Genocide and Social Time1
Bradley Campbell
Assistant professor at California State University
De acordo com Donald Black, todo conlito resulta de
movimentos do tempo social – alterações na diversidade, na estratiicação, ou no grau de intimidade. É o
caso para os conlitos genocidas, que envolvem transformações em termos de diversidade e estratiicação.
Genocídios resultam de ampliações na diversidade,
como no caso do contato intercultural, e reduções na
estratiicação, como quando membros de um grupo
étnico subordinado buscam elevar seu status. Mas
o genocídio é ele próprio um movimento no tempo
social, uma redução da diversidade e um aumento na
estratiicação, e que provoca ainda mais conlito. A teoria aqui apresentada explica os conlitos que levam ao
genocídio, bem como aqueles que dele resultam.
Palavras-chave: genocídio, moralidade, sociologia pura,
tempo social, violência
According to Donald Black, all conflicts result from
movements of social time – changes in diversity,
stratification, or intimacy. This is true of genocidal
conflicts, which involve changes in diversity and
stratification. Genocide results from increases in
diversity, such as through intercultural contact,
and decreases in stratification, such as when
members of a subordinate ethnic group seek
to increase their status. But genocide is also a
movement of social time, a reduction of diversity
and an increase in stratification, and it causes
further conflict. The theory presented here
explains the conflicts that lead to genocide as
well as those that result from it.
Keywords: genocide, morality, pure sociology, social
time, violence
Introduction
Recebido em: 19/12/2012
Aprovado em: 15/04/2013
I
n 1915 Turkey, Turkish gendarmes play the so-called “game
of swords,” which involves tossing Armenian women from
horses and impaling them on swords sticking up from the
ground (BALAKIAN, 2003, p. 315). In 1942, the men of German Police Battalion 101 kill 1,500 Jews from Jozefow, Poland.
Oten their bullets strike the targets in such a way that “blood,
bone splinters, and brains” spray everywhere (BROWNING,
1998, p. 64). he men are “quite literally saturated in the blood
of victims shot at point-blank range” (BROWNING, 1998, p.
162). In 1994 Rwanda, Hutus kill their Tutsi victims with lowtech weapons such as machetes and clubs studded with nails.
hey chop of arms, legs, and breasts. hey throw children
down wells (DIAMOND, 2005, p. 316). hey impale people
like kebabs (HATZFELD, 2005, p. 81). hey cut the Achilles
tendons of those they cannot kill right away to keep them from
running (ALVAREZ, 2001, p. 109; TAYLOR, 2002, p. 164).
1 An earlier version of this
article was presented at
the annual meeting of the
American Society of Criminology, Chicago, Illinois,
November 16, 2012. I thank
Donald Black and Jason
Manning for comments on
earlier drafts.
DILEMAS: Revista de Estudos de Conlito e Controle Social - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
465
These are glimpses of genocide – a form of ethnically based mass killing (CAMPBELL, 2011). Genocide
scholars sometimes focus on “desk killers,” “bureaucratization,” and the like, but scenes like these remind us of
the reality of so much face-to-face, enthusiastic killing.
These behaviors shock and disturb us, and we may refer
to genocide as “extraordinary human evil” (WALLER,
2002, pp. 9-22), a “miracle of evil” (OPDYKE and ARMSTRONG, 1999, p. 118), an “icon of evil” (BERGER,
2004, pp. 145, 157), “more than wickedness (…) more
than barbarity” (quoted in HATZFELD, 2005, pp. 27,
50), the “most heinous” variety of violence (PINKER,
2011, p. 320), or the “work of Homo sapiens at its worst”
(DAVIS, 2005, p. 35). Condemnations of genocide are
not explanations, though, and if we are to explain genocide, we must not confuse our own moral judgments
with those of the killers. The truth is that the killers often see themselves as righteous and their targets as evil.
Recognize this and genocide immediately becomes easier to understand. Though we see the targets of genocide
as victims and find the violence against them shocking,
the killers see them as offenders, wicked people who deserve their punishment – apostates, heathens, invaders,
rebels, traitors, parasites, murderers, or thieves.
In sociological terms, genocide is not just deviant behavior, a behavior that some people condemn; it is also social control, a way of handling
deviant behavior. It arises out of conflicts – clashes
of right and wrong. In previous work, I have offered
a theory of genocide as social control(CAMPBELL,
2009; 2010; 2011). But this was limited in that, as a
theory of social control, it explained only the handling of ethnic conflicts, not the conflicts themselves. Here I focus on genocidal conflicts – the
conflicts that give rise to genocide, and also those
arising from genocide. As we shall see, the same
theory can help us better understand why genocides occur and why people react to them as they
do. The theory is sociologist Donald Black’s (2011)
new theory of conflict, which views all conflict as
the result of movements of social time.
466
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
Bradley Campbell
Social space and social time
Social time is a new concept in Black’s pure sociology, a
theoretical strategy that previously explained various kinds of
behaviors only with their location and direction in social space.
Black introduced pure sociology – and the idea of social space
– in he Behavior of Law (1976), which predicted the extent to
which law, or “governmental social control,” would be used in
response to conlicts. For example, within a society, conlicts
across greater distances in social space – such as conlicts between strangers – attract more law than closer conlicts – such
as conlicts between intimates (BLACK, 1976, pp. 40-48). hus,
the killing of a stranger, to give one example, is punished more
severely than the killing of an intimate (COONEY, 2009, pp.
156-167). Conlicts at higher elevations in social space – such
as conlicts between two high-status persons – attract more law
than conlicts at lower elevations – such as conlicts between
two low-status persons (BLACK, 1976, pp. 16-21). When husbands kill their wives, then, the killing is treated more severely
the higher the couple’s status (COONEY, 2009, pp. 36-37).
Conlicts with a downward direction in social space – such as
when someone has a grievance against a subordinate – attract
more law than upward conlicts – such as when someone has
a grievance against a superior (BLACK, 1976, pp. 21-29). In
many slave societies, for example, masters could kill their slaves
without penalty, while slaves who killed their masters were tortured and executed (COONEY, 2009, pp. 39-42).
Subsequent to he Behavior of Law, Black and others not only expanded and applied the theory of law (e.g.,
BAUMGARTNER, 1992; BLACK, 1989; COONEY, 1994;
2009), they also applied pure sociology to the explanation of
social control generally (BLACK, 1998; HORWITZ, 1990)
and to speciic forms of social control – such as collective
violence (SENECHAL DE LA ROCHE, 1996), domestic violence (BAUMGARTNER, 1993), suicide (MANNING, 2012;
forthcoming), drug testing (BORG and ARNOLD, 1997;
BORG 2000), employee thet (TUCKER, 1989), criticism
(HOFFMANN, 2006), and apology (COONEY and PHILLIPS, 2013)2. Using the same theoretical strategy, we can examine any form of social control. Every conlict has a position
in social space, and this explains how it is how it is handled.
