manifesto for a post-critical pedagogy
Before you start to read this book, take this
moment to think about making a donation to
punctum books, an independent non-proit press,
@ https://punctumbooks.com/support/
If you’re reading the e-book, you can click on the
image below to go directly to our donations site.
Any amount, no matter the size, is appreciated and
will help us to keep our ship of fools aloat. Contributions from dedicated readers will also help us to
keep our commons open and to cultivate new work
that can’t ind a welcoming port elsewhere. Our adventure is not possible without your support.
Vive la open-access.
Fig. 1. Hieronymus Bosch, Ship of Fools (1490–1500)
manifesto for a post-critical pedagogy. Copyright © 2017 by the editors
and authors. his work carries a Creative Commons BY-NC-SA 4.0 International
license, which means that you are free to copy and redistribute the material in
any medium or format, and you may also remix, transform, and build upon the
material, as long as you clearly attribute the work to the authors (but not in a way
that suggests the authors or punctum books endorses you and your work), you
do not use this work for commercial gain in any form whatsoever, and that for
any remixing and transformation, you distribute your rebuild under the same
license. https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0/
First published in 2017 by punctum books, Earth, Milky Way.
https://punctumbooks.com
ISBN-13: 978-1-947447-38-7 (print)
ISBN-13: 978-1-947447-39-4 (ePDF)
lccn: 2017961281
Library of Congress Cataloging Data is available from the Library of Congress
Book design: Vincent W.J. van Gerven Oei
Manifesto for a
Post-Critical Pedagogy
Naomi Hodgson
Joris Vlieghe
Piotr Zamojski
Contents
Introduction · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · 11
Naomi Hodgson, Joris Vlieghe, and Piotr Zamojski
MANIFESTO FOR A POST-CRITICAL PEDAGOGY
Manifesto for a Post-Critical Pedagogy · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · 15
Naomi Hodgson, Joris Vlieghe, and Piotr Zamojski
responses
A Response to the
“Manifesto for A Post-Critical Pedagogy” · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · 23
Tyson E. Lewis
A Sociologist’s Conversation with the
“Manifesto for a Post-Critical Pedagogy” · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · 35
Olga Ververi
Towards a Pedagogical Hermeneutics: A Response to the
“Manifesto for a Post-Critical Pedagogy” · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · ·43
Norm Friesen
Diferences hat Might Matter?
A Manifesto Difractively Read · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · 49
Geert hyssen
ix
he Post-Critical Mind as a Gateway to
Embodied Hope and Love for the World · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · 57
Oren Ergas
Love for the World in Education · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · ·63
Stefan Ramaekers
post-critique
Post-Critique: A Conversation between
Naomi Hodgson, Joris Vlieghe, and Piotr Zamojski· · · · · · · · · 71
Contributors · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · · 103
x
Introduction
Naomi Hodgson, Joris Vlieghe, and Piotr Zamojski
he Manifesto for a Post-Critical Pedagogy was written in September 2016 and irst presented at Liverpool Hope University
on October 17, 2016. At that launch event, we heard a keynote
response from Tyson Lewis and further invited responses from
Geert hyssen and Olga Ververi. From the outset, having made
the manifesto available online in open access, we were encouraged by the enthusiastic response and the genuine interest
shown by colleagues internationally. We therefore chose to invite further responses, to broaden the conversation, but did so
speciically from early- to mid-career scholars. Hence, we also
include here responses from Oren Ergas, Norm Friesen, and
Stefan Ramaekers.
When seeking a way to publish the manifesto and the responses to it, we looked purposefully beyond the usual avenues
taken in our ield, for a publisher in keeping with the ethos of
the manifesto itself. We thank punctum books and Eileen Joy
and Vincent W.J. van Gerven Oei in particular for the conidence and enthusiasm they have shown in this project.
he strong commitment to open access publishing by
punctum books is part of a shiting environment for academic
publishing in which the demands of visibility and metrics
compete with, and compromise, the public dimension of
publication in academia. We are grateful to Liverpool Hope
University for the Higher Education Impact Funding we
11
manifesto for a post-critical pedagogy
received to support the cost not only of publication but also of
maintaining the book in open access in perpetuity.
