Cambridge University Press
978-1-107-10440-2 — Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Book X
Edited and translated by Joachim Aufderheide
Index
More Information
Index
activity
activation of capacity 131–2
best 167–9, 182
chosen for itself 67–8, 113–14,
152–3, 176–8, 209
complete 108
continuity of 122–4, 159, 169–71,
173, 183, 211
incomplete 108
individuation of 94, 132–5, 137–8
audience, Aristotle’s 2, 6–7, 27–8,
60–1, 97, 199, 222–3, 229–30
akribeia see precision
Alexander of Aphrodisias 62
amusement (paidia) 158–9, 179
Anacharsis 158–9
Anaxagoras 218–20, 225–6
animals 13–14, 55, 62–6, 71–3, 114,
128, 142–4, 210–11
authority
authoritative element determines whole 189–90
of a father 239, 244–6, 250–1
of judgement 156–7
of the law 244–6, 251
bios see life
bloom (hôra) 119–20
book
ancient division xi
‘common books’ 30–1, 53–4
Callicles 17, 90–3
character 18–19, 56, 92–4, 124–6,
232–2; see also virtue of
character
childhood 96
choice see also activity, chosen for
itself, kalon, to
de dicto vs de re 126–7
motive 235
‘package’ view of choice 92,
126–7, 178
community, political (koinônia)
230, 247–8
completeness see teleios
contemplation see theôria
desire 14, 17, 20, 124–7, 138–9, 223, 245
divine
activity 183–4, 205–10, 212
benefit 224–7
element 165–7, 169, 171, 184–5, 187
human beings as 188–90
influence on happiness 7,
216–17, 224–7, 233
280
© in this web service Cambridge University Press
www.cambridge.org
Cambridge University Press
978-1-107-10440-2 — Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Book X
Edited and translated by Joachim Aufderheide
Index
More Information
Index
development, ethical 158–9; see also
virtue, acquisition of
doctor 115–16, 231, 254, 264–6
education 55–6, 229, 236–7; see also
teaching
general vs particular knowledge
required 254–6
private 246–53
public 246–8, 252
Empedocles 188
energeia see activity
endoxa see method
enquiry, the goal of 27–8, 228–9;
see also audience, Aristotle’s
ergon 13–17, 101, 128–9, 142–4,
147–8, 166, 264
argument 13–15, 148, 164
human 13–15, 142–4, 148,
191–2
eudaimonia see happiness
Eudoxus
his argument from addition
68–71
his argument from opposites
65–8, 73–5
his argument from universal
pursuit 61–4, 71–3, 142
his character 64–5
exactness see precision
excellence see virtue
experience 234–6, 240, 255, 260–7,
269
expert 254–6, 261–2, 264
father 243–4, 250–1, 253
finality see teleios
fine see kalon
flatterer 95–6
friend 95–6, 120
function see ergon
© in this web service Cambridge University Press
281
genesis see pleasure, not a process
of coming to be
god(s) 205–9, 216, 224–7 see also
divine
good, the highest 4–7, 10–12,
16, 24–6, 27–8, 68–71, 150,
152–3, 158, 174–5, 193, 258; see
also happiness
goods
as qualities 75–6
as something limited/
determinate 77–80
common 247, 258
conditional 69–70, 93
good for 17, 62–3, 72–3, 91–3
intrinsic / in themselves 11,
24–6, 68–70, 80–3, 152–3, 223
habituation 233–8, 240, 259
happiness 24–7
activity of happiness 152–3, 164,
182, 209
acquisition of 233
aggregative conception of 211–12
as translating eudaimonia 7–8
as what makes life happy 10,
70–1, 153, 209
complete/perfect/final (teleia)
148, 164–7, 181–3, 207–9
criteria for 10–11; see also
self-sufficiency, teleios
divine 7, 184–5, 197, 207–12
found in leisure see leisure
extension of 210–13
in virtue of resemblance 212–13,
215, 231
level of determinateness of 175
outline of 7–17, 150–2
pleasures of 171–3
stability of 170
superlative 191–2, 209
www.cambridge.org
Cambridge University Press
978-1-107-10440-2 — Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Book X
Edited and translated by Joachim Aufderheide
Index
More Information
282
Index
health 80, 90–2, 94, 115–16, 145,
250, 253–5
hedonism see also Eudoxus
culture hedonism 154–5
normative 57, 62–4, 65–8