2 Pure sociologists have mostly studied social control and
conflict, and that is the focus
here, but the strategy may
be applied to any form of human behavior, and it has in
fact been applied to subjects
such as art (BLACK, 1998, pp.
168-169), ideas (BLACK, 2000;
PHILLIPS and LAPUCK, forthcoming), research (JACQUES
and WRIGHT, 2008), welfare
(MICHALSKI, 2003), and predation (CAMPBELL, forthcoming;
COONEY, 1997a; 2006: 58-60;
COONEY and PHILLIPS, 2002).
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
467
Bradley Campbell
his is the strategy I have used in my work on genocide.
Genocide, I have argued, is a direct function of social distance and inequality. It is more likely when the antagonists
are lacking in intimacy, interdependence, cultural similarity, and other forms of closeness, and when the aggressors
have more authority, military power, and other forms of status than the targets. his theory enables us to predict when
conlicts are most likely to be handled with genocide, who
is most likely to participate, and whom the participants will
target (CAMPBELL, 2009). It also explains the occurrence
of predatory behaviors alongside genocide (CAMPBELL,
forthcoming), the diferences between cases of genocide
(CAMPBELL, 2011) and the puzzling phenomenon of contradictory behavior, where the same individuals act as killers
and rescuers (CAMPBELL, 2010). But as noted above, what
it does not do is to explain the conlicts themselves – why
the aggressors have grievances against the targets to begin
with. Nor does it take into account the seriousness of the
conlict – the nature of the grievances. It explains the handling of conlicts only with their position in social space.
But why are some conlicts more serious than others?
And why do they occur in the irst place? In regard to genocide, why would anyone have grievances against Turkish
Armenians, European Jews, Rwandan Tutsis, or any of the
other targets? Answering these questions requires a theory
that explains what people deine as wrong and whom they
deine as wrongdoers – a theory of conlict rather than just
a theory of social control. Black’s new theory of conlict answers such questions, and it does so, as noted above, with
the concept of social time.
What is social time? It is simply the dynamic dimension of social life. Social life is unstable. No position in
social space is ixed. Cultural distance, which refers to diversity, or cultural diferences, increases and decreases as
people accept and reject new ideas, new forms of music, or
new ways of dressing. Relational distance, which refers to
a lack of intimacy, increases and decreases as relationships
end and new ones begin. Vertical distance, which refers
to inequality, or stratiication, increases and decreases as
people gain and lose status. In other words, social space
luctuates – it changes. And just as change in the physi468
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
Bradley Campbell
cal world may be identiied with time, so too in the social
world: Social change is social time. Each luctuation of social space, then, is what Black calls a “movement of social
time”, and it is these movements of social time, he says, that
cause all conlict (2011, pp. 4-5).
Movements of social time cause conlict, and the faster
and greater the movements, the more conlict they cause.
All deviant behaviors, for example, are movements of social
time. his is why they cause conlict, why they are deviant.
So rape causes conlict – people condemn it, criminalize
it, and punish it – because it is a drastic reduction of relational distance, a movement of relational time. Likewise,
heresy causes conlict because it is a movement of cultural
time, and thet causes conlict because it is a movement of
vertical time. he same is true of cross-dressing, blasphemy,
intolerance, insanity, bad manners, drunkenness, homicide,
trespassing, promiscuity, adultery, lying, voyeurism, public nudity, and arrogance: All are movements of social time
(BLACK, 2011, pp. 3-9).
Not all movements of social time are deviant behaviors,
though. People sometimes praise those who form new relationships or achieve new successes. And many illnesses,
injuries, and deaths may have no human cause. But such
movements of social time may cause conlict even when
they are not themselves deined as deviant. hey may intensify or cause conlicts about other things, as when former
friends or lovers begin inding fault with one another as they
grow more distant. Or they may lead to false accusations of
wrongdoing. In many societies, for example, someone who
is downwardly mobile, such as a wealthy person who suddenly becomes poor due to illness, may falsely accuse someone of witchcrat, while someone who is upwardly mobile,
such as a poor person who suddenly becomes very wealthy,
may be the target of false accusations (BLACK, 2011, pp.
10-11, 15-16, 61-63, 83-84). Not all conlicts are as they
seem, then, but all conlicts have the same kinds of causes:
increases or decreases in diversity (in Black’s terminology,
“overdiversity” or “underdiversity”), increases or decreases
in intimacy (“overintimacy” or “underintimacy”), or increases or decreases in stratiication (“overstratiication” or
“understratiication”) (Idem, pp. 5-6).
Bradley Campbell
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
469
The causes of genocide
he fundamental cause of genocide is overdiversity.
Whenever two previously separated ethnic groups come
into contact, conlict results. And wherever two ethnic
groups live alongside one another, conlict is present. he
latter situation may not seem to involve an increase in cultural diversity, and at the societal level, it may not. But in
any multicultural society, people are constantly encountering those who are diferent, increasing the diversity in their
lives. Diversity is thus an unstable property of social life, and
as Black puts it, “who says diversity says conlict” (2011, p.
102). his applies to all types of diversity – including political, religious, and ethnic diversity. All lead to cultural clashes, even if only mild ones. Cultural clashes have a tendency
to intensify, though. In most cases, if I ofend you, our conlict may remain between the two of us. But if my political
beliefs ofend you, so do the beliefs of all those who share
them – Democrats if I am a Democrat, Republicans if I am
a Republican. he same is true of religion: A conlict with
me over religion is also a conlict with my co-religionists.
In cultural conlicts, then, the stakes are high. All cultural
conlicts are prone to collectivization. his is all the more
true of ethnic conlicts, since ethnic groups, whatever the
reality, are normally thought of as extended kinship groups,
and ethnic identity is relatively unchangeable. One thing
this means is that those who are closest to us – our mothers
and fathers, husbands and wives, sons and daughters – usually share our ethnicity. In any ethnic conlict, all who are
closest to me, those I care about the most, are on my side. I
am more likely to join in their grievances and ight in their
battles. And since I cannot alter my ethnicity, I cannot easily
switch sides, or come to share your view. Ethnicity is thus an
especially dangerous cultural distinction.
An increase in ethnic diversity alone may lead to genocide – or similar behavior – such as when certain tribal
groups kill all outsiders they encounter (BLACK, 2011, p.