We would also like to thank the Centre for Higher Education
and Policy Analysis (CEPA) at Liverpool Hope University and
the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain (PESGB)
for their support in hosting and funding the launch seminar.
We provide no commentary here on the manifesto itself, or
the responses that follow it in this book, other than to say that,
as a manifesto it is intended to be short and to contain no references. he responses are more academic in style but still adopt
a more conversational tone than a regular text, and they vary
in length. he conversation form is taken up more fully in the
inal chapter in which we seek to address some of the questions
they raise in ways that, we hope, provide further provocation
and keep the conversation open.
12
MANIFESTO FOR
A POST-CRITICAL
PEDAGOGY
Manifesto for a Post-Critical Pedagogy
Naomi Hodgson, Joris Vlieghe, and Piotr Zamojski
Formulating principles, in philosophy of education at least,
seems to hark back to a form of normative, conceptual analysis associated with Anglophone, analytic styles of philosophy.
But poststructuralist and postmodernist philosophy — at least
as they have been taken up in educational theory and in popular thought more generally — oten brings with it a relativism,
which while potentially inclusive, and certainly constitutive today of the possibility of individual choice, renders the defence of
principles diicult. By stating principles in the form of a manifesto, we risk accusations of universalising, exclusive normativity. But, it is perhaps time to question the assumption that these
are inherently and always negative. Below we set out principles
founded in the belief in the possibility of transformation, as
found in critical theory and pedagogy, but with an airmative
attitude: a post-critical orientation to education that gains purchase on our current conditions and that is founded in a hope
for what is still to come.
he irst principle to state here is simply that there are principles to defend. But this does not in itself commit us to anything further, i.e., that we ought to do x. his is not normativity
in the sense of deining an ideal current or future state against
which current practice should be judged. hus, this principle
might be characterised as the defence of a shit from procedural
normativity to principled normativity.
15
manifesto for a post-critical pedagogy
In educational theory, poststructuralist and postmodernist thought has oten been taken up in terms of the politics of
identity, and so a concern with otherness, alterity, and voice.
Respect for the other and for diference requires that educators accept that we can never fully know the other. Any attempt
to do so constitutes “violence” against the other, so to speak.
hus, the possibility of acting and speaking is foreclosed; a political as well as an educational problem, perhaps summarised
in the oten heard (albeit mumbled) phrase “I know you’re not
allowed to say this anymore, but…,” and the bemoaning of socalled political correctness. he acceptance that we can never
fully understand the other — individual or culture — ought not
to entail that we cannot speak. his rendering of “respect” overlooks that understanding and respect are perpetual challenges
and hopes. Here, we start from the assumption that we can
speak and act — together — and thus shit from the hermeneutical pedagogy that critical pedagogy entails, to defend a — second principle — pedagogical hermeneutics. It is precisely the
challenges of living together in a common world that constitute
the hope that make education continue to seem a worthwhile
activity. Hermeneutics isn’t a (unsolvable) problem, but rather
something educators need to create. We shouldn’t speak and act
on the basis of a priori assumptions about the (im)possibility of
real mutual understanding and respect, but rather show that,
in spite of the many diferences that divide us, there is a space
of commonality that only comes about a posteriori (cf. Arendt,
Badiou, Cavell).
his existing space of commonality is oten overlooked in
much educational research, policy, and practice in favour of a
focus on social (in)justice and exclusion, based on an assumption of inequality. he ethos of critical pedagogy endures today
in the commitment to achieving equality, not through emancipation, but rather through empowerment of individuals and
communities. However, it is rendered hopeless — not to mention, cynical — by the apparent inescapability of neoliberal rationality. But, there is no necessity in the given order of things,
and thus, insurmountable as the current order seems, there is
16
manifesto for a post-critical pedagogy
hope. he third principle, then, based on the assumption of
equality (cf. Rancière) and of the possibility of transformation — at the individual and collective levels — entails a shit
from critical pedagogy to post-critical pedagogy.
