A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism - Hans-Hermann Hoppe
A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism - Hans-Hermann Hoppe
A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism - Hans-Hermann Hoppe
Socialism and
Capitalism
Economics, Politics,
and Ethics
Hans-Hermann Hoppe
Department of Economics
University of Nevada, Las Vegas
Hoppe, Hans-Hermann.
A theory of socialism and capitalism : economics, politics, and
ethics / by Hans-Hermann Hoppe.
p. cm.
Includes index.
ISBN 0-89838-279-3
1. Socialism. 2. Capitalism. 3. Property 4. Comparative
economics. 5. Comparative government. I. Title.
HX73.H67 1988
3O6'.3»dcl9 88-14066
CIP
Acknowledgments ix
1 Introduction 1
Notes 211
References 259
Index 273
About the Author
Hoppe is the author of Handeln und Erkennen (Bern 1976); Kritik der
kausalwissenschaftlichen Sozialforschung (Opladen 1983); Eigentum,
Anarchie und Staat (Opladen 1987) and numerous articles on philosophy,
economics and the social sciences.
Acknowledgements
But in doing this I will also constantly touch upon and illuminate social
and political problems in the narrower, more common sense of these terms.
In fact, it is one of the major goals of this treatise to develop and explain the
conceptual and argumentative tools, economic and moral, needed to
analyze and evaluate any kind of empirical social or political system, to un-
derstand or appraise any process of social change, and to explain or inter-
pret similarities as well as differences in the social structure of any two or
more different societies.
At the end of the treatise it should be clear that only by means of a theory,
economic or moral, which is not itself derived from experience but rather
deductive way (perhaps using some explicitly introduced empirical and em-
the dark, producing, at best, arbitrary opinions on what might have caused
this or that, or what is better or worse than something else: opinions, that
is, whose opposites can generally be defended as easily as the original posi-
tions themselves (which is to say that they cannot be defended in any strict
sense at all!).
i.e., the overall degree of interference with property rights that exists in a
given country, explains its overall wealth. The more socialist a country, the
more hampered will be the process of production of new and the upkeep of
old, existing wealth, and the poorer the country will remain or become. 1 The
fact that the United States is, by and large, richer than Western Europe, and
West Germany much richer than East Germany can be explained by their
richest country in the world, has now fallen to what is aptly called an under-
INTRODUCTION
developing country.
But the concern here will not be exclusively with the overall wealth ef-
fects, nor with the economic side of the problem alone. For one thing, in
analyzing different types of socialism for which there exist real, historical ex-
amples (examples which, to be sure, very often are not called socialism, but
are given a more appealing name 2 ), it is important to explain why, and in
what way, every intervention anywhere, big or small, here or there, produces
a particular disruptive effect on the social structure which a superficial,
theoretically untrained observer, blinded by an immediate "positive" conse-
quence of a particular intervention, might not perceive. Yet this negative ef-
fect nonetheless exists, and with some delay will cause problems at a
different place in the social fabric more numerous or severe than the ones
originally solved by the initial act of intervening. Thus, for instance, highly
visible positive effects of socialist policies such as "cheap food prices," "low
rents," "free" this and "free" that, are not just positive things hanging in mid-
air, unconnected to everything else, but rather are phenomena that have to
be paid for somehow: by less and lower quality food, by housing shortages,
decay and slums, by queuing up and corruption, and, further, by lower living
standards, reduced capital-formation, and/or increased capital consump-
tion. And a much less conspicuous but almost always "positively" men-
tioned fact-a greater feeling of solidarity among the people, the greater
value attached to things like family, relatives, or friends, which is found to
exist between, for instance, the East Germans as compared to their more
"individualistic," egoistic West/German counterparts-is again not a simple,
isolated, unanalyzable fact. Such feelings are the result of a social system
of constant shortages and of continually repressed opportunities to improve
one's situation by one's own means. In East Germany, in order to ac-
complish the most simple routine tasks, such as a house repair which in
other countries requires no more than a telephone call, you simply must rely
A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
Analyzed in some detail are the particular disruptive effects that are
produced: (1) by a traditional Marxist policy of nationalizing or socializing
the means of production, or rather, by the expropriation of private owners
of means of production; (2) by a revisionist, social-democratic policy of
egalitarian income redistribution; (3) by a conservatively minded policy of
attempting to preserve the status quo through economic and behavioral
regulations and price controls; and (4) by a technocratically minded sys-
tem of pragmatic, piecemeal social and economic engineering and inter-
vention.
These policy types, which will be analyzed sequentially, are not com-
pletely homogeneous and mutually exclusive. Each one can be carried
through to varying degrees, there are different ways of doing things under
each of these categories of policy and the different policy schemes can be
combined to a certain extent. In fact, every given society is a mixture of all
of them as it is the result of diverse political forces which have varied at dif-
ferent times in strength and influence. The reason for analyzing them
separately (apart from the obvious one that not all problems can be dis-
cussed at once) is that they constitute policy schemes associated with clear-
ly distinguishable social groups, movements, parties, etc., and that each
policy scheme affects overall wealth in a somewhat different way.
collapse once it is demonstrated that in fact the opposite is true and it brings
impoverishment, not wealth. Certainly, socialism loses much of its attrac-
tiveness for most people once this is understood. However, it is definitely
not at its argumentative end so long as it can claim-whatever its economic
performance may be-that it represents a higher morality, that it is more just,
that it has an ethically superior foundation.
The reconstruction of the morals of private property and its ethical jus-
tification then leads to a reevaluation of socialism and, as it turns out, the in-
stitution of the state, depending as it does for its very existence on taxation
and forced membership (citizenship), as the very incorporation of socialist
ideas on property. Without any solid economic or moral reasons for their
existence, socialism and the state are then reduced to and will be explained
as phenomena of merely socio-psychological relevance.
Next to the concept of action, property is the most basic category in the
social sciences. As a matter of fact, all other concepts to be introduced in
this chapter-aggression, contract, capitalism and socialism-are definable
in terms of property: aggression being aggression against property, con-
tract being a nonaggressive relationship between property owners,
socialism being an institutionalized policy of aggression against property,
and capitalism being an institutionalized policy of the recognition of proper-
ty and contractual ism.
A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
ize that one's body is indeed the prototype of a scarce good for the use of
which property rights, i.e., rights of exclusive ownership, somehow have to
be established, in order to avoid clashes.
Thus, because of the scarcity of body and time, even in the Garden of
Eden property regulations would have to be established. Without them, and
assuming now that more than one person exists, that their range of action
overlaps, and that there is no preestablished harmony and synchronization
of interests among these persons, conflicts over the use of one's own body
would be unavoidable. I might, for instance, want to use my body to enjoy
drinking a cup of tea, while someone else might want to start a love affair
with it, thus preventing me from having my tea and also reducing the time
left to pursue my own goals by means of this body. In order to avoid such
possible clashes, rules of exclusive ownership must be formulated. In fact,
so long as there is action, there is a necessity for the establ ishment of proper-
ty norms.
While even in a world with only one type of scarce resource all sorts of
norms regulating exclusive ownership with respect to scarce means are
conceivable in principle (for example, a rule such as "On Mondays I deter-
mine to which uses our bodies can be put, on Tuesdays you determine their
use," etc.), it is certain that not all of them would in fact have the same chance
of being proposed and accepted. It then seems to be best to start one's
analysis with the property norm, which would most likely be accepted by
the inhabitants of Eden as the "natural position" regarding the assignment
of rights of exclusive ownership in bodies. To be sure, at this stage of the
argument we are not yet concerned with ethics, with the problem of the
moral justification of norms. Thus, while it can well be admitted from the
very outset that I am indeed going to argue later on that the natural position
PROPERTY, CONTRACT, AGGRESSION, CAPITALISM, SOCIALISM 11
is the only morally defendable one, and while I am also convinced that it is
the natural one because it is morally defendable, at this stage, natural does
not imply any moral connotation. It is simply meant to be a socio-
psychological category used to indicate that this position would probably
find the most support in public opinion. Indeed, its naturalness is reflected
by the very fact that in talking about bodies, it is almost impossible to avoid
using possessive (possession-indicating) expressions as well. A body is
normally referred to as a specific person's body: my body, yours, his, etc.
(and, incidentally, the same is done whenever one speaks of actions!); and
one does not have the slightest problem distinguishing what is mine, yours,
etc.; clearly, in doing so, one is assigning property-titles and distinguishing
between proper owners of scarce resources.
a claim to the right to determine the use of the scarce resource "my body"
would be a claim of nonusers, of nonproducers, and would be based ex-
clusively on subjective opinion, i.e., on a merely verbal declaration that
things should be this or that way. Of course, such verbal claims could (and
very likely always will) point to certain facts, too ("I am bigger, I am smarter,
I am poorer or I am very special, etc.!"), and could thereby try to legitimize
themselves. But facts such as these do not (and cannot) establish any ob-
jective link between a given scarce resource and any particular person(s).
Everyone's ownership of every particular resource can equally well be es-
tablished or excluded on such grounds. It is such property claims, derived
from thin air, with purely verbal links between owners and things owned,
which, according to the natural theory of property, are called aggressive.
As compared with this, my property claim regarding my body can point to
a determinate natural link; and it can do so because my body has been
produced, and everything produced (as contrasted with things "given"),
logically, has a determinate connection with some definite individual
producer(s); it has been produced by me. To avoid any misunderstanding,
'to produce" is not to say "to create out of nothing" (after all, my body is also
a naturally given thing); it means to change a naturally given thing accord-
ing to a plan, to transform nature. It is also not to say 'to transform each
and every part of it" (after all, my body has lots of parts with respect to which
I never did anything!); it means instead to transform a thing within (includ-
ing/excluding) borders, or, even more precisely, to produce borderlines for
things. And finally, "to produce" also is not to say that the process of produc-
tion must go on indefinitely (after all, I am sleeping sometimes, and my body
is certainly not a product of my actions right then!), it simply means that it
was produced in the past and can be recognized as such. It is such proper-
ty claims, then, which can be derived from past, embordering productive ef-
forts and which can be tied to specific individuals as producers, which are
14 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
Even in the land of milk and honey, people evidently could choose dif-
ferent lifestyles, set different goals for themselves, have different standards
as to what kind of personality they want to develop and what achievements
to strive for. True, one would not need to work in order to make a living as
there would be a superabundance of everything. But, put drastically, one
could still choose to become a drunk or a philosopher, which is to say, more
technically, one could choose to put one's body to uses that would be more
or less immediately rewarding from the point of view of the acting person,
or one could put one's body to such uses which would only bear fruit in a
more or less distant future. Decisions of the afore-mentioned type might be
called "consumption decisions." Decisions, on the other hand, to put one's
body to a use that only pays later, i.e., choices induced by some reward or
satisfaction anticipated in a more or less distant future requiring the actor to
overcome disutility of waiting (time is scarce!), might be called "investment"
decisions-decisions, that is, to invest in "human capital," in the capital em-
bodied in one's own physical body. 10 Now assume that aggressively
founded ownership is introduced. Whereas before every person was the
exclusive owner of his body and could decide on his own whether to be-
come a drunk or a philosopher, now a system is established in which a
person's right to determine how to use his body is curtailed or completely
eliminated, and instead, this right is partly or fully delegated to another per-
PROPERTY, CONTRACT, AGGRESSION, CAPITALISM, SOCIALISM 15
son who is not naturally linked to the respective body as its producer. What
would be the consequence of this? The abolition of private ownership of
one's body can be far-reaching: the nonproducers can have the right to
determine all of the uses of "my" body all of the time, or their right to do so
can be restricted with respect to time and/or domains, and these restrictions
again can be flexible (with the nonproducers having the right to change the
restrictive definitions according to their own taste) or fixed once and for all,
and so the effects can, of course, be more or less drastic! But whatever the
degree, socialization of ownership always, and necessarily so, produces
two types of effects. The first effect, "economic" in the narrower sense of
the term, is a reduction in the amount of investment in human capital as
defined above. The natural owner of a body cannot help but make decisions
regarding that body as long as he does not commit suicide and decides to
stay alive, however restricted his ownership rights might be. But since he
can no longer decide on his own, undisturbed by others, to what uses to
put his body, the value attached to it by him is now lower; the want satisfac-
tion, the psychic income, that is to say, which he can derive from his body
by putting it to certain uses is reduced because the range of options avail-
able to him has been limited. But then, with every action necessarily imply-
ing costs (as explained above), and with a given inclination to overcome
costs in exchange for expected rewards or profits, the natural owner is faced
with a situation in which the costs of action must be reduced in order to
bring them back in line with the reduced expected income. In the Garden
of Eden, there is only one way left to do this: by shortening the waiting time,
reducing the disutility of waiting, and choosing a course of action that
promises earlier returns. Thus, the introduction of aggressively founded
ownership leads to a tendency to reduce investment decisions and favors
consumption decisions. Put drastically, it leads to a tendency to turn
philosophers into drunks. This tendency is permanent and more
16 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
pronounced when the threat of intervention with the natural owner's rights
is permanent, and it is less so to the degree that the threat is restricted to
certain times or domains. In any case, though, the rate of investment in
human capital is lower than it would be with the right of exclusive control of
natural owners over their bodies being untouched and absolute.
In short, with these two effects we have already pinpointed the most fun-
damental reasons for socialism's being an economically inferior system of
property arrangements. Indeed, both effects will reappear again and again
in the course of the following analyses of socialist policy schemes. All that
is left now is to explain the natural theory of property as regards the real
world of all around scarcity, for this is the point of departure for all forms of
real socialism.
can never be parted with by the natural owner completely but only be "lent
out" as long as the owners' agreement lasts, naturally all other scarce resour-
ces can be "alienated" and a property title for them can be relinquished once
and for all. 12
It will be the task of the next four chapters to explain how different ways
of deviating from a pure capitalist system, different ways of redistributing
property titles away from natural owners of things (i.e., from people who
have put some particular resources to a specific use and so are naturally
linked to them, and onto people who have not yet done anything with the
resources but who have simply made a verbal, declarative claim regarding
them) lowers investment and increases consumption, and in addition
causes a change in the composition of the population by favoring non-
productive over productive people.
3
SOCIALISM RUSSIAN STYLE
I now want to enlarge and concretize this analysis of socialism and its
most people have come to view as "socialism par excellence" (if not the only
type of socialism there is), this probably being the most appropriate start-
ing point for any discussion of socialism. This "socialism par excellence" is
a social system in which the means of production, that is, the scarce resour-
Indeed, while Karl Marx, and like him most of our contemporary intel-
lectuals of the left, was almost exclusively concerned with the analysis of
the economic and social defects of capitalism, and in all of his writings made
only a few general and vague remarks about the constructive problem of
the organization of the process of production under socialism, capitalism's
allegedly superior alternative, there can be no doubt that this is what he con-
sidered the cornerstone of a socialist policy and the key to a better and more
prosperous future.1 Accordingly, socialization of the means of production
20 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
The second observation is intimately connected with the first and con-
How well-founded this thesis indeed is, and exactly why it is that
economically superior will become clear when one turns away from ap-
parent differences and concentrates on real ones instead, and looks at the
under which this process must now take place: a redistribution away from
people who have forgone possible consumption and instead saved up funds
in order to employ them productively, i.e., for the purpose of producing fu-
ture consumption goods, and who now can no longer do so or who now
redistribution scheme, gain a say, however partial, over the saver's funds.
sarily know today what he will know at a later point in time; that there is a
scarcity of a multitude of goods and that accordingly man is pressed by a
multitude of needs, not all of which he can satisfy at the same time and/or
without sacrificing the satisfaction of other needs; because of this, man must
choose and order his needs in a scale of preferences according to the rank
of urgency that they have for him; also, more specifically, that neither the
process of original appropriation of resources perceived as scarce, nor the
process of production of new and the upkeep of old means of production,
nor the process of contracting, is costless for man; that all of these activities
cost at the very least time, which could be spent otherwise, e.g., for leisure
activities; and in addition one should not forget that one is dealing with a
world characterized by the division of labor, which is to say that one is not
talking about a world of self-sufficient producers, but one in which produc-
tion is carried out for a market of independent consumers.
