or at least one theists need to give
more attention too.
5. Bayesian Fine-Tuning Arguments
The other way the fine-tuning arguments are formulated is in terms of Bayes’s theorem
(Collins, 2009; Hawthorne and Isaacs, 2017; 2018), where this contrasts with inference to the
best explanation formulations.70 The argument run this way can be stated as thinking that a
life permitting universe, which requires fine-tuning, is more likely on theism rather than on
atheism. As such, the life permitting universe confirms theism over atheism. The question for
us is whether the necessitarian response is also effective in responding to this type of
argument.
So to answer this question, it is vital to see that epistemic probabilities are essential for
understanding the Bayesian approach, where these measure the degree of confidence we
rationally should have in a proposition. This has a worrisome effect on the necessitarian
response, since even if these specific laws and constants are metaphysically necessary there
is no argument for this claim that renders it highly probable or absolutely certain. This is
because metaphysical necessities do nothing to render epistemic probability claims high or
certain. This is made obvious when considering identity claims. For instance, Superman is
Clark Kent. Nonetheless it seems Lois Lane should assign as a low epistemic probability that
Superman is Clark Kent, even though it is metaphysically necessary that Superman is Clark
68
To investigate this in detail would take us too far afield into the relationship between explanation and
modality.
69
For other objections and replies to strong necessitarianism, see the papers where it is defended in note 35.
70
Hawthorne and Isaacs (2018) are critical of explanation versions of the argument compared with probabilistic
accounts.
22
Kent. Given this, the mere fact that the laws and constants are metaphysically necessary does
nothing to block this form of argument.
This is made clearer when we set out the argument more precisely. Hence take the argument
for theism based on fine-tuning, where T refers to theism and LPU a life permitting universe,
to be as follows:
𝑃(𝑇|𝐿𝑃𝑈) =
𝑃(𝑇) × 𝑃(𝐿𝑃𝑈|𝑇)
𝑃(𝐿𝑃𝑈)
Put informally this means that the probability of theism given a life permitting universe is
equal to the probability of theism multiplied by the probability of a life permitting universe
given theism, divided by the probability of a life permitting universe. Here we are
conditionalizing the probability of theism on the existence of a life permitting universe, since
we know there is a life permitting universe as we live in one.71 The place where the
necessitarian response would come in is in trying to raise the probability of a life permitting
universe, P(LPU), so to diminish the ratio between a life permitting universe given theism and
a life permitting universe in general, P(LPU|T)/P(LPU). If it were to do this, then it would
diminish the confirmation that a life permitting universe gives to theism. We can think of the
general probability of a life permitting universe, P(LPU), as asking what the probability of
getting this evidence is in general, where this is understood as a function of all the different
ways we could get this evidence. For our purposes we only need to plug in two mutually
exclusive, but exhaustive ways this evidence could come about, one where strong
necessitarianism holds and the other where it does not.72 Thus, we can understand the
probability of a life permitting universe, where N refers to strong necessitarianism, as follows:
𝑃(𝐿𝑃𝑈) = 𝑃(𝑁) × 𝑃(𝐿𝑃𝑈|𝑁) + 𝑃(~𝑁) × 𝑃(𝐿𝑃𝑈|~𝑁)
Put informally, the probability of a life permitting universe is equal to the probability of strong
necessitarianism multiplied by the probability of a life permitting universe given strong
necessitarianism, plus the probability of strong necessitarianism not holding multiplied by the
probability of a life permitting universe given strong necessitarianism not holding. What
needs to be the case to render the probability of a life permitting universe in general high, so
to diminish the force of the fine-tuning argument, is that something in this formula makes it
that the general epistemic probability of a life permitting universe is high. Since we are
considering the necessitarian response we are interested in the first half of the formula. Here
71
Since we should only ever conditionalize on the most epistemic certain data, rather than mere possibilities, it
is therefore highly likely that we should never conditionalise on strong necessitarianism as it will never be the
most epistemically probable thing available to us in fine-tuning arguments.
72
These two categories can be split into many further subtypes, but this further division does not concern us
here.