psychological 62–4, 65–6
‘sober’ hedonism 64–5
sybaritic hedonism 155–9
Heraclitus 142
Herodotus 216
Homer 247
honour 9–10, 68, 152, 180, 200–1
household 239–40, 248, 258, 270
human beings as compound 184–5,
188, 198
human nature 14, 22, 55, 58, 65, 97,
142–4, 147–8, 166–7, 183–92,
194, 214, 234, 236, 250
human needs 181, 199–200, 202,
214; see also self-sufficiency
human soul 14, 18–19, 161–2, 166,
185, 189–90, 197–8
illness 90–3, 145, 255
immortality 186–8, 244
inclusivism 11–12, 16, 24–7, 69,
203–4
intellectualism see monism
intelligence see nous
Isocrates 262
kalon, to (the fine) see also teleios
chosen for its own sake 68,
113–14, 127, 153–4, 176, 178–9,
189, 210, 236–7, 258
love for 232, 235–6
orientation towards 236–7, 240–1
Kant 56, 93
kinêsis see Movement and Pleasure
not a movement
© in this web service Cambridge University Press
law 237–46, 249–51, 257
law-giving 249–51, 254, 256–9
how to become expert at
259–70
learning 125–6, 144, 172, 232–6,
240–2, 259, 261–7
leisure 155–6, 163, 178–83, 188, 202,
204
life
of frivolous pleasure 9–10, 152,
155, 161–4, 193, 201
of practical virtue 9–10, 161,
184–6, 192–202, 207, 213–14
of reflection 184–8, 193, 201, 216,
218–20, 221
political 9–10, 152, 201–2
translating zôê or bios 163, 193
limit 77–9
liturgy 203
locomotion 106–7
logos (word, talk, reason) 232–3,
241, 244
love 124–6, 172, 176–7, 189, 224–6,
235–6, 251
malista (most of all) 189–92,
207–8
many, the 58–60, 218–20, 223,
232–3, 240–2
measure, the good man as 144–9,
156–7, 160
medicine 242–3, 255, 264–6
method
Aristotle’s method 2, 8–9, 60–1,
74–5, 89–90, 100, 150, 214,
268–9
genus et differentiae 100–2
match between word and deed
58–60, 64–5, 220–3
pragmatic considerations 57–9
www.cambridge.org
Cambridge University Press
978-1-107-10440-2 — Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Book X
Edited and translated by Joachim Aufderheide
Index
More Information
Index
monism 11–12, 16–18, 24–7, 70–1,
203–4
mortality 183, 186–8, 203, 207
movement
completion of 103–4, 107–8
definition of 108
difference in form 106–7
divisible into subprocesses
105–6, 131–2
taking time 109–10
nature 63, 85–6, 146–7, 233, 244
see also human nature
neutralism 76
nous (intelligence) 156, 165–9,
186–2, 198–9, 224–7, 243–5
now, the 109–10
nutrition 89, 146
outline (tupos) 24, 27, 150–2, 175,
228
pain 66–7, 73–5, 88–9, 237–8
perception
as end in itself 113–14, 209
norms of 118, 145
perfection see teleios and Pleasure
and completion/perfection
Pericles 245, 261
philosopher 199, 200, 202–4, 215,
218–20, 225–6, 272
philosophy 2, 172–3, 199, 225, 227,
268, 272; see also theôria
phronêsis 18–21, 153–4, 167–9,
185–7, 190, 195–8, 205, 213–15,
219–20, 230, 234–5, 263
piety 225
Plato
extent of background
knowledge required 2–3
© in this web service Cambridge University Press
283
on the role of the highest good
11, 69–71
Apology 225
Euthydemus 93
Euthyphro 225
Gorgias 90
Meno 233
Laws 227, 242–5
Phaedo 181
Philebus 69–71, 77–9, 81–3,
86–9, 99, 134, 140–1, 170, 189,
227
Protagoras 243, 245, 260–1
Republic 87, 97, 140–1, 157, 170,
177
Timaeus 188, 227
pleasure
alien (allotrios) 135–8
and virtue 98, 235
and completion/perfection
22–3, 113–20, 128–30
and fit 120–4
as superadded end 118–20
bad pleasures 89–94
bodily pleasure 88–9, 155–7,
162–3, 232
conditions of 113–22
continuity of 122–4
desire for 124–6, 138
dim when too familiar 122–4
enjoyment 91–3, 121, 124–6, 136,
139
functional definition of 101–2
human 142–9
kinds of 93–6, 127–38
likened to seeing 102–3
metaphysics of 75–6, 80–3,
102–3
not a movement 83–4, 103–12,
131–2
www.cambridge.org
Cambridge University Press
978-1-107-10440-2 — Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Book X
Edited and translated by Joachim Aufderheide
Index
More Information
284
Index
pleasure (cont.)