With this in mind, then, what are the effects of socializing the means of
colloquial sense of the term? There are three intimately related effects.7
First~and this is the immediate general effect of all types of socialism-there
is a relative drop in the rate of investment, the rate of capital formation. Since
of means of production and, mutatis mutandis, raises the costs for users,
producers, and contractors, there will be fewer people acting in the latter
scarcity is realized, there will be less production of new and less upkeep of
old factors of production, and there will be less contracting. For all of these
activities involve costs and the costs of performing them have been raised,
tivities, which at the same time have become relatively less costly, and thus
more open and available to actors. Along the same line, because everyone's
26 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
ly gone, then at least relatively reduced. True, since the caretaker in a so-
cialized economy also cannot privately appropriate the receipts from the
sale of products, but must hand them ove/ to the community of caretakers
at large to be used at their discretion, his incentive to produce and sell
products at all is relatively weakened as well. It is precisely this fact that ex-
plains the lower rate of capital formation. But as long as the caretaker works
and produces at all, his interest in gaining an income evidently exists, even
if it cannot be used for purposes of private capital formation, but only for
private consumption and/or the creation of private, nonproductively used
wealth. The caretaker's inability to sell the means of production, then, im-
plies that the incentive to increase his private income at the expense of capi-
tal value is raised. Accordingly, to the extent that he sees his income
dependent on the output of products produced (the salary paid to him by
the community of caretakers might be dependent on this!), his incentive will
be raised to increase this output at the expense of capital. Furthermore,
since the actual caretaker, insofar as he is not identical with the community
of caretakers, can never be completely and permanently supervised and
thus can derive income from using the means of production for private pur-
poses (i.e., the production of privately used, non- or black-marketed goods)
he will be encouraged to increase this output at the expense of capital value
to the extent that he sees his income dependent on such private produc-
tion. In any case, capital consumption and overuse of existing capital will
occur; and increased capital consumption once more implies relative im-
poverishment, since the production of future exchange goods will, as a con-
sequence, be reduced.
deed important to point out specifically that the above analysis also applies
to the productive factor of labor. With respect to labor, too, socialization im-
plies lowered investment, misallocation, and overutilization. First, since the
owners of labor factors can no longer become self-employed, or since the
opportunity to do so is restricted, on the whole there will be less investment
in human capital. Second, since the owners of labor factors can no longer
sell their labor services to the highest bidder (for to the extent to which the
economy is socialized, separate bidders having independent control over
specific complementary factors of production, including the money needed
to pay labor, and who take up opportunities and risks independently, on
their own account, are no longer allowed to exist!) the monetary cost of
using a given labor factor, or of combining it with complementary factors,
can no longer be established, and hence all sorts of misallocations of labor
will ensue. And third, since the owners of labor factors in a socialized
economy own at best only part of the proceeds from their labor while the
remainder belongs to the community of caretakers, there will be an in-
creased incentive for these caretakers to supplement their private income
at the expense of losses in the capital value embodied in the laborers, so
that an overutilization of labor will result.10
Last, but certainly not least, a policy of the socialization of the means of
production affects the character structure of society, the importance of
which can hardly be exaggerated. As has been pointed out repeatedly,
adopting Russian-type socialism instead of capitalism based on the natural
theory of property implies giving a relative advantage to nonusers, non-
producers, and noncontractors as regards property titles of the means of
production and the income that can be derived from using of these means.
If people have an interest in stabilizing and, if possible, increasing their in-
come and they can shift relatively easily from the role of a user- producer or
contractor into that of a nonuser, nonproducer, or noncontractor-assump-
SOCIALISM RUSSIAN STYLE 31
status, and the like. Accordingly, as people want to improve their income
and want to move into more highly evaluated positions in the hierarchy of
caretakers, they increasingly have to use their political talents. It becomes
irrelevant, or is at least of reduced importance, to be a more efficient
producer or contractor in order to rise in the hierarchy of income recipients.
Instead, it is increasingly important to have the peculiar skills of a politician,
i.e., a person who through persuasion, demagoguery and intrigue, through
promises, bribes, and threats, manages to assemble public support for his
own position. Depending on the intensity of the desire for higher incomes,
people will have to spend less time developing their productive skills and
more time cultivating political talents. And since different people have dif-
fering degrees of productive and political talents, different people will rise to
the top now, so that one finds increasing numbers of politicians everywhere
in the hierarchical order of caretakers. All the way to the very top there will
be people incompetent to do the job they are supposed to do. It is no
hindrance in a caretaker's career for him to be dumb, indolent, inefficient,
and uncaring, as long as he commands superior political skills, and accord-
ingly people like this will be taking care of the means of production
everywhere.11
degree can help illustrate the truth of the above conclusions. Even a super-
ficial acquaintance with these countries suffices to see the validity of the first
that itself would have to be explained by the degree of strictness with which
is clearly much lower than that in the so-called capitalist countries of the
West. (This is true even though the degree to which Western countries are
SOCIALISM RUSSIAN STYLE 33
ter structure, work ethics, divided after Hitler-Germany's defeat in World War
II. In West Germany, more because of lucky circumstances than the pres-
sure of public opinion, a remarkably free market economy was adopted, the
previous system of all-around price controls abolished in one stroke, and
almost complete freedom of movement, trade, and occupation intro-
duced. 15 In East Germany, on the other hand, under Soviet Russian
dominance, socialization of the means of production, i.e., an expropriation
of the previous private owners, was implemented. Two different institution-
al frameworks, two different incentive structures have thus been applied to
the same population. The difference in the results is impressive.16 While
both countries do well in their respective blocs, West Germany has the
highest standard of living among the major West-European nations and East
Germany prides itself in being the most well-off country in the East bloc, the
standard of living in the West is so much higher and has become relatively
more so over time, that despite the transfer of considerable amounts of
money from West to East by government as well as private citizens and in-
creasingly socialist policies in the West, the visitor going from West to East
is simply stunned as he enters an almost completely different, impoverished
world. As a matter of fact, while all of the East-European countries are
plagued by the emigration problem of people wanting to leave for the more
prosperous capitalist West with its increased opportunities, and while they
all have gradually established tighter border controls, thus turning these
countries into sort of gigantic prisoner camps in order to prevent this out-
flow, the case of Germany is a most striking one. With language differen-
ces, traditionally the most severe natural barrier for emigrants, nonexistent,
the difference in living standards between the two Germanys proved to be
so great and emigration from East to West took on such proportions, that
in 1961 the socialist regime in East Germany, in a last desperate step, final-
ly had to close its borders to the West completely. To keep the population
SOCIALISM RUSSIAN STYLE 35
in, it had to build a system the likes of which the world had never seen of
walls, barbed wire, electrified fences, mine fields, automatic shooting
devices, watchtowers, etc., almost 900 miles long, for the sole purpose of
preventing its people from running away from the consequences of Russian-
type socialism.
Besides exemplifying the main point, the case of the two Germanys, be-
cause of its experimental-like character, proves particularly helpful in il-
lustrating the truth of the rest of the theoretically derived conclusions.
Looking at comparable social positions, almost nowhere in West Germany
will one find people working as little, as slowly, or as negligently (while the
working hours, higher in the East, are of course regulated!) as their East
German counterparts. Not, to be sure, because of any alleged differences
in mentality or work ethics, as those are very much the same historically,
but because the incentive to work is considerably reduced by a policy
scheme that effectively closes all or most outlets for private investment. Ef-
fective work in East Germany is most likely to be found in the underground
economy. And in response to the various disincentives to work, and in par-
ticular to work in the "officially" controlled economy, there is also a tenden-
cy among East Germans to withdraw from public life and to stress the
importance of privacy, the family, relatives, and personal friends and con-
nections, significantly exceeding what is seen in the West. 17
Experience also corroborates what has been said about the other side
of the coin: the overutilization of publicly owned means of production. In
West Germany such public goods also exist, and as would be expected,
they are in relatively bad shape. But in East Germany, and no differently or
in fact even worse in the other Soviet-dominated countries, where all factors
of production are socially owned, insufficiently maintained, deteriorating,
unrepaired, rusting, even simply vandalized production factors, machinery,
and buildings are truly rampant. Further, the ecology crisis is much more
dramatic in the East, in spite of the relatively underdeveloped state of the
general economy, than in the West-and all this is not, as the case of Ger-
many proves clearly enough, because there are differences in people's
"natural" inclination to care and to be careful.
where they are still members of the labor force, some as escapees but more
frequently because a sort of ransom has been paid for them, sufficient
material also exists to illustrate the conclusion that in the long run a social-
ized economy will reduce people's productive capacities. Among those
going to the West there is a significant number who led quite normal produc-
tive lives in the East but who, despite the absence of any linguistic and cul-
tural barriers, prove to be incapable of, or have the greatest difficulties,
adapting to Western society with its increased demand for productive and
competitive skills and spirits.
4
SOCIALISM SOCIAL-DEMOCRATIC STYLE
Much more so than any theoretical argument, it has been the disap-
decline in the popularity of orthodox Marxist socialism and has spurred the
will be the concern of this chapter. Both types of socialism, to be sure, derive
least in theory,2 and both have essentially the same ultimate goal: the
ing to his needs." From the very beginnings of the socialist movement in
the methods best suited for achieving these goals. While generally there
40 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
However, this was only the first step in the transformation of the socialist
movement effected by the experience of the Russian revolution. The next
step, as indicated, was forced upon It by the dim experience with Soviet
Russia's economic performance. Regardless of their differing views on the
desirability of revolutionary changes and equally unfamiliar with or unable
or unwilling to grasp abstract economic reasoning, socialists and com-
munists alike could still, during a sort of honeymoon period which they felt
the new experiment deserved, entertain the most illusory hopes about the
economic achievements of a policy of socialization. But this period could
not last forever, and the facts had to be faced and the results evaluated after
some time had elapsed. For every decently neutral observer of things, and
42 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
later for every alert visitor and traveler, It became evident that socialism Rus-
sian-style did not mean more but rather less wealth and that it was a sys-
tem above all, that in having to allow even small niches of private capital
formation, had in fact already admitted its own economic inferiority, if only
implicitly. As this experience became more widely known, and in particular
when after World War II the Soviet experiment was repeated in the East
European countries, producing the very same dim results and thus disprov-
ing the thesis that the Soviet mess was only due to a special Asian mentality
of the people, in their race for public support the socialist, i.e., the social-
democratic and communist, parties of the West were forced to modify their
programs further. The communists now saw various flaws in the Russian
implementation of the socialization program as well, and increasingly toyed
with the idea of more decentralized planning and decision-making and of
partial socialization, i.e., socialization only of major firms and industries, al-
though they never entirely abandoned the idea of socialized production.4
The socialist or social-democratic parties, on the other hand, less sym-
pathetic from the beginning towards the Russian model of socialism and
through their decidedly reformist-democratic policy already inclined to ac-
cept compromises such as partial socialization, had to make a further adap-
tive move. These parties, in response to the Russian and East European
experiences, increasingly gave up the notion of socialized production al-
together and instead put more and more emphasis on the idea of income
taxation and equalization, and, in another move, on equalization of oppor-
tunity, as being the true cornerstones of socialism.
democratic one took place, and still is taking place in all Western societies,
it was not equally strong everywhere. Roughly speaking and only looking
at Europe, the displacement of the old by the new kind of socialism has been
more pronounced, the more immediate and direct the experience with Rus-
SOCIALISM SOCIAL-DEMOCRATIC STYLE 43
sian-type socialism for the population in which the socialist and/or com-
munist parties had to find supporters and voters. Of all the major countries,
in West Germany, where the contact with this type of socialism is the most
direct, where millions of people still have ample opportunities to see with
their own eyes the mischief that has been done to the people in East Ger-
many, this displacement was the most complete. Here, in 1959, the social
democrats adopted (or rather were forced by public opinion to adopt) a new
party program in which all obvious traces of a Marxist past were con-
spicuously absent, that rather explicitly mentioned the importance of private
ownership and markets, that talked about socialization only as a mere pos-
sibility, and that instead heavily stressed the importance of redistributive
measures. Here, the protagonists of a policy of socialization of the means
of production within the social-democratic party have been considerably
outnumbered ever since; and here the communist parties, even when they
are only in favor of peaceful and partial socialization, have been reduced to
insignificance.5 In countries further removed from the iron curtain, like
France, Italy, Spain, and also Great Britain, this change has been less
dramatic. Nonetheless, it is safe to say that today only social-democratic
socialism, as represented most typically by the German social-democrats,
can claim widespread popularity in the West. As a matter of fact, due part-
ly to the influence of the Socialist International-the association of socialist
and social-democratic parties-social-democratic socialism can now be said
to be one of the most widespread ideologies of our age, increasingly shap-
ing the political programs and actual policies not only of explicitly socialist
parties, and to a lesser degree those of the western communists, but also
of groups and parties who would not even in their most far-fetched dreams
call themselves socialists, like the east coast "liberal" Democrats in the
United States.6 And in the field of international politics the ideas of social-
democratic socialism, in particular of a redistributive approach towards the
44 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
so-called North-South conflict, have almost become something like the of-
ficial position among all "well-informed" and "well-intentioned" men; a con-
sensus extending far beyond those who think of themselves as socialists.7
Seen from the point of view of the natural theory of property-the theory
underlying capitalism~the adoption of these rules implies that the rights of
the natural owner have been aggressively invaded. According to this theory
of property, it should be recalled, the user-owner of the means of produc-
tion can do whatever he wants with them; and whatever the outcome of his
SOCIALISM SOCIAL-DEMOCRATIC STYLE 45
usage, it is his own private income, which he can use again as he pleases,
as long as he does not change the physical integrity of someone else's
property and exclusively relies on contractual exchanges. From the
standpoint of the natural theory of property, there are not two separate
processes-the production of income and then, after income is produced,
its distribution. There is only one process: in producing income it is
automatically distributed; the producer is the owner. As compared with this,
socialism social-democratic style advocates the partial expropriation of the
natural owner by redistributing part of the income from production to people
who, whatever their merits otherwise, definitely did not produce the income
in question and definitely did not have any contractual claims to it, and who,
in addition, have the right to determine unilaterally, i.e., without having to
wait for the affected producer's consent, how far this partial expropriation
can go.
private ownership. But then the second rule in principle allows the ex-
propriation of all of the producer's income from production and thus reduces
forced to hand over to society can in fact be quite moderate, this, in prac-
But still, it must be realized that from the standpoint of the nonproducing fel-
With this statement a first step in the analysis that follows has already
been taken. What are the economic, in the colloquial sense of the term, con-
sequences of adopting a system of social-democratic socialism? After what
has just been said, it is probably no longer altogether surprising to hear that
at least as regards the general direction of the effects, they are quite similar
to those of traditional Marxist-type socialism. Still, to the extent that social-
democratic socialism settles for partial expropriation and the redistribution
of producer incomes, some of the impoverishment effects that result from
a policy of fully socializing means of production can be circumvented. Since
these resources can still be bought and sold, the problem most typical of a
caretaker economy-that no market prices for means of production exist and
hence neither monetary calculation nor accounting are possible, with ensu-
ing misallocations and the waste of scarce resources in usages that are at
best of only secondary importance-is avoided. In addition, the problem of
overutilization is at least reduced. Also, since private investment and capi-
tal formation is still possible to the extent that some portion of income from
production is left with the producer to use at his discretion, under socialism
social-democratic style there is a relatively higher incentive to work, to save,
and to invest.
For a long time by far the most popular idea for implementing the general
policy goal of social-democratic socialism was to redistribute monetary in-
come by means of income taxation or a general sales tax levied on
producers. A look at this particular technique shall further clarify our point
and avoid some frequently encountered misunderstandings and miscon-
ceptions about the general effect of relative impoverishment. What is the
economic effect of introducing income or sales taxation where there has
been none before, or of raising an existing level of taxation to a new height? 10
In answering this, I will further ignore the complications that result from the
different possible ways of redistributing tax money to different individuals or
groups of individuals-these shall be discussed later in this chapter. Here
we will only take into account the general fact, true by definition for all
48 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
higher output with an identical input (in terms of costs), or a physically iden-
tical output with a reduced input, then the coincidence of increased taxa-
tion and increased output is anything but surprising. But, to be sure, this
does not at all affect the validity of what has been stated about relative im-
poverishment resulting from taxation.
Another objection that enjoys some popularity is that raising taxes leads
to a reduction in monetary income, and that this reduction raises the mar-
ginal utility of money as compared with other forms of income (like leisure)
and thus, instead of lowering it, actually helps to increase the tendency to
work for monetary return. This observation, to be sure, is perfectly true. But
it is a misconception to believe that it does anything to invalidate the rela-
tive impoverishment thesis. First of all, in order to get the full picture it should
be noted that through taxation, not only the monetary income for some
people (the producers) is reduced but simultaneously monetary income for
other people (nonproducers) is increased, and for these people the mar-
ginal utility of money and hence their inclination to work for monetary return
would be reduced. But this is by no means all that need be said, as this
might still leave the impression that taxation simply does not affect the out-
put of exchangeable goods at ail-since it will reduce the marginal utility of
money income for some and increase it for others, with both effects cancell-
ing each other out. But this impression would be wrong. As a matter of fact,
this would be a denial of what has been assumed at the outset: that a tax
hike, i.e., a higher monetary contribution forced upon disapproving income
producers, has actually taken place and has been perceived as such-and
would hence involve a logical contradiction. Intuitively, the flaw in the belief
that taxation is "neutral" as regards output becomes apparent as soon as
the argument is carried to its ultimate extreme. It would then amount to the
statement that even complete expropriation of all of the producers'
monetary income and the transfer of it to a group of nonproducers would
50 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
not make any difference, since the increased laziness of the nonproducers
resulting from this redistribution would be fully compensated by an in-
creased workaholism on the part of the producers (which is certainly ab-
surd). What is overlooked in this sort of reasoning is that the introduction
of taxation or the rise in any given level of taxation does not only imply favor-
ing nonproducers at the expense of producers, it also simultaneously chan-
ges, for producers and nonproducers of monetary income alike, the cost
attached to different methods of achieving an (increasing) monetary in-
come. For it is now relatively less costly to attain additional monetary in-
come through nonproductive means, i.e., not through actually producing
more goods but by participating in the process of noncontractual acquisi-
tions of goods already produced. Even if producers are indeed more intent
upon attaining additional money as a consequence of a higher tax, they will
increasingly do so not by intensifying their productive efforts but rather
through exploitative methods. This explains why taxation is not, and never
can be, neutral. With (increased) taxation a different legal incentive struc-
ture is institutionalized: one that changes the relative costs of production
for monetary income versus nonproduction, including nonproduction for
leisurely purposes and nonproduction for monetary return, and also versus
production for nonmonetary return (barter). And if such a different incen-
tive structure is applied to one and the same population, then, and neces-
sarily so, a decrease in the output of goods produced for monetary return
must result.11
While income and sales taxation are the most common techniques, they
methods. No matter how the taxes are redistributed to the individuals com-
posing a given society, no matter, for instance, to what extent monetary in-
come is equalized, since these individuals can and do lead different lifestyles
and since they allocate different portions of the monetary income assigned
SOCIALISM SOCIAL-DEMOCRATIC STYLE 51
produce offspring has been lowered and for nonintelligent ones raised.