23
the necessitarian is likely to claim that P(LPU|N), the probability of a life permitting universe
given strong necessitarianism is very high, perhaps even 1. Nonetheless, the epistemic
probability of strong necessitarianism holding seems to be extraordinarily low. As such it does
nothing to boost the overall probability of a life permitting universe, LPU. For instance,
suppose the epistemic probability of strong necessitarianism was 0.000001, then given that
the probability of a life permitting universe on strong necessitarianism is 1, the overall
probability of this conjunct of the equation for the general probability of a life permitting
universe is 0.000001. We can see that necessitarian responses will fail similarly for other types
of data too, and so this is not restricted to fine-tuning arguments. For example, suppose you
come across some finger prints at a crime scene, you might assign a certain probability for
them being there in general. One reason they might be there is that the laws of nature make
it necessary that this finger print be here. As such the probability that the finger print is here
given these laws of nature is 1, but the epistemic probability that these laws of nature
necessarily entail this finger print is extraordinarily low. Given all this, we can see that
metaphysical necessity does nothing to block the Bayesian argument which relies upon
epistemic probability. Things therefore look grim for the necessitarian on this construal.
What then can the strong necessitarian say in response? One thing they might say is that once
we see the world is as he claims, then Bayesian reasoning is undercut by necessitarianism,
since the objective chance of the laws and constants being as they are is in fact 1. This may
well be epistemically surprising, but any surprise we feel should lapse. Responding to this,
one might think this a big cost to pay given how prevalent Bayesian reasoning is. However,
the main problem with this response is that it just doesn’t seem possible that we could know
with anything close to certainty that strong necessitarianism holds. As a result, the response
doesn’t even get going.
Another route the strong necessitarian might try is claiming that Bayesian reasoning is
problematic and so shouldn’t be adopted.73 Whilst some no doubt think this way, it is fair to
say that it is a minority view and as such will be thoroughly unconvincing for most. Finally,
perhaps the last hold-out for the strong necessitarian is if there are other devastating
criticisms particular to the Bayesian formulation of the fine-tuning argument that do not
plague the best explanation style argument.74 If there are then the Bayesian version will need
to be dropped for the best explanation formulation. The difficulty here is that the concerns
which might be brought to bear against the Bayesian version seem also to potentially
frustrate the inference to best explanation formulation as well. As such the strong
necessitarian response doesn’t seem to hold up well against Bayesian style fine-tuning
arguments. At the most, it would seem to provide some reason for increasing our credence’s
that the laws and constants are necessary. Yet it doesn’t increase these nearly enough for it
73
For some potential issues see: Easwaran (2011).
For instance: Plantinga (2011, 219-224); Manson (2000); McGrew, McGrew, & Vestrup (2003); McGrew, &
McGrew (2005).
74
24
to be problematic. We might therefore suggest that given strong necessitarianism is impotent
against the fine-tuning argument formulated in Bayesian terms we have another reason,
along with Hawthorne and Isaac’s criticisms, to prefer this style of argument over the
inference to the best explanation version.
To conclude this section, suppose we somehow came to know that the laws and constants of
the universe are as the strong necessitarian supposes. As a result the epistemic probability of
this would be 1, and as Collins writes “epistemic probabilities are only useful in conditions of
ignorance” (2005, 389) and hence applicable no more since we know the world to be as the
strong necessitarian claims. Still, we might be able to run an argument for theism based on
this by asking whether it is likelier on theism than on atheism that there are necessary life
permitting laws and constants. I suggest it would be likelier on theism than on atheism,
perhaps for some reasons mentioned above regarding God’s perfection, and hence strong
necessitarianism of laws and constants confirms theism over atheism.75 The argument will be
much weaker than the fine-tuning argument, but it is an argument to theism nonetheless.