103). Usually, however, something else must happen: An inferior group rises (or threatens to rise) or a superior group
falls (or is in danger of falling). hese social changes are
understratiication, reductions in stratiication. Recall that
470
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
Bradley Campbell
genocide normally involves superior ethnic groups attacking inferior ones. But prior to the genocide, the stratiication
between these groups decreases, and this causes the conlict
that leads to genocide. Note that even though this involves
a change in inequality rather than culture, all conlicts that
occur across cultural boundaries – such as across ethnic
boundaries – are in danger of becoming cultural conlicts.
When murders or thets cross ethnic boundaries, they are
no longer just murders or thets of individuals, but ofenses
by one group against another. Even if the original conlict
has nothing to do with ethnicity, interethnic conlict has the
potential to become collective, with each side mobilizing its
own ethnic supporters.3
Scenarios of genocide
Colonialism is one situation that may involve large
and sudden increases in diversity. In the 1850s, for example, white ranchers began moving into the Round Valley of
Northern California, the home of the Yuki Indians. Ethnic conlict began immediately, as the white settlers made
use of the valley without much regard to the prior inhabitants. hey depleted wild game and other natural resources,
fenced of areas of land used by the Indians, and kidnapped
and enslaved Indian women and children, sometimes for
their own use and sometimes to sell to others. he Indians
then began killing stock belonging to the ranchers. And it
was this ofense – the Indians’ thet – that led to genocide.
At irst the genocide consisted of unconnected genocidal
expeditions. Whenever cows, horses, or hogs were missing or found dead, the aggrieved ranchers would gather
together a group of men to go out and kill nearby Indians
– perhaps 50 at a time. Later, the settlers successfully petitioned the state government to fund a more permanent
militia group – the Eel River Rangers – to deal regularly with such ofenses (MILLER, 1979; CARRANCO and
BEARD, 1981). As Black (2011, p. 87) notes, thet is always
a reduction of wealth, and when, as in these cases, someone of lower status steals from someone of higher status,
thet decreases stratiication, if only slightly.
3 Although all cultural conlict is collective in logic,
and although all interethnic conlict may potentially
collectivize, other features
of conlicts help determine
whether collectivization actually occurs (SENECHAL DE
LA ROCHE, 2001; see also
CAMPBELL, 2011, pp. 593595).
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
471
Bradley Campbell
he Round Valley Genocide was similar to the killings
of other California Indians and to the killings of Aborigines
in Australia (KROEBER, 1961; REYNOLDS, 2006). In these
cases the natives sometimes killed white settlers in addition
to stealing from them, and in other colonial genocides, even
greater threats to stratiication might occur. In South-West
Africa, for instance, an organized rebellion against German
imperialism led to genocide of the Hereros in the early 1900s
(DRECHSLER, 1980; MADLEY, 2004). What we see in all
these cases is a massive increase in diversity, when two previously separated ethnic groups come into contact, followed by
a decrease in stratiication – sometimes very small, but sometimes much larger – when the natives ofend the settlers.
Many other cases of genocidal conlict, though, do not
begin with sudden increases in diversity. In Rwanda, for example, Tutsis and Hutus had lived alongside one another for
centuries prior to the 1994 genocide. he degree of overdiversity was low, the result of luctuations of cultural diversity in
daily life rather than the drastic increases that arise from previously separated groups coming into contact. he degree of
understratiication, on the other hand, was much greater. he
minority Tutsis had been politically subordinate to Hutus for
decades when, in 1990, the Rwandan Patriotic Front (RPF) –
consisting mostly of Tutsi exiles from Rwanda – launched an
invasion from Uganda. Prior to this, Rwanda’s ruling party
had faced an internal political challenge, and the president,
Juvénal Habyarimana, had allowed rival political parties to
form. Ater the invasion, he began peace talks with the RPF
and eventually agreed to what were known as the Arusha Accords, a power sharing agreement very favorable to the RPF.
he Arusha Accords would have excluded a major anti-Tutsi
political party from the government, and they would have
mandated that 50% of Rwanda’s army oicers and 40% of its
troops come from the RPF. he president’s party, though, and
later President Habyarimana himself, opposed the agreement
and sought to block its implementation. Others, too, began
to see the RPF invasion and the Arusha Accords as a threat
to the gains Hutus had made in the 1959 revolution, when
the previously subordinate but majority Hutu population had
gained political power. Each of the opposition parties thus
split into a “Hutu Power” faction, which aligned with the re472
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
Bradley Campbell
gime to oppose the Arusha accords, and a “moderate” faction,
which continued to support the power-sharing agreement.
he anti-Arusha Hutu Power forces gained further support
with the October 21, 1993 assassination of the Hutu president of neighboring Burundi by Tutsi army oicers and the
anti-Hutu massacres that followed (FUJII, 2009; MAMDANI,
2001; PRUNIER, 1995).
he invasion by Tutsi exiles, the Arusha agreement, and
the assassination of Burundi’s president were all movements
of social time, and they led to a resurgence of ethnic grievances in Rwanda. Extremists within the government and their
allies portrayed the civil war in ethnic terms. Tutsis had oppressed Hutus in the past and now sought to do so again. All
Tutsis were enemies, whether they were members of the Burundian military, members of the Ugandan based RPF, or ordinary Rwandan citizens. But another fateful event occurred
on April 6, 1994, when President Habyarimana’s plane was
shot down. he Hutu Power forces immediately blamed the
Tutsis – the RPF and their “accomplices.” he extremist forces
began eliminating opposition leaders and formed an interim
government composed only of the ruling party and the Hutu
Power factions of the opposition parties. he RPF resumed its
invasion, and the Hutu Power forces in Rwanda began killing
Tutsi civilians – eventually about 800,000 of them.
In the Rwandan case, as with the colonial genocides,
overdiversity and understratiication together caused the
genocide. Where the cultural changes are greatest, as in the
colonial genocides, the immediate provocation to genocide
might be small threats to ethnic stratiication, such as thets
or isolated killings. But in a context of longstanding diversity, as in the Rwandan case, it takes something major, such
as a rebellion or invasion. So in Rwanda, the RPF invasion
and the events surrounding it threatened to end – or even to
reverse – the political dominance of Hutus over Tutsis.