not a process of coming to be
84–9, 111–12
object of 139–40
proper (oikeion) 130–8, 142–4,
191–2
proximity to activity 126–7, 139
pure 79, 89, 140–1, 148–9
response-(in)dependence of
146–7
source of 91–4, 98
subject of 84–8
translation 23–4
uniformity of 131–3
value of 57–8, 68–71, 75–6,
89–100, 136–40, 142
pluralism see inclusivism
politician 6–7, 200–1, 229–31,
257–8, 260–1
politics
goal of 180, 229, 257–8
political life 199–202; see also life
of practical virtue
political science 229, 264
practical wisdom see phronêsis
praxis see virtuous action
precision
of activities 136
of exposition 150
of prescriptions 252
purity 79, 140–1, 148–9, 172–3
reason
as human characteristic 14,
15–16; see also human nature
as authoritative element 165–8,
184–5, 187–92, 241, 244
practical vs theoretical 19–21,
166, 168–9; see also theôria
and phronêsis
© in this web service Cambridge University Press
reflection (theoretical) see theôria
resources 200, 202–4, 213–20,
225–6
response–dependence 146–7
Sardanapallus 155
self-sufficiency 11, 153, 173–6, 214,
217
seriousness 159–62, 179, 182–3
sign 210
slave 162–3
Solon 216–18
sophia 20–1, 167–9, 172, 219; see
also theôria
sophist s 260–3
Speusippus 75
statesman see politician
spoudaios see measure, good
man as
taste 90–1, 145
teaching 231–2, 234–5, 255–6,
259–61, 263
teleios 10–11, 28–9, 81, 113–14, 129,
152–3
Theognis 231–2
theoretical wisdom see sophia
theôria 168–9, 170–1, 183, 202,
212–13
time 110, 211–12
Thales 219
tyrant 154–7, 163
virtue
as measure 91
acquisition of 231–41, 254–6;
see also habituation
characteristically human 195–9
of character 18–19, 56, 195,
206–7, 233–5
www.cambridge.org
Cambridge University Press
978-1-107-10440-2 — Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Book X
Edited and translated by Joachim Aufderheide
Index
More Information
Index
of intellect 19–21
political dimension of
258, 270
proper virtue of intelligence
166
rest of 184–5, 193, 196–7
stability of 170
virtuous action see also
kalon, to
lack of leisure 179–81, 204
resources required for 200–2
self-sufficiency of 174–6
© in this web service Cambridge University Press
285
the internal and external goal(s)
of 153–4, 176–8, 179–80, 219,
258
war 179–80, 182–3, 240
wealth 91–3, 200, 216, 218–19
wise, the 219
work see ergon
young, the 55, 236–40, 242, 251
zôê see life
www.cambridge.org
Cambridge University Press
978-1-107-10440-2 — Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Book X
Edited and translated by Joachim Aufderheide
Excerpt
More Information
Introduction
0. The Commentary
That a reader benefits from a commentary on Aristotle’s dense writing
should be obvious to anyone who has tried to read Aristotle. Precisely because there exist excellent commentaries on the Nicomachean Ethics already
(on which, see the Preface), why have a commentary on Book X? First,
many readers rightly regard Book X as the pinnacle of the Nicomachean
Ethics. It is here that he puts the coping-stone on the edifice so artfully
constructed in EN I–IX. Other readers, by contrast, find Book X incongruent with the rest of the EN because it seems to propagate an amoral
ideal, that of a thinker who flies high above the common run of people
and is not subject to their human concerns. So Book X is controversial and
will, for this reason, benefit from a fresh discussion.1
Second, none of the commentaries I have consulted are comprehensive
in the sense that they aspire to comment on the whole of the text of Book
X. Usually, they leave out the bits that seem too clear, too boring, or too
obscure. While I also do not comment on every single word or line, I
nevertheless try to be comprehensive, insofar as I divide the whole text
into units of thought, and then go through every unit in the corresponding entry of the commentary. I call the entries by their traditional name,
lemma (plural lemmata, from the Greek lêmma: assumption, premise, or
argument). Dividing the text comprehensively into lemmata, however,
yields more than mere comprehensiveness. It also allows the commentary
to trace the flow of Aristotle’s thought, to emphasise the continuity of his
arguments, and to show how the smaller units feed into the larger structure. So, the commentary tries not only to illuminate what Aristotle thinks
in each lemma, but also how he thinks.
1
I use the traditional acronym ‘EN’ (which stems from the Latin Ethica Nicomachea) instead of the
now common ‘NE’.