Given the laws of genetics, the result will be a population that is all in all less
intelligent. And besides, in any case of taxation of natural assets, true for
the example of health as well as for that of intelligence, because monetary
income is taxed, a tendency similar to the one resulting from income taxa-
tion will set in, i.e., a tendency to reduce one's efforts for monetary return
and instead increasingly engage in productive activity for nonmonetary
return or in all sorts of nonproductive enterprises. And, of course, all this
once again reduces the general standard of living.
But this is still not all that has to be said about the consequences of
socialism social-democratic-style, as it will also have remote yet nonethe-
less highly important effects on the social-moral structure of society, which
will become visible when one considers the long-term effects of introducing
redistributive policies. It probably no longer comes as a surprise that in this
regard, too, the difference between Russian-type socialism and socialism
social-democratic style, while highly interesting in some details, is not of a
principal kind.
the degree of taxation rises and the circle of taxed income widens, people
will increasingly develop personalities as inconspicuous, as uniform, and as
mediocre as is possible--at least as far as public appearance is concerned.
At the same time, as a person's income simultaneously becomes depend-
ent on politics, i.e., on society's decision on how to redistribute taxes (which
is reached, to be sure, not by contracting, but rather by superimposing one
person's will on another's recalcitrant one!), the more dependent it be-
comes, the more people will have to politicalize, i.e., the more time and ener-
gy they will have to invest in the development of their special talents for
achieving personal advantages at the expense (i.e., in a noncontractual way)
of others or of preventing such exploitation from occurring.
The difference between both types of socialism lies (only) in the follow-
ing: under Russian-type socialism society's control over the means of
production, and hence over the income produced with them, is complete,
and so far there seems to be no more room to engage in political debate
about the proper degree of politicalization of society. The issue is settled-
just as it is settled at the other end of the spectrum, under pure capitalism,
where there is no room for politics at all and all relations are exclusively con-
tractual. Under social-democratic socialism, on the other hand, social con-
trol over income produced privately is actually only partial, and increased
or full control exists only as society's not yet actualized right, making only
for a potential threat hanging over the heads of private producers. But living
with the threat of being fully taxed rather than actually being so taxed ex-
plains an interesting feature of social-democratic socialism as regards the
general development toward increasingly politicalized characters. It ex-
plains why under a system of social-democratic socialism the sort of
politicalization is different from that under Russian-type socialism. Under
the latter, time and effort is spent nonproductively, discussing how to dis-
tribute the socially owned income; under the former, to be sure, this is also
SOCIALISM SOCIAL-DEMOCRATIC STYLE 55
done, but time and effort are also used for political quarrels over the issue
of how large or small the socially administered income-shares should ac-
tually be. Under a system of socialized means of production where this issue
is settled once and for all, there is then relatively more withdrawal from public
life, resignation, and cynicism to be observed. Social-democratic socialism,
on the other hand, where the question is still open, and where producers
and nonproducers alike can still entertain some hope of improving their posi-
tion by decreasing or increasing taxation, has less of such privatization and,
instead, more often has people actively engaged in political agitation either
in favor of increasing society's control of privately produced incomes, or
against it. 13
But not only is increased political ization stimulated (above and beyond
the level implied by socialism generally) by promoting the idea of equaliz-
ing opportunity. There is once more, and this is perhaps one of the most
interesting features of new social-democratic-socialism as compared with
its traditional Marxist form, a new and different character to the kind of
politicalization implied by it. Under any policy of distribution, there must be
people who support and promote it. And normally, though not exclusively
so, this is done by those who profit most from it. Thus, under a system of
income and wealth-equalization and also under that of a minimum income
policy, it is mainly the "have-nots" who are the supporters of the politicaliza-
tion of social life. Given the fact that on the average they happen to be those
with relatively lower intellectual, in particular verbal capabilities, this makes
for politics which appears to lack much intellectual sophistication, to say the
least. Put more bluntly, politics tends to be outright dull, dumb, and appall-
ing, even to a considerable number of the have-nots themselves. On the
other hand, in adopting the idea of equalizing opportunity, differences in
monetary income and wealth are not only allowed to exist but even become
quite pronounced, provided that this is justifiable by some underlying dis-
crepancies in the opportunity structure for which the former differences help
compensate. Now in this sort of politics the haves can participate, too. As
SOCIALISM SOCIAL-DEMOCRATIC STYLE 59
a matter of fact, being the ones who on the average command superior ver-
bal skills, and the task of defining opportunities as better or worse being es-
sentially one of persuasive rhetorical powers, this is exactly their sort of
game. Thus the haves will now become the dominant force in sustaining
the process of politicalization. Increasingly it will be people from their ranks
that move to the top of the socialist party organization, and accordingly the
appearance and rhetoric of socialist politics will take on a different shape,
becoming more and more intellectualized, changing its appeal and attract-
ing a new class of supporters.
Coming then to more specific observations, there are the recent ex-
periences of Portugal, where in 1974 the autocratic Salazar regime of con-
servative socialism (on this type of socialism see the following chapter),
SOCIALISM SOCIAL-DEMOCRATIC STYLE 61
which had kept Portugal one of the poorest countries in Europe, was sup-
planted in an upheaval by redistributive socialism (with elements of
nationalization) and where since then the standard of living has fallen even
further, literally turning the country into a third world region. There is also
the socialist experiment of Mitterand's France, which produced an im-
mediate deterioration of the economic situation, so noticeable-most con-
spicuous being a drastic rise in unemployment and repeated currency
devaluations-that after less than two years, sharply reduced public support
for the government forced a reversal in policy, which was almost comic in
that it amounted to a complete denial of what only a few weeks before had
been advocated as its dearest convictions.
goods, " thereby allegedly equalizing opportunities and enhancing the over-
all "quality of life." By resorting to a Keynesian policy of deficit spending
and unanticipated inflation, the effects of raising the socially guaranteed min-
imum provisions for nonproducers at the expense of more heavily taxed
producers could be delayed for a few years (the motto of the economic
policy of former West German Chancellor Helmut Schmidt was "rather 5%
inflation than 5% unemployment"). They were only to become more dras-
tic somewhat later, however, as unanticipated inflation and credit expansion
had created and prolonged the over- or rather malinvestment typical of a
boom. As a result, not only was there much more than 5 percent inflation,
but unemployment also rose steadily and approached 10 percent; the
growth of GNP became slower and slower until it actually fell in absolute
terms during the last few years of the period. Instead of being an expand-
ing economy, the absolute number of people employed decreased; more
and more pressure was generated on foreign workers to leave the country
and the immigration barriers were simultaneously raised to ever higher
levels. All of this happened while the importance of the underground
economy grew steadily.
But these were only the more evident effects of a narrowly defined
economic kind. There were other effects of a different sort, which were ac-
tually of more lasting importance. With the new socialist-liberal government
the idea of equalizing opportunity came to the ideological forefront. And as
has been predicted theoretically, it was in particular the official spreading of
the idea mehr Demokratie wagen ("risk more Democracy")--init'ally one of
the most popular slogans of the new (Willy Brandt) era-that led to a degree
of politicalization unheard of before. All sorts of demands were raised in the
name of equality of opportunity; and there was hardly any sphere of life,
from childhood to old age, from leisure to work conditions, that was not ex-
amined intensely for possible differences that it offered to different people
SOCIALISM SOCIAL-DEMOCRATIC STYLE 63
This chapter will show that the same is true of conservatism, because
and all the more so, the more resolutely it is applied. But before going into
socialism, and how it is related to the two egalitarian forms of socialism dis-
cussed previously.
But this partial emancipation from the restrictions and the stagnation of
feudalism was only temporary, and was followed by reaction and decline.
This was due in part to internal weaknesses in the movement of the new
merchant class itself. Still too much ingrained in the minds of men was the
feudal way of thinking in terms of different ranks assigned to people, of sub-
ordination and power, and of order having to be imposed upon men through
coercion. Hence, in the newly emerging commercial centers a new set of
noncontractual regulations and restrictions-now of "bourgeois" origin-was
soon established, guilds that restrained free competition were formed, and
a new merchant oligarchy arose. 5 More important, though, for this reaction-
68 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
ary process was yet another fact. In their endeavor to free themselves from
the exploitative interventions of the various feudal lords, the merchants had
to look for natural allies. Understandably enough, they found such allies
among those from the class of feudal lords who, though comparatively more
powerful than their noble fellows, had the centers of their power at a rela-
tively greater distance from the commercial towns seeking assistance. In
aligning themselves with the merchant class, they sought to extend their
power beyond its present range at the expense of other, minor lords.6 In
order to achieve this goal they first granted certain exemptions from the "nor-
mal" obligations falling upon the subjects of feudal rule to the rising urban
centers, thus assuring their existence as places of partial freedom, and of-
fered protection from the neighboring feudal powers. But as soon as the
coalition had succeeded in its joint attempt to weaken the local lords and
the merchant towns' "foreign" feudal ally had thereby become established
as a real power outside of its own traditional territory, it moved ahead and
established itself as a feudal super power, i.e., as a monarchy, with a king
who superimposed his own exploitative rules onto those of the already ex-
isting feudal system. Absolutism had been born; and as this was nothing
but feudalism on a larger scale, economic decline again set in, the towns
disintegrated, and stagnation and misery returned.7
It was not until the late seventeenth and early eighteenth centuries, then,
that feudalism came under truly heavy attack. This time the attack was more
commerce and industry that had been experienced, and a more intensive
study of Roman and in particular of Natural Law, which had both been redis-
al merchant law and justify it against the competing claims of feudal law,
had led to a sounder understanding of the concept of liberty, and of liberty
as a prerequisite to economic prosperity.8 As these ideas, culminating in
such works as J. Locke's 'Two Treatises on Government," 1688, and A.
Smith's "Wealth of Nations," 1776, spread and occupied the minds of a
steadily expanding circle of people, the old order lost its legitimacy. The old
way of thinking in terms of feudal bonds gradually gave way to the idea of
a contractual society. Finally, as outward expressions of this changed state
of affairs in public opinion, the Glorious Revolution of 1688 in England, the
American Revolution of 1776, and the French Revolution of 1789 came
along; and nothing was the same after these revolutions had occurred. They
proved, once and for all, that the old order was not invincible, and they
sparked new hope for further progress on the road toward freedom and
prosperity.
cumulation reached new heights. While the standard of living did not rise
immediately for everyone, it became possible to support a growing number
of people-people, that is, who only a few years before, under feudalism,
would have died of starvation because of the lack of economic wealth, and
who could now survive. In addition, with population growth leveling off
below the growth rate of capital, now everyone could realistically entertain
the hope of rising living standards being just around the corner. 10
tends to idealize and glorify the old system of feudalism as orderly and
outrightly advocate a return to the prerevolutionary status quo ante and ac-
cepts certain changes, however regretfully, as irreversible. But it is hardly
ruffled when old feudal powers that had lost all or parts of their estates to
the natural owners in the course of the liberalization process are restored to
their old position, and it definitely and openly propagates the conservation
of the status quo, i.e., the given highly unequal distribution of property,
wealth, and income. Its idea is to stop or slow down the permanent chan-
ges and mobility processes brought about by liberalism and capitalism as
completely as possible and, instead, to recreate an orderly and stable so-
cial system in which everyone remains securely in the position that the past
had assigned to him. 13
done according to age-old traditions. What then are the specifically con-
servative elements in present-day societies, and how do they produce rela-
tive impoverishment? With this question, we turn to the systematic analysis
of conservatism and its economic and socio-economic effects. An abstract
characterization of the property rules underlying conservatism and a
description of these rules in terms of the natural theory of property shall
again be the starting point. There are two such rules. First, conservative
socialism, like social-democratic socialism, does not outlaw private proper-
ty. Quite to the contrary: everything»all factors of production and all of the
nonproductively used wealth-can in principle be privately owned, sold,
bought, rented out, with the exception again only of such areas as educa-
tion, traffic and communication, central banking, and security production.
But then secondly, no owner owns all of his property and all of the income
that can be derived from its utilization. Rather, part of this belongs to the
society of present owners and income recipients, and society has the right
to allocate present and future produced income and wealth to its individual
members in such a way that the old, relative distribution of income and
wealth is preserved. And it is also society's right to determine how large or
small the income and wealth-share that is so administered should be, and
what exactly is needed to preserve a given income and wealth-distribution.17
From the perspective of the natural theory of property, the property ar-
of natural owners. Natural owners of things can do whatever they wish with
also gives them the right to reap privately the benefits of increased proper-
that is, that were lucky for them, but which they did not foresee or effectuate.
But at the same time, since according to the principles of the natural theory
of property every natural owner is only protected against physical invasion
and the noncontractual acquisition and transfer of property titles, it also im-
plies that everyone constantly and permanently runs the risk that through
changes in demand or actions which other owners perform with their proper-
ty, property values will fall below their given level. According to this theory,
however, no one owns the value of his property and hence no one, at any
time, has the right to preserve and restore his property values. As compared
with this, conservatism aims precisely at such a preservation or restoration
of values and their relative distribution. But this is only possible, of course,
if a redistribution in the assignment of property titles takes place. Since no
one's property values depend exclusively on one's own actions performed
with one's own property, but also, and inescapably so, on other peoples'
actions performed with scarce means under their own control (and beyond
that of another's), in order to preserve given property values someone-
some single person or some group of persons-would have to rightfully own
all scarce means (far beyond those that are actually controlled or used by
this person or group of persons). Furthermore, this group must literally own
all persons' bodies, since the use that a person makes of his body can also
influence (increase or decrease) existing property values. Thus, in order to
realize the goal of conservatism, a redistribution of property titles must occur
away from people as user-owners of scarce resources onto people who,
whatever their merits as past producers, did not presently use or contrac-
tually acquire those things whose utilization had led to the change in the
given distribution of values.
It has probably become apparent by now that from the point of view of
economic analysis, there is a striking similarity between the socialism of con-
servatism and social-democratic socialism. Both forms of socialism involve
a redistribution of property titles away from producers/contractors onto non-
prod ucers/noncontractors, and both thereby separate the processes of
producing and contracting from that of the actual acquisition of income and
wealth. In doing this, both make the acquisition of income and wealth a
political affair-an affair, that is, in the course of which one (group of) per-
THE SOCIALISM OF CONSERVATISM 77
son(s) imposes its will regarding the use of scarce means onto the will of
other, recalcitrant people; both versions of socialism, though in principle
claiming full ownership of all of the income and wealth produced on behalf
of nonproducers, allow their programs to be implemented in a gradual
fashion and carried through to varying degrees; and both, as a consequence
of all this, must, to the extent that the respective policy is indeed enacted,
lead to relative impoverishment.
The difference between conservatism and what has been termed social-
democratic socialism lies exclusively in the fact that they appeal to different
people or to different sentiments in the same people in that they prefer a dif-
ferent way in which the income and wealth extracted noncontractual^ from
producers is then redistributed to nonproducers. Redistributive socialism
assigns income and wealth to nonproducers regardless of their past
achievements as owners of wealth and income recipients, or even tries to
eradicate existing differences. Conservatism, on the other hand, allocates
income to nonproducers in accordance with their past, unequal income and
wealth-position and aims at stabilizing the existing income distribution and
existing income differentials.18 The difference is thus merely one of social-
psychology: in favoring different patterns of distribution, they grant
privileges to different groups of nonproducers. Redistributive socialism par-
ticularly favors the have-nots among nonproducers, and especially disad-
vantages the haves among the producers; and, accordingly, it tends to find
its supporters mostly among the former and its enemies among the latter.
Conservatism grants special advantages to the haves among the group of
nonproducers and particularly damages the interests of the have-nots
among productive people; and so it tends to find its supporters mainly in
the ranks of the former and spreads despair, hopelessness, and resentment
among the latter group of people.
But although it is true that both systems of socialism are very much alike
78 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
from an economic point of view, the difference between them with respect
to their socio-psychological basis still has an impact on their respective
economics. To be sure, this impact does not affect the general impoverish-
ment effects resulting from the expropriation of producers (as explained
above), which they both have in common. Instead, it influences the choices
that social-democratic socialism on the one hand and conservatism on the
other make among the specific instruments or techniques available for
reaching their respective distributional goals. Social-democratic
socialism's favorite technique is that of taxation, as described and analyzed
in the preceding chapter. Conservatism can use this instrument, too, of
course; and indeed it must make use of it to some extent, if only to finance
the enforcement of its policies. But taxation is not its preferred technique,
and the explanation for this is to be found in the social-psychology of con-
servatism. Dedicated to the preservation of a status quo of unequal posi-
tions of income, wealth, and status, taxation is simply too progressive an
instrument for reaching conservative goals. To resort to taxation means that
one lets changes in the distribution of wealth and income happen first, and
only then, after they have come into existence, does one rectify things again
and restore the old order. However, to proceed in this way not only causes
bad feelings, particularly among those who through their own efforts have
actually improved their relative position first and are then cut back again.
But also, by letting progress occur and then trying to undo it, conservatism
weakens its own justification, i.e., its reasoning that a given distribution of
income and wealth is legitimate because it is the one which has always been
in effect. Hence, conservatism prefers that changes do not occur in the first
place, and it prefers to use policy measures that promise to do just this, or
rather, promise to help make such changes less apparent.