Many other cases are similar. For example, Bosnia’s secession from Yugoslavia in 1992 would have given Bosnia’s Muslim plurality (44%) political power over less numerous Serbs
and Croats. Serbs were the dominant ethnic group in the Yugoslav Federation, and the Serbs in Bosnia, who made up 31%
of the population, refused to become subordinate in an independent, Muslim-led Bosnia. Aided by the federal army and
Bradley Campbell
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
473
4 One Tutsi survivor, for
example, tells of the false
accusations against her father, who was said to have
aided the RPF. After learning
of these accusations, the
Hutu man who was hiding
this woman in his home told
her, “Your father was a very
bad Tutsi.” When he said the
authorities had found 600
guns in her father’s home
and a death list of Hutu names, she became furious: “If
my father had so many guns,
why didn’t he pass them out
to the thousands of Tutsis
who came to us asking for
protection (…) why didn’t
he use the guns to protect
his wife and daughter from
killers and rapists?” (ILIBAGIZA, 2007, pp. 95-97).
outside paramilitaries, Bosnian Serbs began taking control of
parts of Bosnia, and by the end of 1992 the newly declared Republika Srbska covered 70% of what had been Bosnian territory (CIGAR, 1995, p. 5; JUDAH, 1997, p. 239; MALCOLM,
1994, pp. 224-238). Because Muslims, Serbs, and Croats lived
alongside one another throughout Bosnia, in order to turn this
part of Bosnia into a new Serb state, the Serbs engaged in what
would come to be called “ethnic cleansing,” which consisted of
mass killings, imprisonment, gang rapes of women, deportations, and the destruction of mosques and other cultural artifacts (MANN, 2005, pp. 356-357). Genocide was thus only one
component of the larger campaign of violence against Croats
and Muslims, their property, and their symbols. In all, 200,000
to 250,000 Bosnian Muslims were killed – more than 10% of
their population (GUTMAN, 1993, p. xxxi).
Combinations of overdiversity and understratiication
cause genocide, then. In many cases, as in the previous examples, these movements of social time are largely identical
to the aggressors’ grievances against their targets. he grievances accurately describe the targets’ behavior – the cause of
the genocide. But the aggressors might also make false accusations. Indeed, most genocidal conlicts involve a mixture of
true and false accusations. In Rwanda, for example, the RPF
had certainly invaded Rwanda, but they probably did not assassinate President Habyarimana (REUTERS,2012). Hutus
also falsely accused many Tutsis of conspiring with or aiding the rebels4. In other genocides, the major accusations are
completely false, perhaps delusional. his was the case during
the Holocaust, where, according to political scientist Daniel
Jonah Goldhagen, the Nazis’ “proneness to wild, ‘magical
thinking’ (…) and their incapacity for ‘reality testing’ generally distinguishes them from the perpetrators of other mass
slaughters” (1996, p. 412). One false accusation was of Jewish
treachery – a “stab in the back” – that led to Germany’s defeat in World War I (STAUB, 1989, p. 100; FRIEDLANDER,
1997, pp. 73-74). But the idea of Jews as organized conspirators went much further. For example, the Nazis believed that
all their apparent enemies were simply Jewish puppets. he
Nazis’ form of socialism – National Socialism – difered from
both capitalism and communism, and they believed that international Jewry was the real source behind both of these
474
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
Bradley Campbell
competing economic systems. his belief was later conirmed,
the Nazis believed, by the alliance of capitalist and communist
nations – the US, Britain, and the Soviet Union – against Germany (SNYDER, 2010, p. 217). More broadly, the Nazis believed the Jews sought to dominate all of humanity, and that
they were thus behind all sorts of other evils. Nazi propagandist Joseph Goebbels, speaking of the Jews in 1937, put it like
this:“Look, there is the world’s enemy, the destroyer of civilizations, the parasite among the peoples, the son of Chaos, the
incarnation of evil, the ferment of decomposition, the demon
who brings about the degeneration of mankind” (quoted in
COHN, 1969, p. 204).
False accusations such as these result from the same
kinds of movements of social time that lead to other genocidal conlicts. For example, warfare is an extreme movement of social time. As we have seen, when wars are interethnic, they may lead to conlict involving all those who
share the antagonists’ ethnicity. Wars may also lead to conlict with others. When a state loses a war, especially when
this leads to a loss of territory, genocide becomes more
likely. he Ottoman Empire had lost almost half of its territory during the two centuries prior to the 1915 genocide
of Armenians in Turkey, and prior to the Holocaust, defeat
in World War I had resulted in major territorial losses for
Germany and the Austro-Hungarian Empire (MIDLARSKY, 2005, pp. 135-162). Neither the Armenians nor the
Jews were responsible, but in both cases these losses – a
kind of downward mobility – not only exacerbated the already existing conlict with the losers’ ethnic inferiors,
but also led to new, and false, accusations against them.
In the case of the Holocaust, World War II also threatened
the Nazis’ status, especially when the war with the Soviet
Union began to prove much more diicult than expected.
Hitler blamed the Jews for this war, and it was only ater
the invasion of the Soviet Union that the large-scale mass
killing of Jews began5. A state that loses a war, loses territory, or ights a war experiences a rapid loss or threat of loss
to its status. hese social upheavals cause so much conlict
that they may result in the creation of new enemies, as socially distant and inferior ethnic groups, regardless of their
actual behavior, are accused of treason and other ofenses.
5 Other movements of social time, such as Germany’s
economic depression in the
1920s and 1930s, as well as
the Jews’ upward mobility
during the early 20th century, no doubt also contributed to the false accusations
that led to the Holocaust
(BLACK, 2011, pp. 68-70).
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
475
Bradley Campbell
Genocide as deviant behavior
6 It is certainly much more
common to think of genocide as a deviant behavior
than to think of it as a form
of social control – a response
to the deviant behavior of
others. After all, most genocide scholars identify with the
targets of genocide and condemn their killers. But social
science is “value-free” (BERGER, 1963, pp. 5-6; BLACK,
forthcoming; SEUBERT, 1991;
WEBER, 1958).It cannot tell
us whether the targets’ or the
killers’ or our own values are
correct, and in any case, such
information would be sociologically useless – a distraction from the task of explanation. Understanding this
diference – the diference
between factual statements
and value judgments – is especially important when studying deviant behavior and
social control, where we are
otherwise in danger of completely misunderstanding
our subject. In this case, if
we were to mistake our condemnation of genocide for a
sociological classiication, we
might be tempted to think
of genocide and the social
control of genocide as behaviors completely unlike one
another. But both are acts of
social control, reactions to
deviant behavior. Genocide
involves moral judgments
against the targets, and the
condemnation and punishment of genocide involve
moral judgments against the
aggressors. They can be understood similarly.
Genocide responds to movements of social time – usually increases in diversity and decreases in stratiication. But
genocide is itself a movement of social time. It decreases diversity and increases stratiication, so it, too, causes conlict. he
targets of genocide condemn their killers, and when they are
able, they may punish them. For example, in 1921 Soghomon
Tehlirian, an Armenian, assassinated former Turkish Interior
Minister Talaat Pasha, one of the architects of the Armenian
genocide. Likewise, in 1960 Israeli operatives captured Adolf
Eichmann in Argentina and took him to Israel, where he was
tried, found guilty, and hanged for his role in the Holocaust.