1
© in this web service Cambridge University Press
www.cambridge.org
Cambridge University Press
978-1-107-10440-2 — Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Book X
Edited and translated by Joachim Aufderheide
Excerpt
More Information
2
Introduction
But how do we find out what he thinks? What would help us to understand the point of each unit of thought? One influential line, adopted by many of the ancient commentators, is to explain ‘Aristotle through
Aristotle’. That is, we adduce other passages from the same author to illuminate the passage over which we puzzle. However, whether, and to what
extent, a commentary should rely on this time-tried hermeneutical principle depends on how we understand it. I have eschewed the version employed by many of the ancient commentators, because it seems to rest on
shaky ground. In particular, I reject inferences of the type ‘Aristotle must
mean … in this passage in the EN, because he says XYZ in the Physics.’
This approach seems to presuppose a more or less rigid system of thought
in which one can simply use the building-blocks from one work to patch
up apparent holes in another. But his thinking seems more flexible and
interesting, as the many signs of reworking the material show (cf. §4). A
more promising approach takes into account some flexibility in Aristotle’s
thought, but nevertheless assumes that the foundations of Aristotelian philosophy remain intact throughout his works. This approach, too, suggests
that he expected his readers to know his non-ethical treatises well enough
to understand the points made in the EN – even if the transferred building-blocks may need to be cut to size to make them fit. If his ethical philosophy is built in part on non-ethical foundations, it would be the task of the
commentary to guide the reader to the relevant passages in the non-ethical
works. But there is also an alternative that rejects the common assumption
of the first two approaches, namely that the EN rests on principles that are
justified in works other than those concerning ethics. This more circumspect approach derives some support from the methodological claim in
EN I.3 that an ethical enquiry has its own kind of precision, differing from
mathematics and, though not stated here, from first philosophy (what we
would call ‘metaphysics’) and natural science. Indeed, in the same chapter,
Aristotle makes demands on the character and age of a suitable audience,
but he does not seem to require previous knowledge of Aristotelian logic,
natural philosophy, or metaphysics. This might indicate that he takes the
latter qualification to be irrelevant to the successful study of ethics.2
The goal of this commentary is to bring Aristotle alive as a thinker. To this
end, each lemma raises and discusses what seem to me philosophically the
most pertinent questions. Usually this requires having an eye on what went
2
Scholars differ over the three hermeneutical approaches. For the latest examples of approaches one
and two, see the introduction in Henry and Nielsen 2015. For a trenchant critique, and a staunch
defence of the separability of ethics, see Polansky 2017.
© in this web service Cambridge University Press
www.cambridge.org
Cambridge University Press
978-1-107-10440-2 — Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Book X
Edited and translated by Joachim Aufderheide
Excerpt
More Information
The Commentary
3
on before, both in the immediate context, but also in the larger argument of
the EN. So, I whole-heartedly endorse ‘Aristotle through Aristotle’ as long
as the scope is confined to the EN. Of course, where relevant (and perhaps
necessary), I also refer the reader to Aristotle’s other works – but primarily
by way of background illustration. While most lemmata are self-contained,
in the sense that they do not rely on other texts to be intelligible, a number
of lemmata come properly to life only when read in the light of the Platonic
subtext. But does Plato really play this important role, given that the EN
contains less than a handful of direct references to Plato? And if he did
play that kind of role, why does Aristotle not say that his students must
know Plato’s philosophical writings? One way of answering the question
is to assume that Plato’s dialogues are aimed at a wider audience, and that
one might expect that a student wanting to study with Aristotle should be
sufficiently interested in philosophy to know at least the most important dialogues of Plato.3 But perhaps one can modify the answer to dispense with
the questionable assumption that dialogues such as the Philebus and the
Laws were widely known, and do so in two ways. Very few of the lemmata
are self-contained in the sense that they could be understood by just anyone. So, i), some training in, or experience with, philosophical thinking is
clearly required. This training may suffice to ‘get’ the argument on the page.
But Aristotle may also expect a specific type of philosophical training, ii),
training that partly consists of familiarity with Plato’s dialogues. Probably,
like Plato, Aristotle wrote the EN for a ‘mixed audience’, one having some
background in i) or ii). Those who discern the Platonic subtext will philosophically get more out of the text, but those who do not may still reach
the goal of the EN (on which §3.3). So, to make reading EN X as rewarding
as possible, the commentary provides the Platonic background where it is
especially fruitful for understanding the philosophical point at issue.