his is by no means an anti-critical position. It is thanks to
the enormous and extremely powerful critical apparatus developed throughout the 20th century that we are aware of the main
features of the status quo we are immersed in. But, unlike the
inherent critique of societal institutions focused on their dysfunctionality, or the utopian critique, driven from a transcendent position and leading towards eternal deferral of the desired
change, we believe that it is time to focus our eforts on making
attempts to reclaim the suppressed parts of our experience; we
see the task of a post-critical pedagogy as not to debunk but to
protect and to care (cf. Latour, Haraway). his care and protection take the form of asking again what education, upbringing,
school, studying, thinking, and practicing are. his reclaiming
entails no longer a critical relation — revealing what is really going on — nor an instrumental relation — showing what educators ought to do — but creating a space of thought that enables
practice to happen anew. his means (re)establishing our relation to our words, opening them to question, and giving philosophical attention to these devalued aspects of our forms of life,
and thus — in line with a principled normativity — to defend
these events as autotelic, not functionalised, but simply worth
caring for.
Education is, in a very practical sense, predicated on hope. In
“traditional” critical pedagogy, however, this hope of emancipation rests on the very regime of inequality it seeks to overcome,
in three particular ways:
1. It enacts a kind of hermeneutical pedagogy: the educator assumes the other to lack the means to understand that they
are chained by their way of seeing the world. he educator
positions herself as external to such a condition, but must
criticize the present and set the unenlightened free (cf. Plato’s cave).
17
manifesto for a post-critical pedagogy
2. In reality this comes down to reairming one’s own superior position, and thus to reinstalling a regime of inequality.
here is no real break with the status quo.
3. Moreover, the external point of view from which the critical pedagogue speaks is through and through chained to the
status quo, but in a merely negative way: the critic is driven
by the passion of hate. In doing so, she or he surreptitiously
sticks to what is and what shall always be. Judgmental and
dialectical approaches testify to this negative attitude.
hus, the pedagogue assumes the role of one who is required to
lit the veil; what they lit the veil from, however, is a status quo
on which they stand in external judgment. To formulate more
positively the role of the pedagogue as initiating the new generation into a common world, we ofer the idea of a post-critical
pedagogy, which requires a love for the world. his is not an
acceptance of how things are, but an airmation of the value of
what we do in the present and thus of things that we value as
worth passing on. But not as they are: educational hope is about
the possibility of a renewal of our common world. When we
truly love the world, our world, we must be willing to pass it on
to the new generation, on the assumption that they — the newcomers — can take it on, on their terms. hus, the fourth principle entails a shit from cruel optimism (cf. Berlant) to hope
in the present. Cynicism and pessimism are not, in a sense, a
recognition of how things are, but an avoidance of them (cf.
Cavell, Emerson).
In current formulations, taking care of the world is framed in
terms of education for citizenship, education for social justice,
education for sustainability, etc. in view of a particular notion of
global citizenship and an entrepreneurial form of intercultural
dialogue. Although perhaps underpinned by a progressive, critical pedagogy, the concern in such formulations of responsibility for the world is with ends external to education. Traditional
or conservative as it might sound, we wish to defend education
for education’s sake: education as the study of, or initiation into,
a subject matter for its intrinsic, educational, rather than in18
manifesto for a post-critical pedagogy
strumental, value, so that this can be taken up anew by the new
generation. Currently, the (future) world is already appropriated
by “education for…” and becomes instrumental to (our) other
ends. hus, the ith principle takes us from education for citizenship to love for the world. It is time to acknowledge and to
airm that there is good in the world that is worth preserving. It
is time for debunking the world to be succeeded by some hopeful recognition of the world. It is time to put what is good in the
world — that which is under threat and which we wish to preserve — at the centre of our attention and to make a conceptual
space in which we can take up our responsibility for them in the
face of, and in spite of, oppression and silent melancholy.