Outsiders, too, may involve themselves in genocidal conlicts
and attempt to punish or prevent genocide. Or they may simply condemn it. So even though genocide is social control, a
response to deviant behavior by the targets, it is also a deviant
behavior – oten extreme deviance, or evil – and its perpetrators may be subject to social control by others.
It may seem obvious that genocide is deviant6. But the
deviant nature of genocide is a variable, not a constant. he
targets condemn the genocides against them, but the aggressors might see their own actions as praiseworthy. And though
some outsiders to the conlicts might condemn genocides
or even try to prevent them, others might not care. Apathy
was especially common in the distant past, when genocide
was hardly deviant at all. “he shocking truth,” psychologist
Steven Pinker notes, “is that until recently most people didn’t
think there was anything particularly wrong with genocide –
as long as it didn’t happen to them” (2011, p. 334; cf. CHALK
and JONASSOHN 1990, p. 8; EVANS, 2008, p. 13; PAYNE,
2004, pp. 44-51). Since few people in the predmodern world
viewed genocide as wrong – much less evil – people boasted of the genocides they committed, and they might falsely
claim to have committed other genocides, exaggerating their
brutality in order to frighten their enemies or impress their
subjects (CHALK and JONASSOHN, 1990, pp. 59-60; FREEMAN, 1995, pp. 214-220). Even religious leaders might praise
genocide and condemn restraint, as when Moses, in the Old
Testament, chastises the Israelite army for allowing defeated
Midianite women and children to live (NUMBERS 31: 14-
476
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
Bradley Campbell
17). But in modern societies, genocide has become more deviant. It is roundly condemned, and instead of boasting, those
who commit genocide – and those who defend them – now
engage in what is called genocide denial (FREEMAN,1991, p.
195; PAYNE, 2004, p. 57; PINKER, 2011, p. 335; WIKIPEDIA, 2012a).
he move from boasting to denial occurred as genocide increasingly became more deviant. Even the coining of the word
genocide is an example of this process. Ater Winston Churchill
described the Nazis’ destruction of nations as a “crime without a
name,” jurist Raphael Lemkin determined to name it and to get
it recognized as a crime under international law (POWER, 2002,
pp. 29-45). He succeeded, and in 1948 the United Nations passed
the Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime
of Genocide. his has not always led to the willingness of outsiders to stop it. For fear that it might require military intervention,
governments are oten reluctant even to label an ongoing mass
killing a genocide (MILES, 2006, pp. 255-256; POWER, 2002).
But intervention has not been completely absent, and it appears to be increasing. he International Criminal Tribunal for
the Former Yugoslavia (ICTY) and the International Criminal
Tribunal for Rwanda (ICTR), established by the United Nations
ater the Rwandan and Bosnian genocides, have convicted more
than 100 persons of genocide and other international crimes
(HOLA, SMEULERS, BIJLEVELD, 2011, p. 412). And governments and intergovernmental organizations sometimes use
military force to try to prevent or halt genocides and other mass
killings. Examples include the 1994 United Nations Aid Mission
for Rwanda (Unamir), a small operation that saved thousands of
Tutsis, though it was unable to stop the genocide; the 1995 and
1999 Nato air strikes against Bosnia and Yugoslavia, respectively;
and the 2011 air strikes against Libya by the United States and
several other nations. he UN Security Council resolution authorizing the intervention in Libya’s civil war referred to a 2005
UN document that identiied an emerging norm known as the
“responsibility to protect.” Governments, according to the document, have a responsibility to protect their civilian populations
from genocide, war crimes, ethnic cleansing, and crimes against
humanity, and when they cannot or will not do so, this becomes
the international community’s responsibility (EVANS, 2008, pp.
48-49; WIKIPEDIA, 2012b).
Bradley Campbell
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
477
We have moved from a world where most people cared little
about the genocides of others – perhaps not even disapproving of
them – to a world where genocide is a crime, where international
courts convict and imprison government oicials for killing their
own citizens, where nations intervene in civil wars to prevent the
killing of civilians, where humanitarian groups document and
publicize what they consider human rights violations all over
the world, and where academics from numerous disciplines ill
bookshelves with discussions of the evil of genocide and ways to
prevent it. Why this change? Why is genocide – once ignored or
even praised – now thought of as an incomprehensible evil? Why
is genocide so deviant? Why does it attract so much social control?
Genocide has become more deviant, irst of all, because it
is a reduction of diversity – underdiversity – and underdiversity
has become more deviant in the modern world. Underdiversity
is more serious in diverse settings, while overdiversity is more
serious in homogenous settings (BLACK, 2011, p. 139)7. With
modern communication and transportation technologies have
comedrastic increases in the diversity in people’s lives – increases, for example, in their knowledge of and participation in other
cultures and their interaction with cultural outsiders (COWEN,
2002, pp. 79-80). International organizations like the United Nations or multicultural societies like the US are especially diverse,
and those associated with them are especially likely to condemn
political censorship, religious persecution, and other assaults on
diversity. But genocide is also more deviant now than in the premodern world because it involves a greater movement of social
time. If the Israelites slaughtered the Midianites, the efects were
mostly localized, but in an interconnected world with dispersed
populations, the efects of genocide might be felt all over the
world. Hitler’s slaughter of European Jews, for example, altered the
lives of Jews everywhere – and the lives of those connected to them
relationally or culturally. Lemkin himself pointed to the possible
efects of genocide on the culture of people other than the targets:
7 Likewise, underintimacy is
more serious between intimates, overintimacy between
strangers, understratiication
between unequals, and overstratiication between equals
(BLACK, 2011, p. 139).
478
We can best understand this when we realize how impoverished our culture
would be if the peoples doomed by Germany, such as the Jews, had not been
permitted to create the Bible, or to give birth to an Einstein, a Spinoza; if the
Poles had not had the opportunity to give to the world a Copernicus, a Chopin, a Curie; the Czechs, a Huss, a Dvorak; the Greeks, a Plato and a Socrates;
the Russians, a Tolstoy and a Shostakovich (Quoted in POWER, 2002, p. 53).
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
Bradley Campbell
The future of genocide
As genocide becomes more deviant, intervention to prevent or punish genocide becomes more likely. And intervention
makes genocide less likely for two reasons. First, it may directly
prevent or stop the killing, and indeed, though not all interventions are successful, those that involve direct challenges to the aggressors or support for the targets do tend to reduce the severity
of genocide (KRAIN, 2005)8. Second, remember that genocide
occurs in a context of inequality, where the aggressors are superior to the targets – normally in size, political authority, and military strength. But as intervention becomes expected, conlicts are
equalized. Outside opposition to the aggressors decreases their
status, and support for the targets increases theirs.