Upshot. The commentary focuses on the philosophical issues that arise
in the course of working through the text. Leaving aside philological niceties, the commentary will often explore several possible ways of reading
the text to enable the reader to make up her own mind about the best
interpretation of a given passage. It concentrates on conceptual questions,
individual arguments, and clusters thereof, and their contribution to the
overall arch of the argument in EN X. But the enquiry does not take place
3
Robb 1994, 233 suggests that ‘some of Plato’s dialogues were read aloud with success to sophisticated
groups of Athenians’. Cf. Harris 1989, 86 who notes that the works of Protagoras, Anaxagoras, and
Isocrates were published in Athens, at least partially, by being read out loud. So, one could pick up
some philosophy outside the specialised schools.
© in this web service Cambridge University Press
www.cambridge.org
Cambridge University Press
978-1-107-10440-2 — Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Book X
Edited and translated by Joachim Aufderheide
Excerpt
More Information
4
Introduction
in a vacuum, conceptual or historical. To bring out the best in Aristotle’s
arguments, the commentary places Aristotle’s thought in a wider framework. The philosophical framework of the EN on which the commentary
relies is sketched in the introduction. The relevant background in Plato’s
philosophy is given in the commentary.
1. The Guiding Principle of the Nicomachean Ethics
The Nicomachean Ethics (EN) is a well-organised work on ethics. It begins, in Book I, with the fairly indeterminate notion of ‘the highest good’,
which it subsequently spells out as happiness. How the highest good structures the whole treatise becomes clear from a postcard-sketch of the EN’s
content.
In an effort to spell out the highest good as happiness, Aristotle identifies living in accordance with excellence or virtue (aretê) as the key to a
happy life. The concept of virtue dominates the subsequent discussion.
Book II provides a general, almost abstract, treatment of virtue, while
Books III and VII contain perceptive treatises on the conditions for acting
virtuously. The individual virtues are discussed in Books III–VI; Books
VIII–IX deal with the social aspect of virtue.
Book X returns more explicitly to happiness as the highest good. A) The
discussion of pleasure (X.1–5) is geared towards connecting pleasure with
the happy life, i.e. a life in accordance with virtue. B) The study of three
prominent kinds of lives in X.6–8 seeks to determine, finally, the virtue in
accordance with which we should live in order to live a completely or perfectly happy life. C) The end of the EN (X.9) examines how we ourselves
and others may acquire virtue.
Since happiness as the highest good structures not only the whole EN,
but also Book X in particular, I shall discuss both the highest good and
happiness in some detail (§§1.1–5) before turning to a briefer sketch of
virtue (§§2.1–2) and an outline of EN X (§§3.1–3).
. The Highest Good
The Nicomachean Ethics centres on the notion of the highest good. More
specifically, it deals with the highest practicable good, the highest human
good, or simply the human good. Goodness, Aristotle maintains, plays a
crucial role in all directed human endeavours, as the beginning of the EN
illustrates: ‘every craft and every enquiry, and similarly every action and
planned undertaking seems to aim at some good’ (1094a1–2).
© in this web service Cambridge University Press
www.cambridge.org
Cambridge University Press
978-1-107-10440-2 — Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Book X
Edited and translated by Joachim Aufderheide
Excerpt
More Information
The Guiding Principle of the Nicomachean Ethics
5
Of course, the goods attained through the various undertakings and
even the notion of goodness at play in different domains will differ.
Nevertheless, all pursuits and their goods are organised into hierarchies.
To take Aristotle’s example, bridle-making and other crafts that produce
gear for horsemanship do so for the sake of horsemanship. In turn, horsemanship and other pursuits belonging to war are subordinate to generalship. Although both bridle-making and horsemanship are subordinate to
generalship, they relate to it in different ways. We can see this by considering how they relate to the goal of generalship, i.e. winning the battle.
While bridle-making is purely instrumental in attaining the goal, excellent
horsemanship can be more than an instrument. The latter can be part of
winning the battle in the sense that excellent horsemanship can constitute
(wholly or partially) winning the battle (I.1.1094a9–14). Although the cavalry is employed for the sake of winning the battle, they will not be mere
instruments.
The example seeks to illustrate the general relationship between subordinate and superordinate pursuits: ‘in all pursuits, the ends of all the ruling
pursuits are more choice-worthy than the ends under them, because it is
for the sake of the former that the latter too are pursued’ (1094a14–16).