6. Conclusion
The aim of this paper was to explicate and assess an alternative response to the fine-tuning
argument. The strong necessitarian’s response to the argument is simple – there couldn’t
have been any other laws or constants, since the laws and constants are metaphysically
necessary, and the fine-tuning argument requires that they are contingent. Yet the efficacy
of this response, as we have seen, depends upon the way the fine-tuning argument is
formulated. If given in terms of inference to the best explanation I claim the response can be
potent. Yet when given to a Bayesian formulation of the argument the response seems
impotent. As such I suggest those formulating fine-tuning arguments should do so in Bayesian
terms so as to avoid the difficulties of the necessitarian response.
75
Or in terms of inference to the best explanation: the best explanation of the necessity of the laws and
constants is God.
25
7. References
Sophie Allen. 2007 “What’s the point in Scientific Realism if we don’t know what’s really
there?” Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 82 (61):97-123.
G. E. M. Anscombe. 1981a. “’Whatever Has a Beginning of Existence Must Have a Cause’:
Hume’s Argument Exposed.”, In From Parmenides to Wittgenstein, edited by G. E. M.
Anscombe, 93-99. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
G. E. M. Anscombe. 1981b. “Times, Beginnings, and Causes.” In Metaphysics and the
Philosophy of Mind, edited by G. E. M. Anscombe, 148-162. Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press.
David M. Armstrong. 1983. What Is a Law of Nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
David M. Armstrong. 1989. A Combinatorial Theory of Possibility. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
David M. Armstrong. 1997. A World of States of Affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
David M. Armstrong. 2010. Sketch for a Systematic Metaphysics. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Robert Black. 2000. “Against Quidditism.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 78 (1):87-104.
Alexander Bird. 2004. “Strong Necessitarianism: The Nomological Identity of Possible
Worlds.” Ratio 17 (3):256-276.
Alexander Bird. 2007. Nature’s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Alexander Bird. 2014. “Time, Chance, and the Necessity of Everything.” In Chance and
Temporal Asymmetry, edited by Alastair Wilson, 280-294. New York: Oxford University Press.
Andrea Borghini and Neil E. Williams. 2008. “A Dispositional Theory of Possibility.” Dialectica
62 (1):21-41
Simon Bostock. 2003 “Are all possible laws actual laws?” Australasian Journal of Philosophy
81 (4):517-533.
Ross Cameron. 2010. “Necessity and Triviality.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88 (3):401415.
John W. Carroll. 1994. Laws of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
26
Nancy Cartwright and John Pemberton. 2013. “Aristotelian Powers: Without Them, What
Would Modern Science Do?” In Powers and Capacities in Philosophy, edited by Ruth Groff and
John Greco, 93-112. New York: Routledge.
David Chalmers. 2002. “Does Conceivability Entail Possibility?” In Conceivability and
Possibility, edited by Tamar S. Gendler and John Hawthorne, 145-200. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Robin Collins. 2005. “Fine-Tuning Arguments and the Problem of the Comparison Range.”
Philosophia Christi 7 (2):385-404.
Robin Collins. 2009. “The Teleological Argument.” In The Blackwell Companion to Natural
Theology, edited by William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland, 202-281. Oxford: Wiley Blackwell.
Gabriele Contessa. 2010. “Modal truthmakers and two varieties of actualism.” Synthese 174
(3):341-353.
John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch. 1988. Descartes: Selected
Philosophical Writings. New York: Cambridge University Press.
William Lane Craig. 2008. Reasonable Faith. 3rd ed. Illinois: Crossway Books.
William Lane Craig. 2003. “Design and the Anthropic Fine-Tuning of the Universe.” In God and
Design, edited by Neil A. Manson, 155-177. New York: Routledge.
Shamik Dasgupta. 2016. “Metaphysical Rationalism.” Noûs 50 (2):379-418.
Michael Della Rocca. 2010. “PSR.” Philosophers Imprint 10 (7):1-13.
Cian Dorr. 2004. “Non-symmetric Relations.” Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 1:155-192.
Cian Dorr. 2008 “There Are No Abstract Objects.” In Contemporary Debates in Metaphysics,
edited by Ted Sider, John Hawthorne and Dean Zimmerman, 32-63. Oxford: Blackwell.
Fred Dretske. 1977. “Laws of Nature.” Philosophy of Science 44 (2):248-268.