For the same reason, genocide declines with the proliferation of liberal democracies. Many genocides have been led by
states, but these are more likely to be totalitarian and authoritarian states, where political elites have so much power relative to the populations they rule, rather than democratic states,
where political power is more difuse (RUMMEL, 1994; 1995;
see also COONEY, 1997b). Already, more than half of the
world’s population lives in a democracy (up from just over 12%
in 1900), and the democratic form of government continues to
spread (MODELSKI and PERRY, 2002, p. 365)9.
Remember also that genocide is more likely in a context of
ethnic diversity – where there is cultural distance between ethnic
groups – and that increasing diversity is one of the common causes
of genocide. But increasingly, communication and transportation
technologies allow for social closeness despite physical distance.
While this increases the diversity in people’s lives by bringing diverse peoples into contact with one another, it reduces the distances between them. hey become culturally closer, more intimate,
and more interdependent (BLACK, 2004, p. 24; COWEN, 2002, p.
79). Ultimately, globalization destroys the social distances conducive to genocide. here is no genocide in a global village10.
Already we see a decline in the kinds of situations that lead
to serious ethnic conlicts, and fewer of these conlicts means less
genocide. Many of the large movements of social time that commonly lead to genocidal conlicts – colonial wars, interstate wars,
civil wars, and revolutions – are much less common. Colonial wars
have ended, and since the end of the Cold War, interstate wars
Bradley Campbell
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
8 But the possibility of intervention may increase the
likelihood of genocide in
some cases. Aggrieved members of subjugated ethnic
groups may rebel against
their governments – despite
the likelihood of retaliatory
genocide and despite the impossibility of military success
– in the expectation that outside intervention in response
to the genocide will enable
them to achieve their goals
(KUPERMAN, 2005; 2009).
Conceivably, then, increasing
intervention, if it leads to
more rebellions that provoke
genocide, could lead to more
genocide overall.This does
not appear to be happening,
though, and in the long term,
if intervention becomes more
certain and more efective,
genocide is likely to decrease.
9 In some cases, though, increasing democratization may
lead to genocide by giving
political power to otherwise disadvantaged ethnic majorities
who have grievances against
economically successful ethnic minorities (CHUA, 2003,
pp. 163-175; see also MANN,
2005). To some extent, this is
what happened in Rwanda.
But overall, democracies are
less genocidal than other governments, and we can expect
less genocide in the long term.
10 Media theorist Marshall
McLuhan (1964) coined the
term “global village” to emphasize that modern technology had made instantaneous
communication – something
originally possible only face-to-face, at the village level –
possible on a global scale. Black (2011, pp. 148-151) points
out that as the relationships
between people throughout
the world come to resemble
those of villagers in their closeness, they also resemble
them morally. People become
more concerned about what
happens to one another, and
they behave more altruistically
(see also PINKER 2011, p. 292).
479
have “become few in number, mostly brief, and relatively low in
battle deaths” (PINKER, 2011, p. 302). he number of civil wars
peaked in the 1990s, but has declined since then. he decline in
the number of deaths caused by civil wars is even greater (Idem,
pp. 303-305). Revolutions have likewise become less frequent, and
when they occur, less violent (PAYNE, 2004, pp. 100-115).
he causes of genocide and the conditions associated
with it are declining, and the people of the world have become
more hostile to it. But is genocide really any scarcer? All the
attention given to genocide recently may leave the impression
that it is not, but the evidence suggests otherwise. Since the
end of World War II and the mass killings associated with it,
the world has not again seen such a high level of genocide.
he killings in Bosnia, Rwanda, and Darfur were severe, but
they were “spikes in a trend that is unmistakably downward.
(…) he irst decade of the new millennium is the most genocide-free of the past 50 years” (PINKER, 2011, p. 340).
Ending genocide, of course, is the goal of many genocide
scholars, whose work, as sociologist homas Cushman puts it,
is “characterized by a strong ideological belief that genocide is
preventable and that knowledge about genocide will help bring
about prevention” (2003, p. 524). Much of the work on prevention is valuable, and it makes sense for those working to prevent
genocide to consult it. he larger story about genocide, however, is
not that it occurs because of a lack of knowledge about its causes.
Information about genocide cannot prevent genocide if no one
wishes to prevent it – if people wish instead to exterminate their
ethnic enemies or to stay out of others’ conlicts. Rather, genocide
is caused by particular kinds of social changes occurring in particular social contexts. When the social conditions conducive to
genocide were strongest, the conditions conducive to genocide
prevention were weakest. Better knowledge about genocide earlier
on would not have done much to prevent it. Conversely, perfect
knowledge about genocide is not required now for its prevention.
Recent social trends have led to the decline of genocide and to an
increase in eforts to stop it when it occurs. his is likely to continue, regardless of how much our theories of genocide advance.
And the theory I have presented explains why. Perhaps some of
the trends identiied here are only temporary, but should they continue into the far future, the pure sociology of genocide makes this
prediction: Genocide is destined for annihilation.
480
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
Bradley Campbell
References
ALVAREZ, Alex. (2001), Governments, Citizens, and Genocide: A Comparative and Interdisciplinary Approach.
Bloomington, Indiana University Press.
BALAKIAN, Peter. (2003), he Burning Tigris: he Armenian Genocide and America’s Response. New York,
Harper Collins.
BAUMGARTNER, Mary P. (1992), “he Myth of Discretion”.
In: HAWKINS, Keith (ed). he Uses of Discretion. Oxford, Clarendon Press, pp. 129-162.
________. (1993), “Violent Networks: he Origins and
Management of Domestic Conlict”. In: FELSON, Richard B. [and] TEDESCHI, James T. (eds). Aggression and
Violence: Social Interactionist Perspectives. Washington, American Psychological Association, pp. 209-231.
BERGER, Peter L. (1963), Invitation to Sociology: A Humanistic Perspective. New York, Anchor.
________. (2004), Questions of Faith: A Skeptical Airmation of Christianity. Malden, Blackwell.
BLACK, Donald. (1976), he Behavior of Law. San Diego,
Academic Press.
________. (1989), Sociological Justice. New York, Oxford
University Press.
________. (1998), he Social Structure of Right and Wrong.
San Diego, Academic Press.
________. (2000), “Dreams of Pure Sociology”. Sociological
heory, Vol. 18, no 3, pp. 343-367.
________. (2004), “he Geometry of Terrorism”. Sociological heory, Vol. 22, no 1, pp. 14-25.
________. (2011), Moral Time. New York, Oxford University Press.
Bradley Campbell
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
481
________. (Forthcoming), “On the Almost Inconceivable
Misunderstandings Concerning the Subject of Valuefree Social Science”. British Journal of Sociology.