The superordinate pursuit rules or controls the subordinate in either of
two ways.4 It can a) prescribe the norms internal to the pursuit. For instance, the practice of riding will determine what counts as a good bridle –
which would seem appropriate, given the bridle’s role as an instrument
that facilitates riding. Alternatively, b), the superordinate pursuit can externally regulate the subordinate pursuit. A general need not tell the cavalry how to ride well. That is, the general does not pronounce on the norms
internal to horsemanship. Rather, the general decides on how many riders
comprise a unit, where to employ them, and when to send them into
battle. In this case, the externally regulated pursuit has its own notion of
excellence, whereas the internally regulated one does not. As the former
has a goal worth pursuing for its own sake (from this pursuit’s perspective),
it occupies a higher place in the hierarchy of ends.
Introducing planned pursuits as nested hierarchies raises the question of
what makes for a complete hierarchy of goals and pursuits. Aristotle argues
that there must be end-points that complete the hierarchical structure. In
the absence of suitable end-points, we would have to admit to unending
hierarchies:
4
Lear 2004, 17–19 distinguishes the two ways of subordination well. See Meyer 2011 for further
illuminating discussion.
© in this web service Cambridge University Press
www.cambridge.org
Cambridge University Press
978-1-107-10440-2 — Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Book X
Edited and translated by Joachim Aufderheide
Excerpt
More Information
Introduction
6
If, then, there is some end in our practical pursuits for which we wish for its
own sake, and we wish for the others because of it, and we do not choose
everything for the sake of something else (for in this way, it will go on to
infinity, making our desire empty and vain), it is clear that this is the good,
i.e. the best good. (a–)
The goal that ends the regress is the good because the good subordinates
all other goals. Aristotle takes care to posit a single good that subsumes all
other goods. While ‘the good’ may plausibly refer to the good of a certain
domain, the best good towers over and controls all other goods.
The proposal has wide-ranging consequences for Aristotle’s thinking
about goods. Of course, it does not follow from the observation that all
planned pursuits aim at some good (1094a1–2) that every good is (to be)
aimed at by some pursuit. There may be goods that cannot be attained
through action. But, as the beginning of the EN makes clear, Aristotle
focuses entirely on practicable goods. And here it is plausible to maintain that any practical good is the good of a practical domain that can
be mastered by some kind of practical knowledge. So, corresponding to
the hierarchies of goals, Aristotle posits a hierarchy of (kinds of ) practical
knowledge that govern the practical spheres. If so, the highest good will be
the goal of the highest and most controlling kind of practical knowledge.
He plausibly identifies the most controlling with the most authoritative
practical knowledge. He uses examples to cast political expertise (politikê)
in this role. Political expertise governs directly or indirectly all aspects of
life in a city-state (polis): which crafts are needed, how many craftsmen
for each, when to wage war; it also legislates what one should and should
not do. So, the best practical good will be the goal of political expertise
(1094a29–b6).
To identify the most controlling knowledge with political expertise
raises the question of the EN’s audience. Does Aristotle merely address
aspiring politicians? Or does he cast his net more widely? The answer, as
so often, is a qualified ‘both’. The EN addresses those who seem to lack
knowledge of the highest good. Since this knowledge belongs to political
expertise, and since the Nicomachean Ethics seeks the highest good, it will
itself in a way be political (politikê tis, 1094b11). However, Aristotle does
not seem to address only would-be statesmen.5 Achieving and preserving
the highest good for the city-state is greater, more complete, finer, and
more divine than doing the same for an individual. However, the latter
5
Pace Bodéüs 1993.
© in this web service Cambridge University Press
www.cambridge.org
Cambridge University Press
978-1-107-10440-2 — Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Book X
Edited and translated by Joachim Aufderheide
Excerpt
More Information
The Guiding Principle of the Nicomachean Ethics
7
should also be welcomed, because the goal is the same in both cases: the
human good (1094b7–11). While he ranks the political expertise successfully exercised by the politician higher than the equivalent on the private
level, Aristotle nevertheless seems to acknowledge the private equivalent
of political expertise – without seeing the need to find a new name for it.
Indeed, he spells out much later in the EN the sameness between political
expertise and the expertise required to run a private life well (VI.8). For
now, however, the important point is that we as private individuals can
acquire a kind of knowledge, discussed in the Nicomachean Ethics, which
aims at the highest good. This knowledge will have a great impact on our
lives because, just as every pursuit in the city is subordinate to the highest
good, so is every pursuit for a private individual.
. Happiness
Having identified political expertise as the knowledge of the highest practical good, Aristotle seeks to identify its goal more precisely: ‘in name, it
is agreed pretty much by the majority, for both the many and the distinguished call it “happiness” (eudaimonia), and they take living well and
doing well to be the same as being happy’ (I.4.1095a17–20).