Kenny Easwaran. 2011. “Bayesianism II: Applications and Criticisms.” Philosophy Compass 6
(5):321-332.
Dorothy Edgington. 2004. “Two Kinds of Possibility.” Aristotelian Society Supplementary
Volume 78 (1):1-22.
Brian Ellis. 2001. Scientific Essentialism. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Kit Fine. 2005. “The Varieties of Necessity.” In Modality and Tense, edited by Kit Fine, 235260. New York: Oxford University Press.
27
Mathias Frisch. 2004. “Laws and Initial Conditions.” Philosophy of Science 71 (5):696-706.
Tamar S. Gendler and John Hawthorne. 2002. “Introduction: Conceivability and Possibility.”
In Conceivability and Possibility, edited by Tamar S. Gendler and John Hawthorne, 1-70. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Ruth Groff and John Greco. 2013. Powers and Capacities in Philosophy: The New
Aristotelianism. New York: Routledge.
John Hawthorne and Yoaav Isaacs. 2017. “Misapprehensions About the Fine-Tuning
Argument.” Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 81:133-155.
John Hawthorne and Yoaav Isaacs. 2018. “Fine-Tuning Fine-Tuning”. In Knowledge, Belief, and
God: New Insights into Religious Epistemology, edited by Matthew Benton, John Hawthorne
and Dani Rabinowitz, 136-168. New York: Oxford University Press.
John Heil. 2013. “Contingency.” In The Puzzle of Existence: Why is There Something Rather
Than Nothing?, edited by Tyron Goldschmidt, 167-181. New York: Routledge.
Christopher Hill. 2016. “Conceivability and Possibility.” In The Oxford Handbook of
Philosophical Methodology, edited by Herman Cappelen, Tamar. S. Gendler and John
Hawthorne, 326-347. New York: Oxford University Press.
Jonathan Jacobs. 2010. “A powers theory of modality: or, how I learned to stop worrying and
reject possible worlds.” Philosophical Studies 151 (2): 227-248.
Jonathan Jacobs. 2017. Causal Powers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Michael Jubien. 2009. Possibility. New York: Oxford University Press.
Norman Kretzmann. 1988 “A General Problem of Creation: Why Would God Create Anything
at All?” In Being and Goodness: The Concept of the Good in Metaphysics and Philosophical
Theology, edited by Scott MacDonald, 208-228. New York: Cornell University Press.
Saul Kripke. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.
Marc Lange. 2000. Natural Laws in Scientific Practice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stephen Leeds. 2001. “Possibility: Physical and Metaphysical.” In Physicalism and its
Discontents, edited by Carl Gillett and Barry M. Loewer, 172-193. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Stephen Leeds. 2007. “Physical and Metaphysical Necessity.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly
88 (4):458-485.
Brian Leftow. 2010. “Swinburne on divine necessity.” Religious Studies 46 (2):141-162.
28
Brian Leftow. 2012. God and Necessity. New York: Oxford University Press.
Brian Leftow. 2017. “A Naturalist Cosmological Argument.” Religious Studies 53 (3):321-338.
John Leslie. (1989) Universes. London: Routledge.
Vassilios Livanios. 2014. “The “Constant” Threat to the Dispositional Essentialist Conception
of Laws.” Metaphysica 15 (1):129-155.
E. J. Lowe. 1999. The Possibility of Metaphysics. New York: Oxford University Press.
David Manley and Ryan Wasserman. 2007. “A Gradable Approach to Dispositions.” The
Philosophical Quarterly 57 (226):68-75.
David Lewis. 1983. “New Work for a Theory of Universals.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy
61 (4):343-377.
Neil A. Manson. 2000. “There is no Adequate Definition of ‘Fine-tuned for Life’.” Inquiry 43
(3):341-352.
Anna Marmodoro. 2010. The Metaphysics of Powers: Their Grounding and their
Manifestations. New York: Routledge.
Timothy McGrew, Lydia McGrew and Eric Vestrup. 2003. “Probabilities and the fine-tuning
argument: a skeptical view.” In God and Design, edited by Neil A. Manson, 200-208. New York:
Routledge.