BORG, Marian J. (2000), “Drug Testing in Organizations:
Applying Horwitz’s heory of the Efectiveness of Social Control”. Deviant Behavior, Vol. 21, no 2, pp. 123154.
________ [and] ARNOLD, William P. (1997), “Social Monitoring as Social Control: he Case of Drug Testing in a
Medical Workplace”. Sociological Forum, Vol. 12, no 3,
pp. 441-460.
BROWNING, Christopher R. (1998), Ordinary Men: Reserve
Police Battalion 101 and the Final Solution in Poland.
New York, Harper Perennial.
CAMPBELL, Bradley. (2009), “Genocide as Social Control”.
Sociological heory, Vol. 27, no 2, pp. 150-172.
________. (2010), “Contradictory Behavior During Genocides”. Sociological Forum, Vol. 25, no 2, pp. 296-314.
________. (2011), “Genocide as a Matter of Degree”. British
Journal of Sociology, Vol. 62, no 4, pp. 586-612.
________. (Forthcoming), “Genocide as Predation”. International Journal of Law, Crime and Justice.
CARRANCO, Lynwood [and] BEARD, Estle. (1981), Genocide and Vendetta: he Round Valley Wars of Northern
California. Norman, University of Oklahoma Press.
CHALK, Frank [and] JONASSOHN, Kurt (1990), he History
and Sociology of Genocide: Analyses and Case studies.
New Haven, Yale University Press.
CHUA, Amy. (2003), World on Fire: How Exporting Free
Market Democracy Breeds Ethnic Hatred and Global
Instability. New York, Doubleday.
CIGAR, Norman. (1995), Genocide in Bosnia. College Station, Texas A&M University Press.
482
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
Bradley Campbell
COHN, Norman. (1969), Warrant for Genocide: he Myth of
the Jewish World-Conspiracy and the Protocols of the
Elders of Zion. New York, Harper & Row.
COONEY, Mark. (1994), “Evidence as Partisanship”. Law and
Society Review, Vol. 28, no 4, pp. 833-858.
________. (1997a), “Hunting Among Police and Predators:
he Enforcement of Traic Law”. Studies in Law, Politics and Society, Vol. 16, pp. 165-188.
________. (1997b), “From Warre to Tyranny: Lethal Conlict and the State”. American Sociological Review, no
62, pp. 316-338.
________. (2006), “he Criminological Potential of Pure
Sociology”. Crime, Law, and Social Change, Vol. 46, pp.
51-63.
________. (2009), Is Killing Wrong? A Study in Pure Sociology. Charlottesville, University of Virginia Press.
________ [and] PHILLIPS, Scott. (2002), “Typologizing Violence: A Blackian Perspective”. International Journal of
Sociology and Social Policy, Vol. 22, no 7/8, pp. 75-108.
________. (2013), “With God on One’s Side: he Social Geometry of Death Row Apologies”. Sociological Forum,
Vol. 28, no 1, pp. 159-178.
COWEN, Tyler. (2002), “he Fate of Culture”. he Wilson
Quarterly, Vol. 26, no 4, pp. 78-84.
CUSHMAN, homas. (2003), “Is Genocide Preventable?
Some heoretical Considerations”. Journal of Genocide
Research, Vol. 5, no 4, pp. 523-542.
DAVIS, Stephen T. (2005), “Genocide, Despair, and Religious
Hope: An Essay on Human Nature”. In: ROTH, John
K. (ed). Genocide and Human Rights: A Philosophic
Guide. New York, Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 35-45.
DIAMOND, Jared. (2005), Collapse: How Societies Choose
to Fail or Succeed. New York, Viking.
Bradley Campbell
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
483
DRECHSLER, Horst. (1980), Let us Die Fighting: he Struggle of the Herero and Nama Against German Imperialism (1884-1915). London, Zed Press.
EVANS, Gareth. (2008), he Responsibility to Protect: Ending Mass Atrocity Crimes Once and for All. Washington, Brookings Institutions Press.
FREEMAN, Michael. (1991), “he heory and Prevention of
Genocide”. Holocaust and Genocide Studies, Vol. 6, no
2, pp. 185-199.
________. (1995), “Genocide, Civilization and Modernity”.
he British Journal of Sociology, Vol. 46, no 2, pp. 207223.
FRIEDLANDER, Saul. (1997), Nazi Germany and the Jews,
Vol. 1. New York, Harper Collins.
FUJII, Lee Ann. (2009), Killing Neighbors: Webs of Violence
in Rwanda. Ithaca, Cornell University Press.
GOLDHAGEN, Daniel Jonah. (1996), Hitler’s Willing Executioners: Ordinary Germans and the Holocaust. New
York, Vintage Books.
GUTMAN, Roy. (1993), A Witness to Genocide. New York,
Macmillan.
HATZFELD, Jean. (2005), Into the Quick of Life. New York,
Trans-Atlantic.
HOFFMANN, Heath C. (2006), “Criticism as Deviance and
Social Control in Alcoholics Anonymous”. Journal of
Contemporary Ethnography, Vol. 35, no 6, pp. 669-695.
HOLA, Barbara; SMEULERS, Alette, [and] BIJLEVELD,
Catrien. (2011), “International Sentencing Facts and
Figures: Sentencing practice at the ICTY and ICTR”.
Journal of International Criminal Justice, Vol. 9, no 2,
pp. 411-439.
HORWITZ, Allan V. (1990), he Logic of Social Control.
New York, Plenum Press.
484
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
Bradley Campbell
ILIBAGIZA, Immaculée. (2007), Let to Tell: Discovering God
Amidst the Rwandan Holocaust. Carlsbad, Hay House.
JACQUES, Scott [and] WRIGHT, Richard. (2008), “Intimacy
with Outlaws: he Role of Relational Distance in Recruiting, Paying, and Interviewing Underworld Research Participants”. Journal of Research in Crime and
Delinquency, Vol. 45, no 1, pp. 22-38.
JUDAH, Tim. (1997), he Serbs: History, Myth and the Destruction of Yugoslavia. New Haven, Yale University Press.
KRAIN, Matthew. (2005), “International Intervention and
the Severity of Genocides and Politicides”. International
Studies Quarterly, Vol. 49, no 3, pp. 363-387.
KROEBER, heodora. (1961), Ishi in Two Worlds: A Biography of the Last Wild Indian in North America. Berkeley, University of California Press.
KUPERMAN, Alan J. (2005), “Suicidal Rebellions and the
Moral Hazard of Humanitarian Intervention”. Ethnopolitics, Vol. 4, no 2, pp. 149-173.