There are three such general types of policy measures: price- controls,
regulations, and behavior controls, all of which, to be sure, are socialistic
THE SOCIALISM OF CONSERVATISM 79
Imposing a minimum price, i.e., a price above the potential market price
below which sales become illegal, mutatis mutandis produces an excess of
supply over demand. There will be a surplus of goods produced that simp-
ly cannot find buyers. And again: this surplus will continue as long as prices
are not allowed to drop along with the reduced demand for the product in
question. Milk and wine lakes, butter and grain mountains, to cite just a few
examples, will develop and grow; and as the storage bins fill up it will be-
come necessary to repeatedly destroy the surplus production (or, as an al-
ternative, to pay the producers not to produce the surplus anymore).
Surplus production will even become aggravated as the artificially high price
attracts an even higher investment of resources in this particular field, which
then will be lacking in other production lines where there is actually a greater
need for them (in terms of consumer demand), and where, as a conse-
quence, product prices will rise.
there are too many (in terms of consumer demand) resources bound up in
production lines of reduced importance and not enough are available in lines
THE SOCIALISM OF CONSERVATISM 81
But this is not all. The preceding analysis also reveals that conservatism
cannot even reach its goal of distributional stability by means of partial price
control. With only partially controlled prices, disruptions in the existing in-
come and wealth position still must occur, as producers in uncontrolled lines
of production, or in lines of production with minimum product prices are
favored at the expense of those in controlled lines, or lines with maximum
product prices. Hence there will continue to be an incentive for individual
producers to shift from one line of production into a different, more profitable
one, with the consequence that differences in the entrepreneurial alertness
and ability to foresee and implement such profitable shifts will arise and
result in disruptions of the established order. Conservatism then, if it is in-
deed uncompromising in its commitment to the preservation of the status
quo, is driven to constantly enlargening the circle of goods subject to price
controls and actually cannot stop short of complete price controls or price-
freezing. 22 Only if the prices of all goods and services, of capital and of con-
sumer goods alike, are frozen at some given level, and the production
process is thus completely separated from demand-instead of disconnect-
82 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
ing production and demand at only a few points or sectors as under partial
price control-does it seem possible to preserve an existing distributional
order in full. Not surprisingly, though, the price that has to be paid for such
full-blown conservatism is even higher than that of only partial price con-
trols. 23 With all-around price control, private ownership of means of produc-
tion is in fact abolished. There can still be private owners in name, but the
right to determine the use of their property and to engage in any contrac-
tual exchange that is deemed beneficial is lost completely. The immediate
consequence of this silent expropriation of producers then will be a reduc-
tion in saving and investing and, mutatis mutandis, an increase in consump-
tion. As one can no longer charge for the fruits of one's labor what the
market will bear, there is simply less of a reason to work. And in addition,
as prices are fixed-independent of the value that consumers attach to the
products in question-there is also less of a reason to be concerned about
the quality of the particular type of work or product that one still happens to
perform or produce, and hence the quality of each and every product will
fall.
But even more important than this is the impoverishment that results
from the allocations! chaos created by universal price controls. While all
product prices, including those of all cost factors and, in particular, of labor
are frozen, the demand for the various products still changes constantly.
Without price controls, prices would follow the direction of this change and
production into more valued ones. Under universal price controls this
mechanism is completely destroyed. Should the demand for a product in-
crease, a shortage will develop as prices are not allowed to rise, and hence,
because the profitability of producing the particular product has not been
quence, excess demand, left unsatisfied, will spill over to other products, in-
THE SOCIALISM OF CONSERVATISM 83
creasing the demand for them above the level that otherwise would have
been established. But here again, prices are not allowed to rise with the in-
creased demand, and again a shortage will develop. And so the process of
shifting demand from most urgently wanted products to products of secon-
dary importance, and from there to products of still lesser relevance, since
again not everyone's attempt to buy at the controlled price can be satisfied,
must go on and on. Finally, since there are no alternatives available and the
paper money that people still have to spend has a lower intrinsic value than
even the least valuable product available for sale, excess demand will spill
over to products for which demand had originally declined. Hence, even in
those lines of production where a surplus had emerged as the consequence
of declining demand but where prices had not been allowed to fall accord-
ingly, sales again will pick up as a consequence of unsatisfied demand else-
where in the economy; in spite of the artificially high fixed price surpluses
will become saleable; and, with profitability thus restored, an outflow of capi-
tal will be prevented even here.
producers can produce anything and the consumers have no choice but to
buy it, whatever it is. Accordingly, any change in the production structure
that is made or ordered to be made without the help offered by freely float-
ing prices is nothing but a groping in the dark, replacing one arbitrary array
vice versa;... indeed of giving them any absurd combination of goods." But,
of course,"... merely giving consumers unbalanced combinations of goods
is itself equivalent to a major decline in production, for it represents just as
much of a loss in human well-being."24 The standard of living does not simp-
ly depend on some total physical output of production; it depends much
more on the proper distribution or proportioning of the various specific
production factors in producing a well-balanced composition of a variety of
consumer goods. Universal price controls, as the 'ultima ratio1 of conser-
vatism, prevent such a well-proportioned composition from being brought
about. Order and stability are only seemingly created; in truth they are a
means of creating allocations chaos and arbitrariness, and thereby drasti-
cally reduce the general standard of living.
Europe and to a somewhat lesser degree in the United States, and while
certain sectors of the economy are indeed already subject to very similar
controls, the most popular and most frequently used conservative-socialist
regulatory instrument is still that of establishing predefined standards for
predefined categories of products or producers to which all innovations
must conform. These regulations lay down the kind of qualifications a per-
son must fulfill (other than the "normal" ones of being the rightful owner of
things and of not damaging the physical integrity of other peoples' proper-
ty through one's own actions) in order to have the right to establish himself
as a producer of some sort; or they stipulate the kinds of tests (as regards,
for instance, materials, appearance, or measurements) a product of a given
type must undergo before being newly allowed on the market; or they
prescribe definite checks that any technological improvement must pass in
order to become a newly approbated method of production. With such
regulatory means innovations can neither be completely ruled out, nor can
it be altogether avoided that some changes might even be quite surprising.
But as the predefined standards to which changes have to conform must of
necessity be "conservative," i.e., formulated in terms of existing products,
producers, or technologies, they serve the purpose of conservatism in that
they will indeed at least slow down the speed of innovative changes and the
range of possible surprises.
In any case, ail these types of regulations, the first mentioned ones more
and the latter less, will lead to a reduction in the general standard of living.25
An innovation, to be sure, can only be successful, and thus allow the in-
is indeed more highly valued by the consumers than the competing old
of property titles away from the innovators and onto the established
ing possible income and wealth gains stemming from innovative changes
in the process of production and mutatis mutandis by fully or partially
socializing the possible losses from not innovating, the process of innova-
tion will be slowed down, there will be fewer innovators and innovations, and
instead, a strengthened tendency will emerge to settle for the way things
are. This means nothing else than that the process of increasing consumer
satisfaction by producing more highly evaluated goods and services in more
efficient, cost-saving ways is brought to a standstill, or is at least hampered.
Thus, even if in a somewhat different way than price controls, regulations
will make the production structure fall out of line with demand, too. And
while this might help safeguard an existing distribution of wealth, it must
once again be paid for by a general decline in the overall wealth that is in-
corporated in this very same production structure.
Any change in the pattern of consumer behavior has its economic side
effects. (If I let my hair grow longer this affects the barbers and the scissors
industry; if more people divorce this affects lawyers and the housing market;
if I start smoking marijuana this has consequences not only for the use of
agricultural land but also for the ice cream industry, etc.; and above all, all
such behavior disequilibrates the existing value system of whoever happens
to feel affected by it.) Any change could thus appear to be a disruptive ele-
ment vis a vis a conservative production structure, conservatism, in prin-
ciple, would have to consider all actions-the whole lifestyle of people in their
roles as individual consumers or noncommercial exchangers as proper ob-
jects of behavioral controls. Full-blown conservatism would amount to the
establishment of a social system in which everything except the traditional
way of behaving (which is explicitly allowed) is outlawed. In practice, con-
THE SOCIALISM OF CONSERVATISM 89
servatism could never go quite this far, as there are costs connected with
controls and as it would normally have to reckon with rising resistance in
the public opinion. "Normal" conservatism, then, is characterized instead
by smaller or greater numbers of specific laws and prohibitions which out-
law and punish various forms of nonaggressive behavior of isolated con-
sumers, or of people engaging in noncommercial exchanges-of actions,
that is to say, which if indeed performed, would neither change the physical
integrity of anyone else's property, nor violate anyone's right to refuse any
exchange that does not seem advantageous, but which would rather (only)
disrupt the established "paternal" order of social values.
Once again the effect of such a policy of behavioral controls is, in any
case, relative impoverishment. Through the imposition of such controls not
only is one group of people hurt by the fact that they are no longer allowed
to perform certain nonaggressive forms of behavior but another group
benefits from these controls in that they no longer have to tolerate such dis-
liked forms of behavior. More specifically, the losers in this redistribution of
property rights are the user-producers of the things whose consumption is
now hampered, and those who gain are nonusers/nonproducers of the con-
sumer goods in question. Thus, a new and different incentive structure
regarding production or nonproduction is established and applied to a given
population. The production of consumer goods has been made more cost-
ly since their value has fallen as a consequence of the imposition of controls
regarding their use, and, mutatis mutandis, the acquisition of consumer
satisfaction through nonproductive, noncontractual means has been made
relatively less costly. As a consequence, there will be less production, less
saving and investing, and a greater tendency instead to gain satisfaction at
the expense of others through political, i.e., aggressive, methods. And, in
particular, insofar as the restrictions imposed by behavioral controls con-
cern the use that a person can make of his own body, the consequence will
90 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
human capital.
With this we have reached the end of the theoretical analysis of conser-
vatism as a special form of socialism. Once again, in order to round out the
discussion a few remarks which might help illustrate the validity of the above
conclusions shall be made. As in the discussion of social-democratic
socialism, these illustrative observations should be read with some precau-
tions: first, the validity of the conclusions reached in this chapter has been,
can, and must be established independent of experience. And second, as
far as experience and empirical evidence are concerned, there are unfor-
tunately no examples of societies that could be studied for the effects of
conservatism as compared to the other variants of socialism and capitalism.
There is no quasi-experimental case study which alone could provide one
with what is normally considered "striking" evidence. Reality is rather such
that all sorts of policy measures-conservative, social-democratic, Marxist-
socialist, and also capitalist-liberal-are so mixed and combined, that their
respective effects cannot usually be neatly matched with definite causes,
but must be disentangled and matched once more by purely theoretical
means.
With this in mind, though, something might well be said about the ac-
tual performance of conservatism in history. Once more, the difference in
the living standards between the United States and the countries of Western
Europe (taken together) permits an observation that fits the theoretical pic-
ture. Surely, as mentioned in the previous chapter, Europe has more
redistributive socialism-as indicated roughly by the overall degree of taxa-
tion-than the United States, and is poorer because of this. But more strik-
ing still is the difference that exists between the two with respect to the
degree of conservatism.26 Europe has a feudal past that is noticeable to
this very day, in particular in the form of numerous regulations that restrict
THE SOCIALISM OF CONSERVATISM 91
ly broken with their feudal past. I n these societies, vast parts of the economy
are even now almost completely exempt from the sphere and the pressure
of freedom and competition and are instead locked in their traditional posi-
tion by regulatory means, enforced, as it were, by outright aggression.
On the level of more specific observations the data also clearly indicate
what the theory would lead one to expect. Returning to Western Europe,
there can be little doubt that of the major European countries, Italy and
France are the most conservative, especially if compared with the northern
nations which, as far as socialism is concerned, have been leaning more
toward its redistributive version. 28 While the level of taxation in Italy and
France (state expenditure as part of GNP) is not higher than elsewhere in
Europe, these two countries clearly exhibit more conservative-socialist ele-
ments than can be found anywhere else. Both Italy and France are studded
with literally thousands of price controls and regulations, making it highly
doubtful that there is any sector in their economies that can be called "free"
with some justification. As a consequence (and as could have been
predicted), the standard of living in both countries is significantly lower than
that of northern Europe, as anyone who is not traveling exclusively in resort
towns cannot fail to notice. In both countries, to be sure, one objective of
conservatism seems to have been reached: the differences between the
haves and the have-nots have been well-preserved-one will hardly find as
extreme income and wealth differentials in West Germany or the United
States as in Italy or France-but the price is a relative drop in social wealth.
As a matter of fact, this drop is so significant that the standard of living for
the lower and lower-middle class in both countries is at best only a bit higher
than that in the more liberalized countries of the East bloc. And the southern
provinces of Italy, in particular, where even more regulations have been piled
on top of those valid everywhere in the country, have just barely left the
camp of the third world nations.
THE SOCIALISM OF CONSERVATISM 93
Experience, too, supports this. By and large, living standards in the East
European countries are significantly lower than in Western Europe, where
the degree to which the socialization of means of production that has taken
place, though certainly remarkable, is relatively much lower. Also, wherever
one extends the degree of redistribute measures and the proportion of
96 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
Nonetheless, socialism is very much alive and well, even in the West
powerful ideologies. How could this come about? One important factor is
that its adherents abandoned the original idea of socialism's economic su-
claim will be considered in Chapter 7. But that is certainly not the end of the
story. Socialism has even regained strength in the field of economics. This
became possible because socialism combined its forces with the ideology
methodology of the twentieth century, not only in the field of the natural
sciences but also in the social sciences and economics. This applies not
cidentally, have since freed themselves from the spell of empiricism and
positivism) but probably even more so to the practitioners (who are still very
positivism, which includes for our purposes the so-called critical rationalism
of K. R. Popper and his followers, socialism developed into what will hence-
THE SOCIALISM OF SOCIAL ENGINEERING 97
THE FOUNDATIONS OF ECONOMIC ANALYSIS
able to provide reasons why all the arguments given so far have failed to be
decisive; it must try to prove how one can avoid drawing the conclusions
that I have drawn and still claim to be rational and to operate in accordance
with the rules of scientific inquiry. But how, in detail, can this be ac-
seemingly plausible arguments. The first and indeed the most central of its
perience is always of such a type that it could, in principle, have been other
than it actually was so that no one could ever know in advance, i.e., before
one way or another. If, mutatis mutandis, knowledge is not verifiable or fal-
sifiable by experience, then it is not knowledge about anything real-empiri-
cal knowledge, that is--but simply knowledge about words, about the use
of terms, about signs and transformational rules for them-or analytical
knowledge. And it is highly doubtful that analytical knowledge should be
ranked as "knowledge" at all.
If one assumes this position, as I will do for the moment, it is not dif-
ficult to see how the above arguments could be severely rebuffed. The ar-
guments regarding the impossibility of economic calculation and the
cost-raising character of social-democratic or conservative measures
necessarily leading to a decline in the production of goods and services and
hence to reduced standards of living evidently claimed to be valid a priori,
i.e., not falsifiable by any kind of experience, but rather known to be true
prior to any later experiences. Now if this were indeed true, then according
to the first and central tenet of empiricism-positivism, this argument could
not contain any information about reality, but instead would have to be con-
sidered idle verbal quibbling-an exercise in tautological transformations of
words such as "cost," "production," "output of production," "consumption"-
-which do not say anything about reality. Hence, empiricism concludes that
insofar as reality, i.e., the real consequences of real socialism, is concerned,
the arguments presented thus far carry no weight whatsoever. Rather, in
order to say anything convincing about socialism, experience and ex-
perience alone would have to be the decisive thing to consider.
If this were indeed true (as I will still assume), it would at once dispose
have to face up to the real experiences with real socialism and wouldn't the
result of this be just as decisive? In the preceding chapters, much more em-
THE SOCIALISM OF SOCIAL ENGINEERING 99
THE FOUNDATIONS OF ECONOMIC ANALYSIS
fact that Marshall aid had streamed into West Germany while East Germany
had to pay reparations to the Soviet Union; or by the fact that from the very
beginning, East Germany encompassed Germany's less developed, rural,
agricultural provinces and so had never had the same starting point; or that
in the eastern provinces the tradition of serfdom had been discarded much
later than in the western ones and so the mentality of the people was indeed
different in both East and West Germany, etc.
sible disturbing influence from the outset without indeed trying it out and
controlling it. Not even the seemingly most absurd and ridiculous variables,
such as, for instance, differences in weather, or a fly passing by in one case
but not in the other, could be ruled out in advance; all that could be done
would be to point to experience again. ("Flies passing or not passing by
never made a difference for the outcome of an experiment.") But accord-
ing to the empiricist doctrine itself, this experience, referring as it does only
to past instances, would once again not help decide the matter definitively,
and a reference to it would only amount to a begging of the question.
No matter what the charges brought against socialism are, then, as long
as they are based on empirical evidence the empiricist-socialist could argue
that there is no way of knowing in advance what the results of a certain policy
scheme will be without actually enacting it and letting experience speak for
itself. And whatever the observable results are, the original socialist idea-
the "hard-core" of one's "research programme" as the neo-Popperian
philosopher Lakatos would have called it 6 ~can always be rescued easily by
pointing out some previously neglected, more or less plausible variable,
whose noncontrol is hypothesized to be responsible for the negative result,
with the newly revised hypothesis again needing to be tried out indefinitely,
ad infinitum.7 Experience only tells us that a particular socialist policy
scheme did not reach the goal of producing more wealth; but it can never
tell us if a slightly different one will produce any different results, or if it is
possible to reach the goal of improving the production of wealth by any
socialist policy at all.
itself must at least implicitly assume and presuppose the existence of non-
empirical knowledge as knowledge about reality. This being mainly a
destructive task, I will then have to address the question of how it is possible
to have or conceive of knowledge that informs about reality, but which is
not itself subject to confirmation or falsification by experience. And thirdly,
I will show that such knowledge not only is conceivable and must be presup-
posed but that there are positive instances of it which serve as the firm epis-
temological foundation on which the economic case against socialism can
be and indeed all along has been built.