19
RESPONSES
1
A Response to the “Manifesto for A PostCritical Pedagogy”
Tyson E. Lewis
First, I would like to thank Hodgson, Vlieghe, and Zamojski for
inviting me to this event and for allowing me to engage with
their ideas. But I must admit that I almost felt like this was a
set-up or an ironic gesture. How can I give a critical response to
a post-critical manifesto without immediately falling prey to the
very problems of critique that the authors identify? If I provide
a critical analysis, then would my response even be relevant?
Could I not immediately be dismissed as symptomatic of a failure in educational philosophy to produce airmative principles?
And if the response cannot be critical without falling into a trap,
need it simply be an airmation, meaning a repetition of what
has already been said? If this were the case, then I need not continue as my response would be redundant. I can merely pack my
bags and head home. Both critique and simple airmation seem
unsatisfactory at this point, and would fail to take up the call
for a creative hermeneutic that has to be produced. As such, my
only real choice in writing this response is to utilize the principles of post-critique in order to care for post-critique. Such care
need not simply be an airmation. Rather, it can point to that
which the authors have failed to care about in their own call to
care, and thus can further develop an underdeveloped aspect
of their post-critical turn. he resulting paper is my attempt to
23
manifesto for a post-critical pedagogy
respond to post-critique by caring for that which is present in
the author’s statement and yet remains marginal and peripheral:
the question of aesthetic form.
Hodgson, Vlieghe, and Zamojski have provided us with an
evocative manifesto for a post-critical pedagogy. hey highlight
the deiciencies with three dominant trends in educational philosophy: Anglophone/analytic; poststructuralist; and critical
schools of thought. Analytic forms of educational philosophy
fall prey to charges of exclusivity and/or ideal theory, which
seems to foreclose on the possibility of the new from appearing
precisely because principles have already been posited that deine what the good is and how we ought to pursue it. At the other extreme of the spectrum, poststructuralism has let us with a
world of only relative opinions and, thus, has eclipsed the common world of which we are a part. No longer can we posit any
principles whatsoever, for all principles are the result of forms
of power over and against someone or something. he result of
this position is the splintering of the common into ever smaller
and more selective sub-cultures and counter-publics, which
might have had some progressive political and educational purposes at one time, but today, it seems that such fragmentation is
part and parcel of the logic of global inance capitalism, which
continually attempts to create niche markets for commodity
exchange. Opposed to this logic of the market, we ind critical
pedagogy, which, as the authors point out, takes a transcendent position outside of the system of capitalism in order to denounce that which is. Here, we ind the great refusal at work, a
refusal that is predicated on dialectical negation in the name of
a utopia to come. Such a position proclaims relative autonomy
from circuits of capitalist production and consumption, yet, in
this very same gesture, reproduces a kind of stultifying logic of
inequality between the critical pedagogue, who has the correct
political orientation and critical knowledge of how things really
are, and the student, who is mystiied by a naïve consciousness.
Hodgson, Vlieghe, and Zamojski ofer up not merely an alternative, but an airmative one at that. hey shit the parameters of the debate from either a relativistic embrace of every24
a response
thing that is, or a critical denunciation of everything that is, to
a position of caring for and protecting the world — not in the
sense of merely accepting the status quo, but rather in the sense
of valuing the present as containing the possibility of renewal of
the commons as an inherent good in itself. his is a commons
that is (a) denied by poststructuralists and (b) deferred into the
future by both the analytic and critical schools. What the authors want to highlight is the common as it exists in the present.
here is much that I agree with in this manifesto, and many
aspects of it dovetail nicely with my own interest in study.1 In
particular, I ind it praiseworthy that the authors have provided
an outline of a new approach to thinking through philosophy
of education that is bold and has the potential to reorient the
ield toward new possibilities. What I would like to do here is
spend the next couple of minutes thinking about the form of address the authors have chosen — the manifesto — and consider
the educational and political implications of this choice. My assumption is that we cannot neglect to consider forms of writing
as having educational importance. My question to the authors
is thus: Does the content match the form? Is the manifesto adequate for articulating a post-analytic, post-post-structural, and
post-critical educational philosophy?