The passage raises two important issues, one about happiness, the
other about method. First, ‘happiness’ does not translate the Greek term
eudaimonia perfectly. But it is preferable to ‘flourishing’ or ‘well-being’,
or to leaving it untranslated. All of the translations fail to convey the connection to the divine, clearly present in eudaimonia. The word is after all
the abstract composite of two words, eu and daimôn. The former is the
adverb for ‘good’; the latter means ‘god’ or ‘deity’, or, more barbarically,
‘higher-than-human-being’. Aristotle cites the tragic playwright Euripides
(ca 485–407/6 bc) to connect the two: a person is happy ‘when the god
gives well’ (hotan ho daimôn eu didô(i), IX.9.1169b7–8). While Aristotle
and his contemporaries did not necessarily take the god to mete out happiness – this would have to be investigated (cf. I.9.1099b11–13) – the quote
from Euripides indicates two points: a) a connection between the divine
and human happiness, however ossified, and b) the absence of determinate
content of happiness conceived abstractly.
Our concept of happiness, I think, captures the second aspect better
than does ‘flourishing’ or ‘well-being’. Like its Greek counterpart, ‘happiness’ does not have a fixed referent, nor a fixed range of applications.
Ordinary people, Aristotle reports, equate eudaimonia with pleasure,
wealth, or honour. Some do not even settle for a single goal, but adopt
© in this web service Cambridge University Press
www.cambridge.org
Cambridge University Press
978-1-107-10440-2 — Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Book X
Edited and translated by Joachim Aufderheide
Excerpt
More Information
8
Introduction
a different goal depending on their circumstances. For instance, to those
who are ill, health might seem to be happiness. By contrast, philosophers
such as Plato distinguish between these ordinary goods and the highest
good existing by itself, making the latter the cause of the former (1095a20–
8). While we rarely speak about happiness abstractly outside of academic
contexts, we do speak a lot about being or feeling happy. Although ‘being
happy’ does not mean ‘being in an elated mood’ or ‘feeling pleasure’, this
common usage fits the conception of happiness employed by the many.
For them, being pleased amounts to being happy, because they take happiness to be pleasure. However, eudaimonia can also be understood as pointing to a more stable or enduring condition (than fleeting happiness). And
while being happy may be conceived of as momentary, living well and
doing well appear to be more enduring conditions – as if being eudaimôn
is something more stable than an elated feeling. ‘Flourishing’ in particular
seems more apt for catering for this aspect of the concept of eudaimonia,
because doing well and living well can plausibly be understood in terms of
prosperity – which we can readily capture as flourishing.6 But ‘happiness’
and its cognates can also indicate a stable state. Think of the formulaic endings of fairy-tales. ‘They lived happily ever after’, usually because
they have surmounted some obstacle, have found each other, have been
rewarded with, say, half a kingdom, and are generally happy. ‘Living happily’ conveys the stability that being eudaimôn can connote, but it stresses
the psychological dimension more than ‘flourishing’ does, for the Prince
and the Princess naturally also feel happy when they prosper. So, our concept of happiness mirrors the versatility of the concept of eudaimonia with
which Aristotle begins his enquiry.
Why should we not choose our translation of eudaimonia merely for its
capacity to capture Aristotle’s conception of it?7 We can answer the question
by attending to the second point that the passage from I.4 (quoted above)
raises. It begins by noting how the word eudaimonia is used, and what
people think about it. The case of happiness illustrates how Aristotle often
operates in the EN. He raises a difficult question, notes either what people
of repute and the many say about it (where relevant), and then examines
more thoroughly where the existing opinions go right and wrong. He is
not usually content with pointing out the mistakes of previous thinkers.
In addition, he tries to diagnose what was (or is) attractive about the view,
6
7
Indeed, this was a widespread use of the term: see Herodotus, Histories, V.28; cf. VII.220.
Most scholars focus on Aristotle’s own conception of eudaimonia and assess its affinity to our
conceptions. See especially Kraut 1979.
© in this web service Cambridge University Press
www.cambridge.org
Cambridge University Press
978-1-107-10440-2 — Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Book X
Edited and translated by Joachim Aufderheide
Excerpt
More Information
The Guiding Principle of the Nicomachean Ethics
9
and often he acknowledges that the other thinkers got something right. It
would otherwise be a mystery why he would engage with his predecessors
at all. So, by dwelling on the views of others, and distilling what truth
they contain, he can develop his own view while keeping an eye on the
desiderata the examination of others has revealed. This technique seems
sensible for anyone who tries to answer difficult philosophical questions –
and philosophers still employ it today. But many scholars see an ‘endoxic
method’ in Aristotle’s approach, articulated at EN VII.1.1145b2–7, which
serves to justify ethical propositions.8 However, the passage in Book VII
seems tailored to its specific context and should not be generalised.9 And
examining how he in fact proceeds in the EN outside of the Book VII
passage casts further doubt on the assumption that a set endoxic method
is used throughout the EN.10 In any case, it is clear that Aristotle sees
himself in a tradition of theorising about eudaimonia. Even when he corrects the mistakes of others and advances his own substantial account, he
nevertheless takes himself to be talking about the same thing, eudaimonia.