However, this is not all that can be mustered against empiricism, even
if the second available alternative is chosen. Upon closer inspection this es-
cape route leads to another trap of self-defeat. Even if this route were
two or more events has been found to fit one particular instance of experien-
ask oneself what is the presupposition which must be made in order to re-
late the second instance of experience to the first as either confirming or fal-
106 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
sifying it? At first it might seem almost self-evident that if in the second in-
stance of experience the observations of the first were repeated, this would
be a confirmation, and if not, a falsification-and clearly, the empiricist
methodology assumes this to be evident, too, and does not require further
explanation. But this is not true. 12 Experience, it should be noted, only
reveals that two or more observations regarding the temporal sequence of
two or more types of events can be "neutrally" classified as "repetition" or
"nonrepetition." A neutral repetition only becomes a "positive" confirmation
and a nonrepetition a "negative" falsification if, independent of what can ac-
tually be discovered by experience, it is assumed that there are constant
causes which operate in time-invariant ways. If, contrary to this, it is as-
sumed that causes in the course of time might operate sometimes this way
and sometimes that way, then these repetitive or nonrepetitive occurrences
simply are and remain neutrally registered experiences, completely inde-
pendent of one another, and are not in any way logically related to each
other as confirming or falsifying one another. There is one experience and
then there is another, they are the same or they are differ ent, but that is all
there is to it; nothing else follows.
if this is not indeed the case, something must be at fault with the particular
specification of causes.
On the positive side, the most important notion for understanding the
THE SOCIALISM OF SOCIAL ENGINEERING 109
THE FOUNDATIONS OF ECONOMIC ANALYSIS
possibility of a priori knowledge, I submit, is that there are not only nature-
given things which one has to learn about through experience, but that there
are also artificial, man-made things which may require the existence or use
of natural materials, but which to the very extent that they are constructs
can nonetheless not only be fully understood in terms of their structure and
implications, but which also can be analyzed for the question of whether or
not their method of construction can conceivably be altered. 14
There are three major fields of constructs: language and thought, ac-
tions, and fabricated objects, all of which are man-made things. We shall
not deal here with fabricated objects but will only mention in passing that
Euclidean geometry, for instance, can be conceived of as ideal norms we
cannot avoid using in constructing measurement instruments that make em-
pirical measurements of space possible. (In so far, then, Euclidean
geometry cannot be said to have been falsified by the theory of relativity;
rather, this theory presupposes its validity through the use of its instruments
of measuring.)15 The field of action, as our area of main concern, will be
analyzed when the aprioristic foundations of economics are discussed. The
first explanation of aprioristic knowledge, then, as knowledge of rules of con-
struction which cannot conceivably be altered, shall be given using the ex-
ample of language and thought. This is chosen as the starting point,
because it is language and thought which one uses in doing what is being
done here, that is, in communicating, discussing, and arguing.
With this in mind we can turn to the field of action in order to prove the
specific point that one also has positive, aprioristic knowledge of actions
and consequences of actions because actions, too, are man-made con-
112 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
act on the basis of this knowledge. Rather, one can only reconstruct the
causes of one's actions after the event, as one can only explain one's
knowledge after one already possesses it. Thus, the empiricist methodol-
ogy applied to the field of knowledge and action, which contains knowledge
as its necessary ingredient, is simply contradictory~a logical absurdity.18
The constancy principle may be correctly assumed within the sphere of
natural objects and as such the methodology of empiricism may be ap-
plicable there, but with respect to actions, any attempt at causal empirical
explanation is logically impossible, and this, which is definitely knowledge
about something real, can be known with certainty. Nothing can be known
a priori about any particular action; but a priori knowledge exists regarding
actions insofar as they are actions at all. It can be known a priori that no ac-
tion can be conceived of as predictable on the basis of constantly operat-
ing causes.
After what has been said about causality, it should indeed be easy to
see that it is a produced rather than a given feature of reality. One does not
experience and learn that there are causes which always operate in the same
114 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
way and on the basis of which predictions about the future can be made.
Rather, one establishes that phenomena have such causes by following a
particular type of investigative procedure, by refusing on principle to allow
any exceptions, i.e., instances of inconstancy, and by being prepared to
deal with them by producing a new causal hypothesis each time any such
an apparent inconstancy occurs. But what makes this way of proceeding
necessary? Why does one have to act this way? Because behaving this
way is what performing intentional actions is; and as long as one acts inten-
tionally, presupposing constantly operating causes is precisely what one
does. Intentional acts are characterized by the fact that an actor interferes
in his environment and changes certain things, or prevents them from
changing, and so diverts the "natural" course of events in order to achieve
a preferred result or state of affairs; or should an active interference prove
impossible, that he prepares himself for a result he cannot do anything about
except anticipate in time, by watching out for temporally prior events which
indicate the later result. In any case, in order to produce a result that other-
wise would not have happened, or to be able to adapt to an inevitable result
that otherwise would have come as a complete surprise, the actor must
presuppose constantly operating causes. He would not interfere if he did
not assume this would help bring about the desired result; and he would not
prepare for and adjust to anything unless he thought the events on whose
basis he began his preparations were indeed the constantly operating
causal forces that would produce the result in question, and the preparation
taken would indeed lead to the goal desired. Of course, an actor could go
wrong with respect to his particular assumptions of cause-and-effect rela-
tions and a desired result might not come about in spite of the interference,
or an anticipated event for which preparations had been made might fail to
occur. But no matter what happens in this respect, whether or not the results
conform to the expectations, whether or not actions regarding some given
THE SOCIALISM OF SOCIAL ENGINEERING 115
THE FOUNDATIONS OF ECONOMIC ANALYSIS
result or event are upheld for the future, any action, changed or unchanged,
presupposes that there are constantly operating causes even if no particular
cause for a particular event can be pre-known to any actor at any time. In
fact, disproving that any natural phenomenon is governed by time-invariant-
ly operating causes would require one to show that given phenomenon can-
not be anticipated or produced on the basis of antecedent variables. But
clearly, trying to prove this would again necessarily presuppose that the oc-
currence or nonoccurrence of the phenomenon under scrutiny could be ef-
fected by taking appropriate action and that the phenomenon must thus
assumedly be embedded in a network of constantly operating causes.
Hence, one is forced to conclude that the validity of the constancy principle
cannot be falsified by any action as any action would have to presuppose
it. 19 (There is only one way in which it might be said that "experience" could
"falsify" the constancy principle: if the physical world were indeed so chaotic
that one could no longer act at all, then of course it would not make much
sense to speak of a world with constantly operating causes. But then human
beings, whose essential characteristic is to act intentionally, would also no
longer be the ones who experience this inconstancy. As long as one sur-
vives as a human being-and this is what the argument in effect says-the
constancy principle must be assumed to be valid a priori, as any action must
presuppose it and no experience that anyone could actually have could pos-
sibly disprove this.) 20
fact, one can observe things in an order that is exactly the opposite of the
real temporal order in which they stand to each other. That one knows how
to interpret observations in a way that might deviate from and correct on the
temporal order in which they were made and can even locate events in ob-
jective time requires that the observer be an actor and know what it means
to produce or prepare for some result.21 Only because one is an actor, and
experiences are those of an acting person, can events be interpreted as oc-
curring earlier and later. And, one cannot know from experience that ex-
periences must be interpreted with reference to actions, as the performance
of any action already presupposes the possession of experiences inter-
preted this way. No person who did not know what it means to act could
ever experience events placed in real time, and hence the meaning of time
must be assumed to be known a priori to any actor because of the fact that
he is an actor.
more, since in order to achieve his most highly valued goal any actor must
interfere at an earlier point in time or must watch out for an earlier event in
order to start preparations for some later occurrence, every action must also
employ means (at least those of the actor's own body and the time absorbed
by the interference or the preparations) to produce the desired end. And as
these means are assumed to be causally necessary for achieving the valued
goal, otherwise the actor would not employ them, value must also be placed
on them. Not only the goals, then, have value for an actor, but the means
do, too-a value that is derived from that of the desired end, as one could
not reach an end without employing some means. In addition, as actions
can only be performed sequentially by an actor, every action involves
making a choice. It involves taking up that course of action which at the
moment of acting promises the most highly valued result to the actor and
hence is given preference by him; at the same time it involves excluding
other possible actions with expected results of a lesser value. As a conse-
quence of having to choose whenever one acts--of not being able to realize
all valued goals simultaneously--the performance of each and every action
implies the incurrence of costs. The cost of an action is the price that must
be paid for having to prefer one course of action over another, and it
amounts to the value attached to the most highly valued goal that cannot
be realized or whose realization must now be deferred, because the means
necessary to produce it are bound up in the production of another, even
more highly valued end. And while this implies that at its starting point every
action must be considered to be worth more than its costs and able to secure
a profit to the actor, i.e., a result whose value is ranked higher than the costs,
every action is also threatened by the possibility of a loss. Such a loss would
occur if in retrospect an actor found that-contrary to his own previous ex-
pectation»the result in fact had a lower value than that of the relinquished
alternative. And just as every action necessarily aims at a profit, the pos-
118 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
and the results aimed for cannot be produced successfully or the events for
which they were produced do not occur; or he can go wrong because every
action takes time to complete and the value attached to different goals can
change in the meantime, making things less valuable now that earlier ap-
After this rather lengthy digression into the field of epistemology, let us
now return to the discussion of the socialism of social engineering. This
digression was necessary in order to refute the claim of empiricism-
positivism, which if true would have saved socialism, that nothing categori-
cal can be said against any policy-scheme, as only experience can reveal
the real consequences of certain policies. Against this I have pointed out
that empiricism clearly seems to contradict intuition. According to intuition,
logic is more fundamental than experience and it is also knowledge about
real things. Furthermore, empiricism-positivism turns out to be self-con-
tradictory, as it itself must presuppose the existence of a priori knowledge
as real knowledge. There indeed exists a stock of positive a priori
knowledge which must be presupposed of every experiencing and acting
person, because he knows what it means to act, and which cannot possib-
ly be refuted by experience, as the very attempt to do so would itself presup-
pose the validity of what had been disputed.
follows: "Experience does not beat logic, but rather the opposite is true."
Logic improves upon and corrects experience and tells us what kind of ex-
periences we can possibly have and which ones are instead due to a mud-
dled mind, and so would be better labeled "dreams" or "fantasies" rather than
of the foundations on which the economic case against socialism has been
social engineering can never be reached by its proposed means, since this
now be brief, as the ideology of social engineering, apart from its empiricist-
from the other versions of socialism. Hence, the analyses provided in the
This becomes clear once the property rules of the socialism of social
engineering are stated. First, the user-owners of scarce resources can do
whatever they want with them. But secondly, whenever the outcome of this
process is not liked by the community of social engineers (people, that is,
who are not the user-owners of the things in question and who do not have
a contractually acquired title to them), it has the right to interfere with the
practices of the actual user-owners and determine the uses of these means,
thereby restricting their property rights. Further, the community of social
engineers has the right to determine unilaterally what is or is not a preferred
outcome, and can thus restrict the property rights of natural owners when-
ever, wherever, and to the extent that it thinks necessary in order to produce
a preferred outcome.
natural owners, since the degree to which their rights can be curtailed is to
ciple abolished and peoples' productive enterprises take place under the
order~the socialism of social engineering does not have any such design.
In any case, since the socialism of social engineering does not differ in
principle from any of the other versions of socialism, in that it implies a
redistribution of property titles away from the users and contractors of
scarce resources and onto nonusers and noncontractors, it, too, raises the
cost of production and so leads to a reduction in the production of wealth;
and this is necessarily so and no one need try it out first to reach this con-
clusion. This general conclusion is true regardless of the specific course
social engineering might take. Let us say that the community of social en-
gineers does not approve of some people having a low income and so
decides to fix minimum wages above the current market level. 24 Logic tells
one that this implies a restriction of the property rights of the employers as
well as the employees who are no longer allowed to strike certain kinds of
mutually beneficial bargains. The consequence is and must be unemploy-
ment. Instead of getting paid at a lower market wage, some people now will
not get paid at all, as some employers cannot pay the additional costs or
hire as many people as they would be willing to hire at lower costs. The
employers will be hurt as they can only employ fewer people and the out-
put of production hence will be lower, in relative terms; and the employees
will be hurt, as instead of some income, albeit low, they now have no in-
come. It cannot be stated a priori who of the employees and the employers
will suffer most from this, except that it will be those of the former whose
THE SOCIALISM OF SOCIAL ENGINEERING 123
THE FOUNDATIONS OF ECONOMIC ANALYSIS
specific labor services have a relatively low value on the market, and those
of the latter who specifically hire precisely this type of labor. However, know-
ing from experience, for instance, that low-skilled labor services are par-
ticularly frequent among the young, among blacks, among women, among
older people who want to reenter the labor force after a longer period of
household-work, etc., it can be predicted with certainty that these will be the
groups hit the hardest by unemployment. And to be sure, the very fact that
the problem which intervention was originally supposed to cure (the low in-
come of some people) is now even worse than before could have been
known a priori, independent of any experience! To think that, misled by faul-
ty empiricist methodology, all this first has to be tried out as it otherwise
could not have been known is not only scientific humbug; like all acting
based on ill-conceived intellectual foundations, it is extremely costly as well.
it still would not pay to construct new apartments. In addition, the increased
shortages would result in very costly inflexibilities, as people who had hap-
pily gotten into one of the low-priced apartments would be increasingly un-
willing to move out again, in spite of the fact that, for instance, the family size
normally changes during the life cycle and so different needs as regards
housing emerge, and in spite of the fact that different job opportunities might
appear at different places. And so a huge waste of rental space occurs, be-
cause old people, for example, who occupy large apartments that were just
the right size when the children were still living at home but are much too
big now, still will not move into smaller apartments as there are none avail-
able; and young families who are in need of larger premises cannot find
those either, precisely because such places will not be vacated. Waste also
occurs because people do not move to the places where there is the greatest
demand for their specific labor services, or they spend large amounts of
time commuting to rather distant places, merely because they cannot find
a place to live where there is work for them, or they can only find accom-
modations at a much higher price than their presently fixed low rent. Clear-
ly, the problem that the social engineers wanted to solve by means of
introducing rent control legislation is much worse than before and the
general standard of living, in relative terms, has declined. Once again, all of
this could have been known a priori. For the social engineer, however,
misled by an empiricist-positivist methodology which tells him that there is
noway of knowing results unless things are actually tried out, this experience
will probably only set the stage for the next intervention. Perhaps the results
were not exactly as expected because one had forgotten to control some
other important variable, and one should now go ahead and find out. But
as this chapter has demonstrated, there is a way of knowing in advance that
neither the first nor any subsequent acts of intervention will ever reach their
goal, as they all imply an interference with the rights of the natural owners
THE SOCIALISM OF SOCIAL ENGINEERING 125
THE FOUNDATIONS OF ECONOMIC ANALYSIS
socialism can be made because of the moral value of its principles and,
mutatis mutandis, that capitalism cannot be defended morally; and (2) the
claim of empiricist socialism that normative statements ("should" or "ought"
statements)-since they neither solely relate to facts, nor simply state a ver-
bal definition, and thus are neither empirical nor analytical statements-are
not really statements at all, at least not statements that one could call "cog-
nitive" in the widest of all senses, but rather mere "verbal expressions" used
to express or arouse feelings (such as "wow" or "grrrrr").1
The second, empiricist or, as its position applied to the field of morals
is called, "emotivist" claim will be dealt with first, as in a way it is more far-
and analytical statements is of an all-inclusive nature; that is, that any state-
quibble, saying nothing about anything real, but rather only defining one
sound by another, and emotivism would thus be a void doctrine. If, instead,
it is empirical, then the doctrine would not carry any weight, as its central
proposition could well be wrong. In any case, right or wrong, it would only
soever why this would have to be the case in the future, too, and hence why
one should or rather should not look for normative statements that are more
the emotivist doctrine would also lose all its weight if it adopted the third al-
THE ETHICAL JUSTIFICATION OF CAPITALISM 129
WHY SOCIALISM IS MORALLY INDEFENSIBLE
ternative and declared its central tenet itself a "wow" statement, too. For if
this were the case, then it would not contain any reason why one should re-
late to and interpret certain statements in certain ways, and so if one's own
instincts or feelings did not happen to coincide with somebody else's
"wowing," there would be nothing that could stop one from following one's
own feelings instead. Just as a normative statement would be no more than
the barking of a dog, so the emotlvist position then is no more than a bark-
ing comment on barking.
truth claims are raised and decided upon in argumentation and that ar-
Hence, one reaches the conclusion that norms must indeed be as-
sumed to be justifiable as valid. It is simply impossible to argue otherwise,
because the ability to argue so would in fact presuppose the validity of those
THE ETHICAL JUSTIFICATION OF CAPITALISM 131
WHY SOCIALISM IS MORALLY INDEFENSIBLE
Clearly then, the universalization principle alone would not provide one
with any positive set of norms that could be demonstrated to be justified.