When we think of educational modes of address that attempt
to articulate principles for change, three come to mind. his is
not an exhaustive list by any means. Rather, it is an attempt to
provide a topology of forms of writing so that we can begin to
understand how diferent forms have diferent pedagogical implications. First, there is the educational creed. Perhaps the most
famous creed was proposed by John Dewey. Published in 1897
in School Journal, Dewey’s creed is important not so much in
relation to its contents — which he more eloquently spells out
in any number of other places — as its mode of address. he
creed is a personal testimony to held beliefs. In this sense, the
“my” in Dewey’s title, “My Pedagogic Creed,” is redundant for
1
Tyson Lewis, On Study: Giorgio Agamben and Educational Potentiality
(New York: Routledge, 2013).
25
manifesto for a post-critical pedagogy
all creeds are of a personal, and thus individual, nature. Groups
and institutions do not usually have creeds. Each statement in
Dewey’s creed begins with “I believe x.” Dewey thus emphasizes
that each statement is not a statement of fact, or of a collective
standpoint, so much as his opinion. Granted, this opinion is a
learned one, but the point remains: the creed belongs to someone, it is someone’s perspective.
he impact of Dewey’s creed on current teacher education
should not be underestimated. here are any number of articles
describing its impact on the public’s perception of the role of
schools in promoting social change, as well as articles describing the relationship between the creed and Dewey’s later, more
philosophically robust, books on education, democracy, and the
school. Yet, in my review of Dewey’s creed, no one seems to have
paused to point out the form of the creed itself, and to speculate
why Dewey chose this form. As a formal statement of personal
belief, a creed is not a philosophy, nor is it a set of laws, nor is it
a set of scientiic principles. Rather, it is a passionate conviction
that one holds. It conveys faith in something or someone. As
such, the creed can be traced back to religious confession. For
this reason, it is not at all surprising that Dewey would end his
creed (which testiies to the powers of science and reason) with
a religious turn of phrase: “I believe that in this way the teacher
always is the prophet of the true God and the usherer in of the
true kingdom of God.”
As strange as it might sound, we live in an era in which the
creed has increasing popularity, especially in teacher education.
For instance, at my former university, it was required that all
undergraduate, pre-service teachers write their own educational creed. his was not meant to be a philosophical statement,
but rather a testimony to one’s individual voice as an emerging
teacher. But if the creed has religious roots, why have we seen
its return in a “secular” age? he popularity of writing creeds in
today’s colleges of education (at least in the US) might very well
have to do with the strangely postmodern logic of the creed.
While there have been any number of scholars attempting to
deine or redeine Dewey’s relation to the postmodern, what I
26
a response
ind fascinating here is how the creed, which is a particularly
Christian technology, can come to be reconigured as a kind of
postmodern pedagogic form that celebrates voices regardless of
critical engagement with the content of the creeds. If the creed
is nothing more than a personal set of beliefs, then how can one
argue against it? Your creed is just as good as my creed. We seem
to ind ourselves in a state of relativism where creeds lourish,
where personal belief triumphs. Everyone in teacher education
must confess their creed, and we should all celebrate the creeds
as statements of individuality. “I believe” overcomes “I argue” or
“I have discovered.”
And as creeds multiply, the commonwealth of the world
withdraws, reducing educational thought to atomized, isolated
confessions of faith. Another way of framing this would be to
say that a creed cannot articulate shared principles to be defended, as Hodgson, Vlieghe, and Zamojski call for. When faced
with opposition, the author of a creed can only say, “Well that is
your opinion. You have your creed, and I have mine.” As such,
the world disappears behind a multiplicity of creeds; dialogue
is replaced by monologue. For these reasons, there is something refreshing about Hodgson, Vlieghe, and Zamojski’s turn
away from the creed to the manifesto. Such a move reorients
educators away from personal, idiosyncratic, and introspective
creeds toward the world of shared principles, dialogue, and the
commons. he struggle with one’s self to articulate a creed is
replaced with a collective struggle over the world and which
principles best care for it.