Timothy McGrew and Lydia McGrew. 2005. “On the Rational Reconstruction of the FineTuning Argument.” Philosophia Christi 7 (2):425-443.
Stephen Mumford. 2004. Laws in Nature. Oxford: Routledge.
Stephen Mumford and Rani L. Anjum. 2011. Getting Causes from Powers. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Timothy O’Connor. 2008. Theism and Ultimate Explanation. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
Graham Oppy. 2013a. The Best Argument Against God. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Graham Oppy. 2013b. “Ultimate Naturalistic Causal Explanations.” In The Puzzle of Existence:
Why is There Something Rather Than Nothing?, edited by Tyron Goldschmidt, 46-63. New
York: Routledge.
Graham Oppy. 2016. “Conflict Model.” In Four Views on Christianity and Philosophy, edited
by Paul. M. Gould and Richard B. Davies, 21-47. Michigan: Zondervan.
29
Timothy Pawl. 2017. “Nine Problems (and Even More Solutions) for Powers Accounts of
Possibility.” In Causal Powers, edited by Jonathan Jacobs, 105-123. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Alvin Plantinga. 1967. God and Other Minds. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Alvin Plantinga. 1974. The Nature of Necessity. New York: Oxford University Press.
Alvin Plantinga. 2011. Where the Conflict Really Lies: Science, Religion, & Naturalism. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Alexander Pruss. 2006. The Principle of Sufficient Reason: A Reassessment. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
William L. Rowe. 2004. Can God Be Free? New York: Oxford University Press.
Jonathan Schaffer. 2009. “Spacetime the One Substance.” Philosophical Studies 145 (1):131148.
Jonathan Schaffer. 2010a. “The Internal Relatedness of All Things.” Mind 119 (474):341-376.
Jonathan Schaffer. 2010b. “Monism: The Priority of the Whole.” Philosophical Review 119
(1):31-76.
Jonathan Schaffer. 2010c. “The Least Discerning and Most Promiscuous Truthmaker.”
Philosophical Quarterly 60 (239):307-324.
Jonathan Schaffer. 2013 “The Action of the Whole.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 87
(1):67-87.
Jonathan Schaffer. 2015. “What Not to Multiply Without Necessity.” Australasian Journal of
Philosophy 93 (4):644-664.
William M. R. Simpson. 2017. “Half-Baked Humeanism.” In Neo-Aristotelian Perspectives on
Contemporary Science, edited by William. M. R. Simpson, Robert C. Koons and Nicholas J. Teh,
123-146. New York: Routledge.
Lawrence Sklar. 1984. “Comments on Malament’s “time Travel” in the Gödel Universe.” PSA:
Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1984 (2):106110.
Lawrence Sklar. 1990. “How free are Initial Conditions?” PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial
Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990 (2):551-564.
Quentin Smith. 2001. “The Metaphysical Necessity of Natural Laws.” Philosophica 67 (1):3155.
30
Richard Swinburne. 2004. The Existence of God. 2nd ed. New York: Oxford University Press.
Michael Tooley. 1977. “The Nature of Laws.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (4):667-698.
Matthew Tugby. 2015. “The Alien Paradox.” Analysis 75 (1):28-37.
Matthew Tugby. manuscript. “Determinable Laws”.
Peter van Inwagen. 1983. An Essay on Free Will. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Peter van Inwagen. 1998. “Modal Epistemology.” Philosophical Studies 92 (1):67-84.
Peter van Inwagen. 2015. Metaphysics. 4th ed. Colorado: Westview Press.
Barbara Vetter. 2015. Potentiality: From Dispositions to Modality. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Neil E. Williams. 2010. “Puzzling Powers: The Problem of Fit.” In The Metaphysics of Powers,
edited by Anna Marmodoro, 84-105. New York: Routledge.
Alastair Wilson. 2013. “Schaffer on laws of nature.” Philosophical Studies 164 (3):653-667.
Alastair Wilson. Manuscript. The Nature of Contingency: Quantum Mechanics as Modal
Realism.
31