Therefore, the translation should be sufficiently wide to accommodate the
various accounts, even if only Aristotle’s is the correct one.
He begins to think properly about the highest good as happiness by
discussing, briefly, three prominent contenders for happy lives in EN I.5:
i) the life of consumption (apolaustikos), ii) the political life (politikos), and
iii) the reflective life (theôrêtikos). He does so because one’s conception of
happiness (articulated or not) does influence how one lives – after all, it is
the overarching goal of all one’s pursuits. The first two lives are plausible
candidates because of their wide support. The life of pleasure is compelling because living happily requires pleasure and thus goes hand in hand
with living a pleasant life (VII.11.1152b6–7). The political life becomes a
serious contender if we do not understand it merely as living the life of a
citizen in a Greek city-state, but as a more elevated kind of life. Indeed,
Aristotle posits honour as the highest good pursued by people living this
kind of life (timê, 1095b22–3). This goal suggests that the political activity in question should go beyond the ordinary political participation in
the assembly or in the jury. Since so many citizens engage in an ordinary
way in politics, no one will be especially honoured or deemed especially
happy for doing only that. Citizens merit honour only in high office, and
it is no accident that offices which involve ruling others (archai, e.g. like
8
9
10
For a clear statement and defence of this view, see Kraut 2006.
Cooper 2009.
See Frede 2012 for a nice corrective to this assumption.
© in this web service Cambridge University Press
www.cambridge.org
Cambridge University Press
978-1-107-10440-2 — Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Book X
Edited and translated by Joachim Aufderheide
Excerpt
More Information
10
Introduction
those of military leaders) were also called ‘honours’ (timai, e.g. Politics,
II.8.1268a21; III.5.1278a20; III.10.1281a31). The happy political life envisaged in I.5 will, therefore, be a life of political distinction, not merely one
of political participation.11 Both lives home in on important values, but
they assign to them a role too important. By judging the life of pleasure
as fit only for cattle, Aristotle intimates that pleasure is not a suitable goal
for political expertise, the knowledge that enables us to strive at the human good (I.5.1095b19–20). By contrast, honour seems all too human,
because it requires other people to honour us (I.5.1095b23–6). It is really
what people are honoured for, their virtue, that people want. So, neither
of the accounts posits a good suitable as the object of a branch of knowledge,12 nor does either one capture the elevated status of the highest good
as something divine. Both pleasure and honour should be concomitants of
happiness, but fail to capture its essential character.
As it turns out, the discussion of lives only provides a preliminary assessment – evident not least by the choice not to discuss the philosophical
life in Book I. Book X fittingly contains the final discussion of potentially happy lives. Having re-examined the life of frivolous pleasure in X.6,
Aristotle assesses the happiness of the life in accordance with theoretical
wisdom vis-à-vis a thoroughly practical life. Although these lives do not
come with the labels ‘political’ and ‘philosophical’, they seem to correspond to the lives sketched in I.5, as a close reading of the relevant text
(provided in the commentary) suggests.
. Happiness as the Highest Good
Having discussed what people say about happiness in I.4–6, Aristotle turns
in I.7 to establishing happiness as the highest human good on less dialectical grounds. In particular, he stresses two criteria for the highest good.
i) The highest good must be teleios. The Greek word forms the adjective of the more familiar telos, which we can render as ‘goal’ or ‘end’. The
adjective conveys ‘endyness’ (or, better, ‘finality’), but also ‘perfection’ and
‘completeness’. We can use teleios to rank goods in a hierarchy. A higher
good will be more teleios (complete/perfect/final) than a subordinate good.
The highest good, naturally, will be most so, or, as Aristotle puts it, it will
be teleios ‘without qualification’, because it is not subordinate to anything
11
12
Happiness based on political engagement stems from a sustained and successful effort to shape the
city-state’s fortunes. Although the offices often lasted only for a year at a time, those who excelled
nevertheless managed to be re-elected and to shape the state through their political activity.
Establishing this conclusion is an important task of Plato’s Gorgias.
© in this web service Cambridge University Press
www.cambridge.org