Another major form of address found in education is the
charter. hese are familiar documents for those in the US, who
have witnessed the rise of the charter school movement. he
charter is composed of fundamental principles that guide the
running of schools. hus, unlike the creed, the charter is collectively oriented. It also has a normative weight not attributed
to creeds. Yet there is a key diference between the charter and
Hodgson, Vlieghe, and Zamojski’s manifesto that should be
pointed out. First, as I have already hinted at, the charter concerns what Hodgson, Vlieghe, and Zamojski refer to as “proce27
manifesto for a post-critical pedagogy
dural normativity.” Stated diferently, the charter is always about
what the school ought to do or what parents and communities
ought to expect. Charters convey normative ideals that communities can then reference in order to determine whether or not a
certain school is living up to its own promises.
Second, charters are written by a legislative or sovereign power, by which an institution is created and its rights, duties, and
privileges deined. As such, it is a binding, formal document that
is guaranteed by a sovereign or legislative body. It is a contract.
he status of the charter is secured by the law, and the security
it ofers is legally binding. What I ind most important about
Hodgson, Vlieghe, and Zamojski’s manifesto is precisely its rejection of any certainty grounded in legislative or sovereign powers. Instead of legal powers, we have recourse to our common
capacities for hermeneutic interpretations. his means that there
are no guarantees; there is no recourse to higher powers over and
above our own capacities for judgment and interpretation.
hird, Hodgson, Vlieghe, and Zamojski’s manifesto is not
institutionally bound. Indeed, the gesture toward the common
and toward the world speaks to a philosophy of education that
cannot be institutionalized without, in some way, privatizing
that which is collective in nature. heir orientation is to the
commonalities of the world that defy any institutional attempt
to control or police. While it might very well be possible to form
charters out of this commonwealth, this need not be the case, as
the commons might challenge the forms of legal and sovereign
powers that bring the charter into existence.
But if the document that Hodgson, Vlieghe, and Zamojski
have written is neither a creed nor a charter, is it really a manifesto? If we think to manifestos in the past, they are certainly
collective in nature, oten describing the commitments of political or artistic or educational movements. hey are also principled. Unlike creeds, they are articulations of positions to be
argued over and debated. And unlike the charter, they are oten
illegal, or extra-legal, challenging a sovereign power that is held
over and above them. I am thinking here of he Manifesto of the
Communist Party written by Marx and Engels. hat manifesto is
28
a response
exemplary in several respects. It is a collective endeavor to articulate not simply a personal set of beliefs but rather the standpoint of a class. It is polemic and, inally, it is illegal, transgressing any state or national laws. In these senses, the document
produced by Hodgson, Vlieghe, and Zamojski does indeed appear to be a manifesto.
Yet at the same time, the manifesto is prophetic, future-oriented, and thus concerned with transformation toward some
kind of alternative future state. hink here of Marx and Engels’
manifesto. Its goal is to forecast certain trends in the ongoing
class war in order to help shape and guide the revolution toward
a post-capitalist state. he manifesto diagnoses, predicts, and ultimately orients us toward a dialectical negation of the present
in the name of a communist future to come. he internal logic
of the manifesto resembles the internal logic of critical pedagogy, hence the reason why the manifesto is the preferred platform
for critical pedagogues such as Henry Giroux and Peter McLaren. To read critical pedagogy is to read manifestos, including
“A Revolutionary Critical Pedagogy Manifesto for the TwentyFirst Century” by Peter McLaren,2 or “When Schools Become
Deadzones of the Imagination: A Critical Pedagogy Manifesto”
by Henry Giroux.3 Such texts are full of proclamations describing what teachers ought to do in order to undermine the system
and help actualize the promise of equality, democracy, and communism in a better tomorrow. As authors, McLaren and Giroux
take on the role of prophets who forecast certain economic and
social trends in order to enrage and inspire protest, all in the
name of critical principles that the critical pedagogue must safeguard. hey are prophets of doom and salvation, both of which
2
3
Matthew Smith, Jean Ryoo, and Peter McLaren, “A Revolutionary Critical
Pedagogy Manifesto for the Twenty-First Century,” Education and Society
27, no. 3 (2009): 59–76.