However, there are other positive norms implied in argumentation aside
from the universalization principle. In order to recognize them, it is only
necessary to call three interrelated facts to attention. First, that argumenta-
tion is not only a cognitive but also a practical affair. Second, that argumen-
tation, as a form of action, implies the use of the scarce resource of one's
body. And third, that argumentation is a conflict-free way of interacting. Not
in the sense that there is always agreement on the things said, but in the
sense that as long as argumentation is in progress it is always possible to
agree at least on the fact that there is disagreement about the validity of what
has been said. And this is to say nothing else than that a mutual recogni-
tion of each person's exclusive control over his own body must be presup-
posed as long as there is argumentation (note again, that it is impossible to
deny this and claim this denial to be true without implicitly having to admit
its truth).
Hence, one would have to conclude that the norm implied in argumen-
tation is that everybody has the right of exclusive control over his own body
as his instrument of action and cognition. Only if there is at least an implicit
recognition of each individual's property right in his own body can argumen-
tation take place. 9 Only as long as this right is recognized is it possible for
THE ETHICAL JUSTIFICATION OF CAPITALISM 133
WHY SOCIALISM IS MORALLY INDEFENSIBLE
someone to agree to what has been said in an argument and hence can
what has been said be validated, or is it possible to say "no" and to agree
only on the fact that there is disagreement. Indeed, anyone who would try
to justify any norm would already have to presuppose the property right in
his body as a valid norm, simply in order to say, 'This is what I claim to be
true and objective." Any person who would try to dispute the property right
in his own body would become caught up in a contradiction, as arguing in
this way and claiming his argument to be true, would already implicitly ac-
cept precisely this norm as being valid.
Thus it can be stated that whenever a person claims that some state-
ment can be justified, he at least implicitly assumes the following norm to
be justified: "Nobody has the right to uninvitedly aggress against the body
of any other person and thus delimit or restrict anyone's control over his
own body." This rule is implied in the concept of justification as argumen-
tative justification. Justifying means justifying without having to rely on coer-
cion. In fact, if one formulates the opposite of this rule, i.e., "everybody has
the right to uninvitedly aggress against other people" (a rule, by the way,
that would pass the formal test of the universalization principle!), then it is
easy to see that this rule is not, and never could be, defended in argumen-
tation. To do so would in fact have to presuppose the validity of precisely
its opposite, i.e., the aforementioned principle of nonaggression.
may seem that not much is won, as conflicts over bodies, for whose pos-
air and love alone. They need a smaller or greater number of other things
these other things norms are needed, too, as it could come to conflicting
evaluations regarding their use. But in fact, any other norm must be logi-
cally compatible with the nonaggression principle in order to be justified it-
self, and, mutatis mutandis, every norm that could be shown to be
incompatible with this principle would have to be considered invalid. In ad-
dition, as the things with respect to which norms have to be formulated are
scarce goods-just as a person's body is a scarce good-and as it is only
necessary to formulate norms at all because goods are scarce and not be-
cause they are particular kinds of scarce goods, the specifications of the
nonaggression principle, conceived of as a special property norm referring
to a specific kind of good, must in fact already contain those of a general
theory of property.
I will first state this general theory of property as a set of rules applicable
to all goods with the purpose of helping one to avoid all possible conflicts
by means of uniform principles, and will then demonstrate how this general
theory is implied in the nonaggression principle. Since according to the
nonaggression principle a person can do with his body whatever he wants
as long as he does not thereby aggress against another person's body, that
person could also make use of other scarce means, just as one makes use
of one's own body, provided these other things have not already been ap-
propriated by someone else but are still in a natural, unowned state. As
soon as scarce resources are visibly appropriated-as soon as someone
"mixes his labor," as John Locke phrased it, 10 with them and there are ob-
jective traces of this-then property, i.e., the right of exclusive control, can
only be acquired by a contractual transfer of property titles from a previous
to a later owner, and any attempt to unilaterally delimit this exclusive con-
trol of previous owners or any unsolicited transformation of the physical
characteristics of the scarce means in question is, in strict analogy with ag-
gressions against other people's bodies, an unjustifiable action. 11
THE ETHICAL JUSTIFICATION OF CAPITALISM 135
WHY SOCIALISM IS MORALLY INDEFENSIBLE
ly, of course, it has also been demonstrated that any rule specifying different
ing a more detailed analysis, though, of why any socialist ethic is indefen-
sible~a discussion which should throw some additional light on the
In making this assertion, one need not claim to have derived an "ought"
from an "is." In fact, one can readily subscribe to the almost generally ac-
cepted view that the gulf between "ought" and "is" is logically unbridgeable.13
Rather, classifying the rulings of the natural theory of property in this way is
a purely cognitive matter. It no more follows from the classification of the
principle underlying capitalism as "fair" or "just" that one ought to act ac-
cording to it, than it follows from the concept of validity or truth that one
should always strive for it. To say that this principle is just also does not
THE ETHICAL JUSTIFICATION OF CAPITALISM 137
WHY SOCIALISM IS MORALLY INDEFENSIBLE
preclude the possibility of people proposing or even enforcing rules that are
incompatible with it. As a matter of fact, with respect to norms the situation
is very similar to that in other disciplines of scientific inquiry. The fact, for
instance, that certain empirical statements are justified or justifiable and
others are not does not imply that everyone only defends objective, valid
statements. Rather, people can be wrong, even intentionally. But the dis-
tinction between objective and subjective, between true and false, does not
lose any of its significance because of this. Rather, people who are wrong
would have to be classified as either uninformed or intentionally lying. The
case is similar with respect to norms. Of course there are many people who
do not propagate or enforce norms which can be classified as valid accord-
ing to the meaning of justification which I have given above. But the distinc-
tion between justifiable and nonjustifiable norms does not dissolve because
of this, just as that between objective and subjective statements does not
crumble because of the existence of uninformed or lying people. Rather,
and accordingly, those people who would propagate and enforce such dif-
ferent, invalid norms would again have to be classified as uninformed or
dishonest, insofar as one had explained to them and indeed made it clear
that their alternative norm proposals or enforcements could not and never
would be justifiable in argumentation. And there would be even more jus-
tification for doing so in the moral case than in the empirical one, since the
validity of the nonaggression principle and that of the principle of original
appropriation through action as its logically necessary corollary must be
considered to be even more basic than any kind of valid or true statements.
For what is valid or true has to be defined as that upon which everyone ac-
ting according to this principle can possibly agree. As a matter of fact, as
has just been shown, at least the implicit acceptance of these rules is the
necessary prerequisite to being able to live and to argue at all. 14
Why is it, then, precisely, that socialist property theories of any kind fail
138 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
to be justifiable as valid? First, it should be noted that all of the actually prac-
ticed versions of socialism and most of its theoretically proposed models
as well would not even pass the first formal universalization test, and would
fail for this fact alone! These versions all contain norms within their
framework of legal rules which have the form "some people do, and some
people do not." However, such rules, which specify different rights or obliga-
tions for different classes of people, have no chance of being accepted as
fair by every potential participant in an argumentation for simply formal
reasons. Unless the distinction made between different classes of people
happens to be such that it is acceptable to both sides as grounded in the
nature of things, such rules would not be acceptable because they would
imply that one group is awarded legal privileges at the expense of com-
plementary discriminations against another group. Some people, either
those who are allowed to do something or those who are not, therefore could
not agree that these were fair rules. 15 Since most kinds of socialism, as
practiced or preached, have to rely on the enforcement of rules such as
"some people have the obligation to pay taxes, and others have the right to
consume them" or "some people know what is good for you and are allowed
to help you get these alleged blessings even if you do not want them, but
you are not allowed to know what is good for them and help them accord-
ingly" or "some people have the right to determine who has too much of
something and who too little, and others have the obligation to comply" or
even more plainly, 'the computer industry must pay to subsidize the
farmers," 'the employed for the unemployed," 'the ones without kids for
those with kids," etc., or vice versa, they all can be discarded easily as
serious contenders to the claim of being part of a valid theory of norms qua
property norms, because they all indicate by their very formulation that they
are not universalizable.
But what is wrong with the socialist property theories if this is taken care
THE ETHICAL JUSTIFICATION OF CAPITALISM 139
WHY SOCIALISM IS MORALLY INDEFENSIBLE
There are two related specifications in the norms of the natural theory
of property with at least one of which a socialist property theory comes into
conflict. The first such specification is that according to the capitalistic ethic,
aggression is defined as an invasion of the physical integrity of another
person's property.16 Socialism, instead, would define aggression as an in-
vasion of the value or psychic integrity of another person's property. Con-
servative socialism, it should be recalled, aimed at preserving a given
distribution of wealth and values, and attempted to bring those forces which
could change the status quo under control by means of price controls,
regulations, and behavioral controls. Clearly, in order to do so, property
rights to the value of things must be assumed to be justifiable, and an in-
vasion of values, mutatis mutandis, must be classified as unjustifiable ag-
gression. Yet not only conservatism uses this idea of property and
aggression. Social-democratic socialism does, too. Property rights to
values must be assumed to be legitimate when social-democratic socialism
allows me, for instance, to demand compensation from people whose chan-
ces or opportunities negatively affect mine. And the same is true when com-
pensation for committing psychological or "structural violence"-a
particularly dear term in the leftist political science literature-is permitted. 17
140 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
tions, if only in order to have any surviving socialist who can make his moral
proposals.
The situation is no less dire for socialism when one turns to the second
essential specification of the rulings of the natural theory of property. The
basic norms of capitalism were characterized not only by the fact that
142 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
that it implies advocating death but must presuppose life to advocate any-
thing. Neither we, our forefathers, nor our progeny could, do, or will survive
and say or argue anything if one were to follow this rule. In order for any
person-past, present, or future-to argue anything it must be possible to
survive now. Nobody can wait and suspend acting until everyone of an in-
determinate class of late-comers happens to appear and agree to what one
wants to do. Rather, insofar as a person finds himself alone, he must be
able to act, to use, produce, consume goods straightaway, prior to any
agreement with people who are simply not around yet (and perhaps never
will be). And insofar as a person finds himself in the company of others and
there is conflict over how to use a given scarce resource, he must be able
to resolve the problem at a definite point in time with a definite number of
people instead of having to wait unspecified periods of time for unspecified
numbers of people. Simply in order to survive, then, which is a prerequisite
to arguing in favor of or against anything, property rights cannot be con-
ceived of as being timeless and nonspecific regarding the number of people
concerned. Rather, they must necessarily be thought of as originating
through acting at definite points in time for definite acting individuals.20
as one cannot argue that there is no possibility for discussion without the
prior control of every person over his own body being recognized and ac-
cepted as fair, a late-comer ethic that does not wish to make this difference
could never be agreed upon by anyone. Simply saying that it could implies
a contradiction, as one's being able to say so would presuppose one's ex-
istence as an independent decision-making unit at a definite point in time.
If neither an economic nor a moral case for socialism can be made, then
owners possible?
The answer can be broken down into three parts which will be discussed
in turn: (1) by aggressive violence; (2) by corrupting the public through let-
ting them or rather parts of them share in the enjoyment of the receipts coer-
cively extracted from natural owners of things; and (3) by corrupting the
public through letting them or parts of them participate in the specific policy
of expropriation to be enacted.
theory of property must rely on the continual threat of violence. Any such
enslavement, or even death, and it must carry out such threats if necessary,
THE SOCIOPSYCHOLOGICAL FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIALISM 147
THE THEORY OF THE STATE
in order to stay 'trust-worthy" as the kind of institution that it is. Since one
is dealing with an institution-an organization, that is, which performs these
actions on a regular basis-it is almost self-explanatory that it refuses to call
its own practice of doing things "aggression," and instead adopts a different
name for it, with neutral or possibly even positive connotations. In fact, its
representatives might not even think that they themselves are aggressors
when acting in the name of this organization. However, it is not names or
terms that matter here or elsewhere, but what they really mean. 1 Regard-
ing the content of its actions, violence is the cornerstone of socialism's ex-
istence as an institution. And to leave no room for misunderstanding here,
the violence on which socialism rests is not the kind of violence that a natural
owner of things would use or threaten to use against aggressive intruders
of his property. It is not the defensive threat toward a prospective murderer
of, let us say, subjecting him to capital punishment, should he in fact mur-
der someone. Rather, it is aggressive violence directed at innocent victims.
An institution carrying out socialism literally rests on the threat posed by a
prospective murderer against innocent people (i.e., people who have not
done any physical harm whatsoever to anyone) to kill them should they not
comply with his demands, or even to kill them just for the "fun" of killing.
would have the right to boycott at any time, as long as he was indeed the
it would have to tolerate it and suffer silently, or else try to persuade the
148 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
state.2
port this life style through his (their) work. Hence, in order for the agents of
socialism to be able to lead a comfortable life and prosper as they do, it is
essential that the number of exploited subjects be considerably larger and
grow over-proportionally as compared with those of the representatives of
the state itself. With this, however, we are back to the question of how the
few can rule the many.
David Hume is one of the classic expositors of this insight. In his essay
on 'The first principles of government" he argues:
support and this is not verbal propaganda, but rather actions with a clear-
that other people have produced, the state, in order to stabilize itself and in-
its policy, designed to be of use to some people outside the circle of its own
personnel. Either it is engaged as an agent of income transfer, i.e., as an
organization that hands out monetary or nonmonetary income to B that it
has previously taken away from A without A's consent-naturally after sub-
tracting a handling charge for the never costless act of such a transfer-or
it engages in the production of goods or services, using the means ex-
propriated earlier from natural owners, and thus contributes something of
value to the users/buyers/consumers of these goods. Either way, the state
generates support for its role. The recipients of transferred incomes as well
as the users/consumers of state-produced goods and services become de-
pendent to varying degrees on the continuation of a given state policy for
their current incomes, and their inclination to resist the socialism embodied
in state rule is reduced accordingly.
But this is only half of the picture. The positive achievements of the state
are not undertaken simply to do something nice for some people, as, for in-
stance, when someone gives somebody else a present. Nor are they done
simply to gain as high an income as possible from the exchange for the or-
ganization doing them, as when an ordinary, profit-oriented institution
engages in trade. Rather, they are undertaken in order to secure the exist-
ence and contribute to the growth of an institution that is built on aggres-
sive violence. As such, the positive contributions emanating from the state
must serve a strategic purpose. They must be designed to break up resis-
tance to or add support for the continued existence of an aggressor as an
aggressor. Of course, the state can err in this task, as can any ordinary busi-
ness, because its decisions about what measures best serves its strategic
purposes have to be made in anticipation of certain expected results. And
if it errs with respect to the responses following its policy decisions, instead
of rising its income can fall, jeopardizing its very existence, just as a profit-
oriented institution can make losses or even go bankrupt if the public is not
THE SOCIO-PSYCHOLOGICAL FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIALISM 153
THE THEORY OF THE STATE
willing to deliberately buy what It was expected to buy. But only if the
peculiar strategic purpose of state transfers and state production as com-
pared with private transfers or production is understood does it become
possible to explain typical, recurring structural patterns of a state's actions,
and to explain why states generally and uniformly prefer to go into certain
lines of activities rather than others.
As regards the first problem: it does not make sense for a state to ex-
ploit every individual to the same extent, since this would bring everyone
against it, strengthen the solidarity among the victims, and in any case, it
would not be a policy that would find many new friends. It also does not
make sense for a state to grant its favors equally and indiscriminately to
everybody. For if it did, the victims would still be victims, although perhaps
to a lesser degree. However, there would then be less income left to be dis-
tributed to people who would truly profiteer from state action, and whose
increased support could help compensate for the lack of support from vic-
timized persons. Rather, state policy must be and indeed is guided by the
motto "divide et impera": treat people differently, play them against each
other, exploit one possibly smaller group and favor another possibly larger
group at the former's expense, and so counterbalance increased resent-
ment or resistance of some by increased support of others. Politics, as
politics of a state, is not 'the art of doing the possible," as statesmen prefer
to describe their business. It is the art, building on an equilibrium of terror,
of helping to stabilize state income on as high a level as possible by means
of popular discrimination and a popular, discriminatory scheme of distribu-
tional favors. To be sure, a profit-oriented institution can also engage in dis-
criminatory business policies, but to do so and to follow a discriminatory
employment policy or not to sell indiscriminately to anyone who is willing to
pay the price set for a given service or product is costly, and so an economic
incentive to avoid such action exists. For the state, on the other hand, there
154 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
Thus, all states-some more extensively than others, but every state to
a considerable degree-have felt the need to take the system of education,
for one thing, into their own hands. It either directly operates the education-
al institutions, or indirectly controls such institutions by making their private
operation dependent on the granting of a state license, thus insuring that
they operate within a predefined framework of guidelines provided by the
state. Together with a steadily extended period of compulsory schooling,
this gives the state a tremendous head start in the competition among dif-
ferent ideologies for the minds of the people. Ideological competition which
might pose a serious threat to state rule can thereby be eliminated or its im-
pact considerably reduced, especially if the state as the incorporation of
socialism succeeds in monopolizing the job market for intellectuals by
making a state license the prerequisite for any sort of systematic teaching
activity.8
strategic importance for a state. Indeed, all states have gone to great pains
to control rivers, coasts and seaways, streets and railroads, and especially,
mail, radio, television, and telecommunication systems. Every prospective
dissident is decisively restrained in his means of moving around and coor-
dinating the actions of individuals if these things are in the hand or under
the supervision of the state. The fact, well known from military history, that
traffic and communication systems are the very first command posts to be
occupied by any state attacking another vividly underlines their central
strategic significance in imposing state rule on a society.