________. (2009), “Darfur: Strategic Victimhood Strikes
Again?”. Genocide Studies and Prevention, Vol. 4, no 3,
pp. 281-303.
MADLEY, Benjamin. (2004), “Patterns of Frontier Genocide 1803-1910: he Aboriginal Tasmanians, the Yuki
of California, and the Herero of Namibia”. Journal of
Genocide Research, Vol. 6, no 2, pp. 167-192.
MALCOLM, Noel. (1994), Bosnia: A short History. New
York, New York University Press.
MAMDANI, Mahmood. (2001), When Victims Become Killers: Colonialism, Nativism and the Genocide in Rwanda. Princeton, Princeton University Press.
MANN, Michael. (2005), he Dark Side of Democracy: Explaining Ethnic Cleansing. New York, Cambridge University Press.
MANNING, Jason. (2012), “Suicide as Social Control”. SocioBradley Campbell
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
485
logical Forum, Vol. 27, no 1, pp. 207-227.
________. (Forthcoming), “Aggressive Suicide”. International Journal of Law, Crime and Justice.
MCLUHAN, Marshall. (1964), Understanding Media: he
Extensions of Man. New York, New American Library.
MICHALSKI, Joseph H. (2003), “Financial Altruism or Unilateral Resource Exchanges? Toward a Pure Sociology
of Welfare”. Sociological heory, Vol. 21, no 4, pp. 341358.
MIDLARSKY, Manus I. (2005), he Killing Trap: Genocide in
the Twentieth Century. New York, Cambridge University Press.
MILES, William F. S. (2006), “Labeling ‘Genocide’ in Sudan:
A Constructionist Analysis of Darfur”. Genocide Studies and Prevention, Vol. 1, no 3, pp. 251-264.
MILLER, Virginia P. (1979), Ukomno’m: he Yuki Indians of
Northern California. Socorro, Ballena Press.
MODELSKI, George [and] PERRY, Gardner. (2002), “‘Democratization in Long Perspective’ Revisited”. Technological Forecasting and Social Change, Vol. 3, no 69, pp.
359-376.
OPDYKE, Irene Gut [and] ARMSTRONG, Jennifer. (1999),
In My Hands: Memories of a Holocaust Rescuer. New
York, Alfred A. Knopf.
PAYNE, James L. (2004), A History of Force: Exploring the
Worldwide Movement Against Habits of Coercion,
Bloodshed, and Mayhem. Sandpoint, Idaho, Lytton
Publishing Company.
PHILLIPS, Scott [and] LAPUCK, Jacqueline. (Forthcoming),
“Social Geometry and the Success of Moral Ideas: he
Case of Capital Punishment”. International Journal of
Law, Crime and Justice.
PINKER, Steven. (2011), he Better Angels of our Nature:
Why Violence Has Declined. New York, Viking.
486
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
Bradley Campbell
POWER, Samantha. (2002), ‘A Problem from Hell’: America
and the Age of Genocide. New York, Basic Books.
PRUNIER, Gerard. (1995), he Rwanda Crisis, 1959-1994:
History of a Genocide. London, Hurst.
REUTERS. (2012, January 10), “French Probe Exonerates
Rwanda Leader in Genocide”. Available online on:
https://www.reuters.com/article/2012/01/10/us-rwanda-genocide-report-idUSTRE80924720120110
REYNOLDS, Henry. (2006),he Other Side of the Frontier.
Sydney, University of New South Wales Press.
RUMMEL, Rudolph J. (1994), Death by Government. New
Brunswick, Transaction Publishers.
________. (1995), “Democracy, Power, Genocide, and Mass Murder.” Journal of Conlict Resolution, Vol. 39, no 1, pp. 3-26.
SENECHAL DE LA ROCHE, Roberta. (1996), “Collective Violence as Social Control”. Sociological Forum, Vol. 11, no
1, pp. 97-128.
________. (2001), “Why is Collective Violence Collective?”.
Sociological heory, Vol. 19, no 2, pp. 126-144.
SEUBERT, Virginia. (1991), “Sociology and Value Neutrality:
Limiting Sociology to the Empirical Level”. he American Sociologist, Vol. 22, no 3-4, pp. 210-220.
SNYDER, Timothy. (2010), Bloodlands: Europe between
Hitler and Stalin. New York, Basic Books.
STAUB, Ervin. (1989), he Roots of Evil: he Origins of
Genocide and Other Forms of Group Violence. New
York, Cambridge University Press.
TAYLOR, Christopher C. (2002), “he Cultural Face of Terror in the
Rwandan Genocide of 1994”. In: HINTON, Alexander Laban
(ed). Annihilating Diference: he Anthropology of Genocide. Berkeley, University of California Press, pp. 137-178.
TUCKER, James. (1989), “Employee het as Social Control”.
Deviant Behavior, Vol. 10, no 4, pp. 319-334.
Bradley Campbell
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
487
WALLER, James. (2002), Becoming Evil: How Ordinary
People Commit Genocide and Mass Killing. New York,
Oxford University Press.
WEBER, Max. (1958), “Science as a Vocation”. In: GERTH,
Hans Heinrich [and] MILLS, C. Wright (orgs). From
Max Weber: Essays in Sociology. New York, Oxford
University Press, pp. 129-156.
WIKIPEDIA. (2012a), “Genocide Denial”. Available (online)
on: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Genocide_denial
________. (2012b), “Responsibility to Protect”. Available
(online) on: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Responsibility_to_protect
RESUMEN: En consonancia con Donald Black, todo
conlicto resulta de movimientos del tiempo social
– alteraciones en la diversidad, en la estratiicación,
o en el grado de intimidad. Es el caso para los conlictos genocidas, que envuelven transformaciones en
términos de diversidad y estratiicación. Genocidios
resultan de ampliaciones en la diversidad, como en
el caso del contacto intercultural, y reducciones en la
estratiicación, como cuando miembros de un grupo
étnico subordinado buscan elevar su estatus. Pero el
genocidio es él propio un movimiento en el tiempo
social, una reducción de la diversidad y un aumento
en la estratiicación, y que provoca aún más conlicto. La teoría presentada em Genocidio y tempo social explica los conlictos que llevan al genocidio, así
como aquellos que de él resultan.
Palavras clave: genocidio, moralidad, sociología
pura, tiempo social, violencia
488
BRADLEY CAMPBELL (
[email protected]) é
professor assistente da California State University, em
Los Angeles, Califórnia (EUA). É PhD em sociologia pela
University of Virginia, tem master em sociologia pela
Clemson University, na Califórnia, e BA em sociologia
pela Lee University, em Cleeveland.
DILEMAS - Vol. 6 - no 3 - JUL/AGO/SET 2013 - pp. 465-488
Bradley Campbell