Henry A. Giroux, “When Schools Become Dead Zones of the Imagination:
A Critical Pedagogy Manifesto,” Policy Futures in Education 12, no. 4 (2014):
491–99. First published August 13, 2013 at truth-out.org, https://www.truthout.org/news/item/18133-when-schools-become-dead-zones-of-the-imagination-a-critical-pedagogy-manifesto.
29
manifesto for a post-critical pedagogy
are always on the horizon, always approaching and receding in
equal measure. Here, hope and doom are synthesized into an
eschatological theory that is always ixated on crisis ater crisis.
In this sense, the manifesto must make manifest that which
is not present, that which is deferred. It does so through the authority of the prophet or seer who can forecast dystopian and
utopian possibilities from the current situation. Interestingly,
we could argue that the prophet takes the creed and makes private beliefs into a kind of charter; this time, a charter guaranteed
by history, or God, or some other transcendent power that only
speaks through the prophet as a chosen emissary.
Yet, on my reading, the document produced by Hodgson,
Vlieghe, and Zamojski rejects not only Giroux and McLaren as
representatives of critical pedagogy, but also, more importantly,
undermines the authority of the prophet as well as the function of the manifesto, which is always oriented away from the
present toward the future. Of course, the collective nature of the
manifesto remains operative, but this is a collectivity that is present, now, and only needs to be veriied rather than conjured up.
As the authors write, the role of a post-critical pedagogy is “not
to debunk but to protect and to care” for what is good in the present. he result is not hope in some kind of future in which freedom, equality, or democracy can be realized, so much as hope in
the present for the freedom, equality, and democracy that exist
but only need veriication. Here, the authors seem to draw inspiration from Jacques Rancière’s interpretation of the masterslave dialectic.4 At the very heart of a relationship that deines
inequality (slavery), Rancière inds a disavowed reliance upon
the equality of intelligences; for how can the slave carry out the
master’s orders if he or she is not already capable of thinking
and speaking? Likewise, the logic of the prophet is rejected as a
stultifying educational position, a position that simultaneously
4
30
Jacques Rancière, The Philosopher and His Poor, ed. Andrew Parker, trans.
John Drury, Corinne Oster, and Andrew Parker (Durham: Duke University
Press, 2004).
a response
(a) is predicated on an equality it disavows, while (b) continually reproducing an inequality that it needs.
In sum, if the manifesto is predicated on the authority of the
prophet to predict a future that is guaranteed by God, or by the
laws of history, then whatever Hodgson, Vlieghe, and Zamojski
have produced cannot be called a manifesto. heir document
does not make manifest in the form of a prediction, so much as
it declares what is present in order to care for it. And this declaration is collective yet poor — poor in the sense that it does not
have the recognition by the law or the sovereign or the prophet
to support it and verify it. If this is a manifesto, then it is an
inoperative one, or a manifesto at a standstill. Such a document
does not tell us what to do, how to do it, or what will happen, so
much as it opens the present to that which remains in potential
and thus undestined for any particular use.
I would thus conclude with the suggestion that what Hodgson, Vlieghe, and Zamojski have produced is properly named
a declaration. hey are declaring that what is contains within
itself a new potentiality that is not reducible to a personal belief,
a legally recognized institutional form, or a prophetic vision of
what is to come. Such a declaration does not tell us what to do,
how to do it, or what will happen, so much as it maintains the
open potentiality of the present for new use. his is what is most
precious and fragile in the present. And for these reasons, potentiality is that which needs the most love.