A third central concern of strategic relevance for any state is the con-
trol and possible monopolization of money. If the state succeeds in this task
and, as is the case now all over the world, supplants a system of free bank-
ing and metal-based currency-most commonly the gold standard-with a
monetary system characterized by a state-operated central bank and paper-
money backed by nothing but paper and ink, a great victory has indeed
been reached. In its permanent struggle for higher income, the state is no
longer dependent on the equally unpopular means of increased taxation or
currency depreciation (coin-clipping), which at all times has been unmasked
quickly as fraudulent. Rather, it can now increase its own revenue and
decrease its own debt almost at will by printing more money, as long as the
additional money is brought into circulation before the inflationary conse-
quences of this practice have taken effect or have been anticipated by the
market.9
Fourth and last, there is the area of the production of security, of police,
fact, it is of such great significance for any state to gain control of these
It is not difficult to see why in order to stabilize its existence, a state can-
not, under any circumstances, leave the production of security in the hands
of a market of private property owners. 10 Since the state ultimately rests on
coercion, it requires armed forces. Unfortunately (for any given state, that
is), other armed states exist which implies that there is a check on a state's
desire to expand its reign over other people and thereby increase its revenue
appropriated through exploitation. It is unfortunate for a given state, too,
that such a system of competing states also implies that each individual
state is somewhat limited regarding the degree to which it can exploit its
own subjects, as their support might dwindle if its own rule is perceived as
more oppressive than that of competing states. For then the likelihood of a
state's subjects collaborating with a competitor in its desire to 'take over,"
or that of voting with their feet (leaving one's own country and going to a
different one) might increase.11 It is even more important, then, for each in-
dividual state to avoid any such unpleasant competition from other poten-
tially dangerous armed organizations at least within the very territory it
happens to control. The mere existence of a private protection agency,
armed as it would have to be to do its job of protecting people from aggres-
sion and employing people trained in the use of such arms, would constitute
a potential threat to a state's ongoing policy of invading private people's
property rights. Hence, such organizations, which would surely spring up
THE SOCIO-PSYCHOLOGICAL FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIALISM 157
THE THEORY OF THE STATE
With respect to the judicial system matters are quite similar. If the state
did not monopolize the provision of judicial services, it would be unavoidable
that, sooner or later (and most likely sooner), the state would come to be
regarded as the unjust institution it in fact is. Yet no unjust organization has
any interest in being recognized as such. For one thing, if the state did not
see to it that only judges appointed and employed by the state itself ad-
ministered the law, it is evident that public law (those norms regulating the
relationship between the state and private individuals or associations of such
individuals) would have no chance of being accepted by the public, but in-
stead would be unveiled immediately as a system of legalized aggression,
existing in violation of almost everyone's sense of justice. And secondly, if
the state did not also monopolize the administration of private law (those
norms regulating the relationships among private citizens) but left this task
to competing courts and judges, dependent on the public's deliberate finan-
cial support, it is doubtful that norms implying an asymmetrical distribution
of rights or obligations between different persons or classes of persons
would have even the slightest chance of becoming generally accepted as
valid laws. Courts and judges who laid down such rules would immediate-
ly go bankrupt due to a lack of continued financial assistance.12 However,
since the state is dependent on a policy of divide et impera to maintain its
158 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
from the frustration of one's lust for power) that any one particular policy im-
ing for his particular power policy can hope to have a shot at it in the future.
terms of the classics of political thought, it must rule more wisely, i.e., rule
less. Since it does not allow any will other than that of the autocrat, and per-
basis, its execution of power appears less tolerable to those ruled. Thus, its
The situation over the last two centuries vividly illustrates the validity of
this thesis. During this time we have experienced an almost universal sub-
cal systems.16 (Even Soviet Russia is notably more democratic than czarist
Russia ever was.) Hand in hand with this change has gone a process never
experienced before regarding its speed and extent: a permanent and seem-
ingly uncontrollable growth of the state. In the competition of different states
for exploitable populations, and in these states' attempts to come to grips
with internal resistance, the democratic state has tended to win outright over
the autocratic one as the superior power-variant. Ceteris paribus, it is the
democratic state-and the democratic socialism incorporated in it-which
commands the higher income and so proves to be superior in wars with
other states. And ceteris paribus, it is this state, too, that succeeds better
in the management of internal resistance: it is, and historically this has been
shown repeatedly, easier to save the power of a state by democratizing it
than by doing the opposite and autocratizing its decision-making structure.
might be; whether the state provides help for working mothers with depend-
ent children or gives medical care, engages in road or airport construction;
whether it grants favors to farmers or students, devotes itself to the produc-
tion of educational services, society's infrastructure, money, steel or peace;
or even if it does all of these things and more, it would be completely falla-
cious to enumerate all of this and leave it at that. What must be said in ad-
dition is that the state can do nothing without the previous noncontractual
expropriation of natural owners. Its contributions to welfare are never an or-
dinary present, even if they are given away free of charge, because some-
thing is handed out that the state does not rightfully own in the first place.
If it sells its services at cost, or even at a profit, the means of production
employed in providing them still must have been appropriated by force. And
if it sells them at a subsidized price, aggression must continue in order to
uphold the current level of production.
has nothing in common with this, and only superficial sociological "studies
in organization" would engage in investigations of structural similarities or
differences between the two. 17
Only if this is thoroughly understood can the nature of the state and
socialism be fully grasped. And only then can there be a complete under-
standing of the other side of the same problem: what it takes to overcome
socialism. The state cannot be fought by simply boycotting it, as a private
business could, because an aggressor does not respect the negative judg-
ment revealed by boycotts. But it also cannot simply be fought by counter-
ing its aggression with defensive violence, because the state's aggression
is supported by public opinion. 18 Thus, everything depends on a change
in public opinion. More specifically, everything depends on two assump-
tions and the change that can be achieved regarding their status as realis-
tic or unrealistic. One such assumption was implied when it was argued
above that the state can generate support for its role by providing certain
goods and services to favored groups of people. There, evidently, the as-
sumption involved was that people can be corrupted into supporting an ag-
gressor if they receive a share, however small, of the benefits. And, since
states exist everywhere, this assumption, happily for the state, must indeed
be said to be realistic everywhere, today. But then, there is no such thing
as a law of nature stating that this must be so forever. In order for the state
to fail in reaching its objective, no more and no less than a change in general
public opinion must take place: state-supportive action must come to be
regarded and branded as immoral because it is support given to an or-
ganization of institutionalized crime. Socialism would be at its end if only
people stopped letting themselves be corrupted by the state's bribes, but
would, let us say, if offered, take their share of the wealth in order to reduce
the state's bribing power, while continuing to regard and treat it as an ag-
gressor to be resisted, ignored, and ridiculed, at any time and in any place.
166 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
The second assumption involved was that people indeed lust for power
and hence can be corrupted into state-supportive action if given a chance
to satisfy this lust. Looking at the facts, there can hardly be any doubt that
today this assumption, too, is realistic. But once again, it is not realistic be-
cause of natural laws, for at least in principle, it can deliberately be made
unrealistic.19 In order to bring about the end of statism and socialism, no
more and no less must be accomplished than a change in public opinion
which would lead people away from using the institutional outlets for policy
participation for the satisfaction of power lust, but instead make them sup-
press any such desire and turn this very organizational weapon of the state
against it and push uncompromisingly for an end to taxation and regulation
of natural owners wherever and whenever there is a chance of influencing
policy. 20
9
CAPITALIST PRODUCTION AND THE
PROBLEM OF MONOPOLY
As long as it produces for a market, i.e., for exchange with other people
or businesses, and subject as it is to the rule of nonaggression against the
property of natural owners, every ordinary business will use its resources
for the production of such goods and such amounts of these goods which,
in anticipation, promise a return from sales that surpasses as far as possible
the costs which are involved in using these resources. If this were not so,
a business would use its resources for the production of different amounts
of such goods or of different goods altogether. And every such business
has to decide repeatedly whether a given allocation or use of its means of
production should be upheld and reproduced, or if, due to a change in
demand or the anticipation of such a change, a reallocation to different uses
is in order. The question of whether or not resources have been used in the
most value-productive (the most profitable) way, or if a given reallocation
was the most economic one, can, of course, only be decided in a more or
less distant future under any conceivable economic or social system, be-
cause invariably time is needed to produce a product and bring it onto the
market. However, and this is decisive, for every business there is an objec-
tive criterion for deciding the extent to which its previous allocations
CAPITALIST PRODUCTION AND THE PROBLEM OF MONOPOLY 169
The situation is entirely different and arbitrariness from the point of view
of the consumer (for whom, it should be recalled, production is undertaken)
replaces rationality as soon as the state enters the picture. Because it is dif-
ferent from ordinary businesses in that it is allowed to acquire income by
noncontractual means, the state is not forced to avoid losses if it wants to
170 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
stay in business as are all other producers. Rather, since it is allowed to im-
pose taxes and/or regulations on people, the state is in a position to deter-
mine unilaterally whether or not, to what extent, and for what length of time
to subsidize its own productive operations. It can also unilaterally choose
which prospective competitor is allowed to compete with the state or pos-
sibly outcompete it. Essentially this means that the state becomes inde-
pendent of cost-profit considerations. But if it is no longer forced to test
continually any of its various uses of resources against this criterion, i.e., if
it no longer need successfully adjust its resource allocations to the changes
in demand of consumers in order to survive as a producer, then the se-
quence of allocations decisions as a whole must be regarded as an ar-
bitrary, irrational process of decision making. A mechanism of selection
forcing those allocations "mutations" which consistently ignore or exhibit a
maladjustment to consumer demand out of operation simply no longer ex-
ists.3 To say that the process of resource allocation becomes arbitrary in
the absence of the effective functioning of the profit-loss criterion does not
mean that the decisions which somehow have to be made are not subject
to any kind of constraint and hence are pure whim. They are not, and any
such decision faces certain constraints imposed on the decision maker. If,
for instance, the allocation of production factors is decided democratically,
then it evidently must appeal to the majority. But if a decision is constrained
in this way or if it is made autocratically, respecting the state of public opinion
as seen by the autocrat, then it is still arbitrary from the point of view of volun-
tarily buying or not-buying consumers.4 Hence, the allocation of resources,
whatever it is and however it changes over time, embodies a wasteful use
of scarce means. Freed from the necessity of making profits in order to sur-
vive as a consumer-serving institution, the state necessarily substitutes al-
locational chaos for rationality. M. Rothbard nicely summarizes the problem
as follows:
CAPITALIST PRODUCTION AND THE PROBLEM OF MONOPOLY 171
decision to grant the state the special right to appropriate revenue in a non-
business can only maintain a given size or possibly grow if it can sell its
products at a price and in such quantity that allow it to recover at least the
costs involved in production and is hopefully higher. Since the demand for
Finally, in addition to the facts that only a market system can ensure a
rational allocation of scarce resources, and that only capitalist enterprises
can guarantee an output of products that can be said to be of optimal quality,
there is a third structural reason for the economic superiority, indeed unsur-
passability of a capitalist system of production. Only through the operation
of market forces is it possible to utilize resources efficiently over time in any
given allocation, i.e., to avoid overutilization as well as underutilization. This
problem has already been addressed with reference to Russian style
socialism in Chapter 3. What are the institutional constraints on an ordinary
profit-oriented enterprise in its decisions about the degree of exploitation or
conservation of its resources in the particular line of production in which
they happen to be used? Evidently, the owner of such an enterprise would
own the production factors or resources as well as the products produced
with them. Thus, his income (used here in a wide sense of the term) con-
sists of two parts: the income that is received from the sales of the products
produced after various operating costs have been subtracted; and the value
174 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
Now it is fairly certain that someone will argue that while one would not
doubt what has been stated so far, things would in fact be different and the
deficiency of a pure market system would come to light as soon as one paid
attention to the special case of monopolistic production. And by necessity,
monopolistic production would have to arise under capitalism, at least in the
long run. Not only Marxist critics but orthodox economic theorists as well
make much of this alleged counter-argument.9 In answer to this challenge
four points will be made in turn. First, available historical evidence shows
that contrary to these critics' thesis, there is no tendency toward increased
monopoly under an unhampered market system. In addition, there are
theoretical reasons that would lead one to doubt that such a tendency could
ever prevail on a free market. Third, even if such a process of increasing
monopolization should come to bear, for whatever reason, it would be harm-
less from the point of view of consumers provided that free entry into the
market were indeed ensured. And fourth, the concept of monopoly prices
as distinguished from and contrasted to competitive prices is illusory in a
capitalist economy.
were true, then one would have to expect a more pronounced tendency
factors are indeed used in the most profitable way-becomes ever more
acute. This is so, in particular, because realistically one must assume that
the monopolist is not only not omniscient but that his knowledge regarding
ces. As production factors are withdrawn from the market, and as the circle
of consumers served by the goods produced with these factors widens, It
will be less likely that the monopolist, unable to make use of economic cal-
culation, can remain in command of all the relevant information needed to
detect the most profitable uses for his production factors. Instead, it be-
comes more likely in the course of such a process of monopolization, that
other people or groups of people, given their desire to make profits by en-
gaging in production, will perceive more lucrative ways of employing the
monopolized factors. 14 Not necessarily because they are better
entrepreneurs, but simply because they occupy different positions in space
and time and thus become increasingly aware of entrepreneurial oppor-
tunities which become more and more difficult and costly for the monopo-
list to detect with every new step toward monopolization. Hence, the
likelihood that the monopolist will be persuaded to sell his monopolized fac-
tors to other producers-nofa bene: for the purpose of thereby increasing
his profits-increases with every additional step toward monopolization.15
labor services whatever he wants. He can consume or save them, use them
for productive or nonproductive purposes, or associate with others and
combine their funds for any sort of joint venture. But if this were so, then
the existence of a monopoly would only allow one to say this: the monop-
olist clearly could not see any chance of improving his income by selling all
or part of his means of production, otherwise he would do so. And no one
else could see any chance of improving his income by bidding away factors
from the monopolist or by becoming a capitalist producer himself through
original saving, through transforming existing nonproductively used private
wealth into productive capital, or through combining funds with others,
otherwise it would be done. But then, if no one saw any chance of improv-
ing his income without resorting to aggression, it would evidently be absurd
to see anything wrong with such a super-monopoly. Should it indeed ever
come into existence within the framework of a market economy, it would
only prove that this self-same super-monopolist was indeed providing con-
sumers with the most urgently wanted goods and services in the most effi-
cient way.
being necessarily more efficient than any socialist or statist system. What
with which he and every producer is faced? He must decide how much of
the good in question to produce in order to maximize his monetary income
(with other, nonmonetary income considerations assumed to be given). To
be able to do this he must decide how the demand curve for the product
concerned will be shaped when the products reach the market, and he must
take into consideration the various production costs of producing various
amounts of the good to be produced. This done, he will establish the
amount to be produced at that point where returns from sales, i.e., the
amount of goods sold times price, minus production costs involved in
producing that amount, will reach a maximum. Let us assume this happens
and the monopolist also happens to be correct in his evaluation of the fu-
ture demand curve in that the price he seeks for his products indeed clears
the market. Now the question is, is this market price a monopoly or a com-
petitive price? As M. Rothbard realized in his path-breaking but much
neglected analysis of the monopoly problem, there is no way of knowing.
Was the amount of the good produced "restricted" in order to take advantage
of inelastic demand and was a monopoly price thus reaped, or was the price
reached a competitive one established in order to sell an amount of goods
that was expanded 'to the limit that a competitive market would allow"?
There is no way to decide the matter. 18 Clearly, every producer will always
try to set the quantity produced at a level above which demand would be-
come elastic and would hence yield lower total returns to him because of
reduced prices paid. He thus engages in restrictive practices. At the same
time, based on his estimate of the shape of future demand curves, every
producer will always try to expand his production of any good up to the point
at which the marginal cost of production (that is, the opportunity cost of not
producing a unit of an alternative good with the help of scarce production
factors now bound up in the process of producing another unit of x) equals
the price per unit of x that one expects to be able to charge at the respec-
CAPITALIST PRODUCTION AND THE PROBLEM OF MONOPOLY 183
tive level of supply. Both restriction and expansion are part of profit-maxi-
mizing and market-price formation, and neither of these two aspects can be
separated from the other to make a valid distinction between monopolistic
and competitive action.
Now, suppose that at the next point of decision making the monopolist
decides to reduce the output of the good produced from a previously higher
to a new lower level, and assume that he indeed succeeds in securing higher
total returns now than at the earlier point in time. Wouldn't this be a clear
instance of a monopoly price? Again, the answer must be no. And this time
the reason would be the indistinguishability of this reallocational "restriction"
from a "normal" reallocation that takes account of changes in demand.