If the authors simply embrace the form of the manifesto as
their own and use it to articulate a post-critical pedagogy, then
there is a danger that the formal elements deining the manifesto
might return to undermine the content of their argument. I can
see several ways in which the form of the manifesto returns to
contaminate the content of this post-critical declaration. For instance, if the authors want a non-instrumental approach to education that does not submit education as a means to an external
end, perhaps instrumentality returns in the form of responsibility, for it is unclear to me that responsibility is an inherently
educational concept. Indeed, one could make the claim that it is,
irst and foremost, an ethical and political concern, which edu31
manifesto for a post-critical pedagogy
cation helps us strive to achieve. And because of this, a telos is
reintroduced back into the framework. he work of post-critical
philosophy is therefore not to care for what is present so much
as to make manifest that which ought to be. And inally, while
the authors are careful to distinguish between cruel optimism
and hope in the present, I would still suggest that hope is always
oriented toward something to come and thus away from what is
present. he formal features of the manifesto — instrumentality, teleology, and hope — thus seep back into the content of the
document in the shape.
At the same time, there is a danger that if the authors invent
an entirely new form of writing, then they will fail to care for
and love the present. Instead of the present, they would be opting for a kind of avant-garde position where, again, the absent
future is privileged and made manifest through new aesthetic
forms. Such a position thus lies in contradiction with the content of their argument, which wants to remain immanent to the
present without introducing the transcendent.
Yet there is a third path here — a path that is neither the reproduction of the manifesto nor the production of something
new. his is the path of the declaration. he declaration is not
simply a manifesto nor its negation. here is nothing old or new
about the declaration. he declaration is an occupation of the
manifesto in order to deactivate its formal features — instrumentality, teleology, and hope — and thus redeem its declarative
use. Unlike the creed, the declaration is collective. It belongs to
no one in particular. Unlike the charter, it is not bound to the
law or the state for its guarantee. It rejects bureaucratization.
And unlike the manifesto, it is grounded in the present and relects this present back to itself in order to expose that which
remains in potential. Also, it has its own afective qualities. If the
creed concerns religious reverence, the charter concerns respect
for the law, and the manifesto concerns rage and hope for a future, then the declaration concerns joy for what is in the present.
hus, one does not say, “I hope that my teaching will transform
the world.” his is a kind of future-oriented afect that leads to
manifesto writing. Rather one says, “I ind joy in the possibilities
32
a response
of teaching right now.” his is a declaration of the potentiality
that exists all around us.
On my reading, the declaration is a formal occupation of a
space and a time of the manifesto by an alternative space and
time that is most interesting, and in turn most educationally
relevant. Yet when Hodgson, Vlieghe, and Zamojski fail to take
into account the formal structure of their document, the form of
the declaration remains underdeveloped and thus the spontaneous ideology of the manifesto seeps back in to contaminate the
post-critical with the critical, the instrumental, the teleological,
and the hopeful. In this sense, the form must be made into its
own kind of content so that we can begin to understand how
post-critique must take care of and preserve not only concepts
but also modes of presentation.
As such, I would like to see the authors examine the following set of questions:
1. Is there not a need to conceptualize the relationship between
form and content in order to discover forms of writing that
can more adequately express our ideas?
2. Is the manifesto the form of public address most appropriate
to post-critical philosophy of education? Or is there another
form that is present yet occluded here behind the manifesto… something I am calling the declaration?
3. If so, what are the features of the declaration and how can
these formal features come to shape your principles anew?
4. And is there perhaps something inherently educational about
declarations? If creeds come from religion, charters from the
law, and manifestos from politics, ethics, and aesthetics, then
perhaps the authors have hit upon a form that is itself inherently educational, and thus needs to be cared for just as much
as the content of the writing….
hese questions are not meant to merely critique or airm the
project, but rather to love that which is most precious about it:
the potentiality of the form. And it is my argument that this
potentiality has yet to be fulilled and must be cared for. Indeed,
33
it must be protected, for like all emerging forms, it is also at risk
of being lost before it is even recognized.