Every event that can be interpreted in one way can also be interpreted in
the other, and no means for deciding the matter exist, for once again both
are essentially two aspects of one and the same thing: of action, of choos-
ing. The same result, i.e., a restriction in supply coupled not only with higher
prices but with prices high enough to increase total revenue from sales,
would be brought about if the monopolist who, for example, produces a uni-
que kind of apples faces an increase in the demand for his apples (an up-
ward shift in the demand curve) and simultaneously an even higher increase
in demand (an even more drastic upward shift of the demand curve) for oran-
ges. In this situation he would reap greater returns from a reduced output
of apples, too, because the previous market price for his apples would have
become a subcompetitive price in the meantime. And if he indeed wanted
to maximize his profits, instead of simply expanding apple production ac-
cording to the increased demand, he now would have to use some of the
factors previously used for the production of apples for the production of
oranges, because in the meantime changes in the system of relative prices
would have occurred. However, what if the monopolist who restricts apple
production does not engage in producing oranges with the now available
184 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
factors, but instead does nothing with them? Again, all that this would indi-
cate is that besides the increase in demand for apples, in the meantime an
even greater increase in the demand for yet another good-leisure (more
precisely, the demand for leisure by the monopolist who is also a consumer) -
-had taken place. The explanation for the restricted apple supply is thus
found in the relative price changes of leisure (instead of oranges) as com-
pared with other goods.
Neither from the perspective of the monopolist himself nor from that of
any outside observer could restrictive action then be distinguished concep-
tually from normal ^allocations which simply follow anticipated changes in
demand. Whenever the monopolist engages in restrictive activities which
are followed by higher prices, by definition he must use the released factors
for another more highly valued purpose, thereby indicating that he adjusts
to changes in relative demand. As M. Rothbard sums up,
action to be resolved does not exist.21 In fact, only when the state enters
186 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
This final chapter will analyze an even more frequently cited special case
of security.
If what has been stated in the foregoing chapter regarding the working
of a market economy is true, and if monopolies are completely harmless to
consumers as long as the consumers have the right to boycott them and
188 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
freely enter the market of competing producers themselves, then one must
draw the conclusion that for economic as well as moral reasons, the produc-
tion of all goods and services should be left in private hands. And in par-
ticular it follows that even the production of law and order, justice and
peace-those things that one has come to think of as being the most likely
candidates for state-provided goods for reasons explained in Chapter 8 -
should be provided privately, by a competitive market. This indeed is the
conclusion that G. de Molinari, a renowned Belgian economist, formulated
as early as 1849-at a time when classical liberalism was still the dominant
ideological force, and "economist" and "socialist" were generally (and right-
ly so) considered to be antonyms:
and true, or else the principles on which economic science is based are in-
valid."2
There is apparently only one way out of this unpleasant (for all socialists,
CAPITALIST PRODUCTION AND THE PROBLEM OF PUBLIC GOODS 189
that is) conclusion: to argue that there are particular goods to which for
some special reasons the above economic reasoning does not apply. It is
this that the so-called public goods theorists are determined to prove. 3
However, we will demonstrate that in fact no such special goods or special
reasons exist, and that the production of security in particular does not pose
any problem different from that of the production of any other good or ser-
vice, be it houses, cheese, or insurance. In spite of its many followers, the
whole public goods theory is faulty, flashy reasoning, ridden with internal in-
consistencies, nonsequiturs, appealing to and playing on popular
prejudices and assumed beliefs, but with no scientific merit whatsoever.4
What, then, does the "escape route" that socialist economists have
found in order to avoid drawing Molinari's conclusion look like? Since
Molinari's time it has become increasingly common to answer the question
of whether there are goods to which different sorts of economic analyses
apply in the affirmative. As a matter of fact, nowadays it is almost impos-
sible to find a single economic textbook that does not make and stress the
vital importance of the distinction between private goods, for which the truth
of the economic superiority of a capitalist order of production is generally
admitted, and public goods, for which it is generally denied. 5 Certain goods
or services, and among them, security, are said to have the special charac-
teristic that their enjoyment cannot be restricted to those persons who have
actually financed their production. Rather, people who have not par-
ticipated in their financing can draw benefits from them, too. Such goods
are called public goods or services (as opposed to private goods or ser-
vices, which exclusively benefit those people who actually paid for them).
And it is due to this special feature of public goods, it is argued, that markets
cannot produce them, or at least not in sufficient quantity or quality, and
hence compensatory state action is required.6 The examples given by dif-
ferent authors for alleged public goods vary widely. Authors often classify
190 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
garden-they could enjoy the sight of It without ever helping me garden. The
same Is true of all kinds of Improvements that I could make on my property
that would enhance the value of neighboring property as well. Even those
people who do not throw money in his hat could profit from a street
musician's performance. Those fellow travellers on the bus who did not help
me buy it profit from my deodorant. And everyone who ever comes into
contact with me would profit from my efforts, undertaken without their finan-
cial support, to turn myself into a most lovable person. Now, do all these
goods-rose gardens, property improvements, street music, deodorants,
personality improvements-since they clearly seem to possess the charac-
teristics of public goods, then have to be provided by the state or with state
assistance?
there is something seriously wrong with the thesis of public goods theorists
that these goods cannot be produced privately but instead require state in-
cal evidence shows us that all of the alleged public goods which states now
provide had at some time in the past actually been provided by private
example, the postal service was once private almost everywhere; streets
were privately financed and still are sometimes; even the beloved ligh-
thouses were originally the result of private enterprise;9 private police for-
ces, detectives, and arbitrators exist; and help for the sick, the poor, the
elderly, orphans, and widows has been a traditional field for private charity
Apart from this, other difficulties arise when the public-private goods
distinction is used to decide what to leave to the market and what not. What,
for instance, if the production of so-called public goods did not have posi-
192 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
Leaving this somewhat sketchy level of discussion and looking into the
distinction between private and public goods more thoroughly, it turns out
to be a completely illusory distinction. A clear-cut dichotomy between
private and public goods does not exist, and this is essentially why there
can be so many disagreements on how to classify given goods. All goods
are more or less private or public and can~and constantly do~change with
respect to their degree of privateness/publicness with people's changing
values and evaluations, and with changes in the composition of the popula-
tion. They never fall, once and for all, into either one or the other category.
In order to recognize this, one must only recall what makes something a
good. For something to be a good it must be realized and treated as scarce
by someone. Something is not a good-as-such, that is to say, but goods
are goods only in the eyes of the beholder. Nothing is a good without at
least one person subjectively evaluating it as such. But then, since goods
CAPITALIST PRODUCTION AND THE PROBLEM OF PUBLIC GOODS 193
But even if one were to ignore all these difficulties, and were willing to
admit for the sake of argument that the private-public good distinction did
hold water, even then the argument would not prove what it is supposed to.
For one thing, to come to the conclusion that the state has to provide
public goods that otherwise would not be produced, one must smuggle a
norm into one's chain of reasoning. Otherwise, from the statement that be-
produced, one could never reach the conclusion that these goods should
be produced. But with a norm required to justify their conclusion, the public
wertfrei science. Instead they have transgressed into the field of morals or
cognitive discipline in order for them to legitimately do what they are doing
and to justifiably derive the conclusion that they actually derive. But it can
hardly be stressed enough that nowhere in the public goods theory litera-
ture can there be found anything that even faintly resembles such a cogni-
tive theory of ethics. 14 Thus it must be stated at the outset, that the public
goods theorists are misusing whatever prestige they might have as positive
CAPITALIST PRODUCTION AND THE PROBLEM OF PUBLIC GOODS 195
But the public goods theory breaks down not just because of the faul-
theory states, it might well be that it would be better to have the public goods
than not to have them, though it should not be forgotten that no a priori
reason exists that this must be so of necessity (which would then end the
public goods theorists' reasoning right here). For it is clearly possible, and
196 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
indeed known to be a fact, that anarchists exist who so greatly abhor state
action that they would prefer not having the so-called public goods at all to
having them provided by the state! 15 In any case, even if the argument is
conceded so far, to leap from the statement that the public goods are
desirable to the statement that they should therefore be provided by the
state is anything but conclusive, as this is by no means the choice with which
one is confronted. Since money or other resources must be withdrawn from
possible alternative uses to finance the supposedly desirable public goods,
the only relevant and appropriate question is whether or not these alterna-
tive uses to which the money could be put (that is, the private goods which
could have been acquired but now cannot be bought because the money
is being spent on public goods instead) are more valuable-more urgent-
than the public goods. And the answer to this question is perfectly clear. In
terms of consumer evaluations, however high its absolute level might be,
the value of the public goods is relatively lower than that of the competing
private goods, because if one had left the choice to the consumers (and had
not forced one alternative upon them), they evidently would have preferred
spending their money differently (otherwise no force would have been
necessary). This proves beyond any doubt that the resources used for the
provision of public goods are wasted, as they provide consumers with goods
or services which at best are only of secondary importance. In short, even
if one assumed that public goods which can be distinguished clearly from
private goods existed, and even if it were granted that a given public good
might be useful, public goods would still compete with private goods. And
there is only one method for finding out whether or not they are more ur-
gently desired and to what extent, or, mutatis mutandis, if, and to what ex-
tent, their production would take place at the expense of the nonproduction
or reduced production of more urgently needed private goods: by having
everything provided by freely competing private enterprises. Hence, con-
CAPITALIST PRODUCTION AND THE PROBLEM OF PUBLIC GOODS 197
trary to the conclusion arrived at by the public goods theorists, logic forces
one to accept the result that only a pure market system can safeguard the
rationality, from the point of view of the consumers, of a decision to produce
a public good. And only under a pure capitalist order could it be ensured
that the decision about how much of a public good to produce (provided it
should be produced at all) is rational as well. 16 No less than a semantic
revolution of truly Orwellian dimensions would be required to come up with
a different result. Only if one were willing to interpret someone's "no" as real-
ly meaning "yes," the "nonbuying of something" as meaning that it is really
"preferred over that which the nonbuying person does instead of non-
buying," of "force" really meaning "freedom," of "non-contracting" really
meaning "making a contract" and so on, could the public goods theorists'
point be "proven."17 But then, how could we be sure that they really mean
what they seem to mean when they say what they say, and do not rather
mean the exact opposite, or don't mean anything with a definite content at
all, but are simply babbling? We could not! M. Rothbard is thus complete-
ly right when he comments on the endeavors of the public goods ideologues
to prove the existence of so-called market failures due to the nonproduc-
tion or a quantitatively or qualitatively "deficient" production of public goods.
He writes, "...such a view completely misconceives the way in which
economic science asserts that free-market action is ever optimal. It is op-
timal, not from the standpoint of the personal ethical views of an economist,
but from the standpoint of free, voluntary actions of all participants and in
satisfying the freely expressed needs of the consumers. Government inter-
ference, therefore, will necessarily and always move away from such an op-
timum." 18
did exist, no special reason could be found why these supposedly special
public goods should not also be produced by private enterprises since they
invariably stand in competition with private goods. In fact, in spite of all the
propaganda from the side of the public goods theorists, the greater efficien-
cy of markets as compared with the state has been realized with respect to
more and more of the alleged public goods. Confronted daily with ex-
perience, hardly anyone seriously studying these matters could deny that
nowadays markets could produce postal services, railroads, electricity,
telephone, education, money, roads and so on more effectively, i.e., more
to the liking of the consumers, than the state. Yet people generally shy away
from accepting in one particular sector what logic forces upon them: in the
field of the production of security. Hence, the rest of this chapter will ex-
plain the superior functioning of a capitalist economy in this particular area-
-a superiority whose logical case has already been made, but which shall
be rendered more persuasive once some empirical material is added to the
analysis and it is studied as a problem in its own right.21
security can no longer be spent on other goods that also might increase
not only prevention, detection, and enforcement but there is also security
whole and also to different aspects of the whole thing, depending on their
security, and the time and place in which they happen to live. 23 Now, and
CAPITALIST PRODUCTION AND THE PROBLEM OF PUBLIC GOODS 201
respect to the one thing that consumers want most urgently--the prevention
of hard-core crime (i.e., crimes with victims), the detection and effective
punishment of hard-core criminals, the recovery of loot, and the securement
of compensation to victims of crimes from the aggressors-they are
notoriously inefficient, in spite of ever higher budget allocations.
Third, anyone who has seen state-run police stations and courts, not to
mention prisons, knows how true it is that the factors of production used to
provide us with such security are overused, badly maintained, and filthy.
There is no reason for them to satisfy the consumers who provide their in-
come. And if, in an exceptional case, this happens not to be so, then it has
only been possible at costs that are comparatively much higher than those
But that is far from all. Besides diversification, the content and quality
of the products would improve, too. Not only would the treatment of con-
sumers by the employees of security enterprises improve immediately, the
"I could care less" attitude, the arbitrariness and even brutality, the
negligence and tardiness of the present police and judicial systems would
ultimately disappear. Since they then would be dependent on voluntary
consumer support, any maltreatment, impoliteness, or ineptitude could cost
them their jobs. Further, the above-mentioned peculiarity-that the settle-
ment of disputes between a client and his service provider is invariably
entrusted to the latter's judgment-would almost certainly disappear from
the books, and conflict arbitration by independent parties would become
the standard deal offered by producers of security. Most importantly
though, in order to attract and retain customers the producers of such ser-
vices would have to offer contracts which would allow the consumer to know
what he was buying and enable him to raise a valid, intersubjectively ascer-
tainable complaint if the actual performance of the security producer did not
live up to its obligations. And more specifically, insofar as they are not in-
dividualized service contracts where payment is made by the customers for
covering their own risks exclusively, but rather insurance contracts proper
which involve pooling one's own risks with those of other people, contrary
to the present statist practice, these contracts most certainly would no
longer contain any deliberately built-in redistribute scheme favoring one
group of people at the expense of another. Otherwise, if anyone had the
feeling that the contract offered to him involved his paying for other people's
peculiar needs and risks-factors of possible insecurity, that is, that he did
not perceive as applicable to his own case-he would simply reject signing
it or discontinue his payments.
CAPITALIST PRODUCTION AND THE PROBLEM OF PUBLIC GOODS 205
Yet when all this is said, the question will inevitably surface, "Wouldn't
a competitive system of security production still necessarily result in per-
manent social conflict, in chaos and anarchy?" There are several points to
be made regarding this alleged criticism. First, it should be noted that such
an impression would by no means be in accordance with historical, empiri-
cal evidence. Systems of competing courts have existed at various places,
such as in ancient Ireland or at the time of the Hanseatic league, before the
arrival of the modern nation state, and as far as we know they worked well. 26
Judged by the then existent crime rate (crime per capita), the private police
in the Wild West (which incidentally was not as wild as some movies in-
sinuate) was relatively more successful than today's state-supported
police. 27 And turning to contemporary experience and examples, millions
and millions of international contacts exist even now-contacts of trade and
travel-and it certainly seems to be an exaggeration to say, for instance, that
there is more fraud, more crime, more breach of contract there than in
domestic relations. And this is so, it should be noted, without there being
one big monopolistic security producer and law-maker. Finally it is not to
be forgotten that even now in a great number of countries there are various
private security producers alongside to the state: private investigators, in-
surance detectives, and private arbitrators. Regarding their work, the im-
pression seems to confirm the thesis that they are more, not less, successful
in resolving social conflicts than their public counterparts.
regarding the question of conflict resolution, and hence will tend to generate
less rather than more social unrest and conflict than under monopolistic
auspices! 28 In order to understand this it is necessary to take a closer look
at the only typical situation that concerns the skeptic and allows him to
believe in the superior virtue of a monopolistically organized order of security
production. This is the situation when a conflict arises between A and B,
both are insured by different companies and the companies cannot come
to an immediate agreement regarding the validity of the conflicting claims
brought forward by their respective clients. (No problem would exist if such
an agreement were reached, or if both clients were insured by one and the
same company--at least the problem then would not be different in any way
from that emerging under a statist monopoly!) Wouldn't such a situation al-
ways result in an armed confrontation? This is highly unlikely. First, any
violent battle between companies would be costly and risky, in particular if
these companies had reached a respectable size which would be important
for them to have in order to appear as effective guarantors of security to
their prospective clients in the first place. More importantly though, under
a competitive system with each company dependent on the continuation of
voluntary consumer payments, any battle would have to be deliberately sup-
ported by each and every client of both companies. If there were only one
person who withdrew his payments because he was not convinced the bat-
tle was necessary in the particular conflict at hand, there would be immediate
economic pressure on the company to look for a peaceful solution to the
conflict.29 Hence, any competitive producer of security would be extreme-
ly cautious about his dedication to engaging in violent measures in order to
resolve conflicts. Instead, to the extent that it is peaceful conflict-resolution
that consumers want, each and every security producer would go to great
lengths to provide such measures to its clients and to establish in advance,
for everyone to know, to what arbitration process it would be willing to sub-
CAPITALIST PRODUCTION AND THE PROBLEM OF PUBLIC GOODS 207
mit itself and its clients in case of a disagreement over the evaluation of con-
flicting claims. And as such a scheme could only appear to the clients of
different firms to be really working if there were agreement among them
regarding such arbitration^ measures, a system of law governing relations
between companies which would be universally acceptable to the clients of
all of the competing security producers would naturally evolve. Moreover,
the economic pressure to generate rules representing consensus on how
conflicts should be handled is even more far-reaching. Under a competi-
tive system the independent arbitrators who would be entrusted with the
task of finding peaceful solutions to conflicts would be dependent on the
continued support of the two disagreeing companies insofar as they could
and would select different judges if either one of them were sufficiently dis-
satisfied with the outcome of their arbitration work. Thus, these judges
would be under pressure to find solutions to the problems handed over to
them which, this time not with respect to the procedural aspects of law, but
its content, would be acceptable to all of the clients of the firms involved in
a given case as a fair and just solution.30 Otherwise one or all of the com-
panies might lose some of their customers, thus inducing those firms to turn
to a different arbitrator the next time they were in need of one. 31
people and their property, and would you continue supporting it if it did?
Certainly the critic would be much muted by this counterattack. But more
important than this is the systematic challenge implied in this personal
counterattack. Evidently, the described change in the situation would imply
a change in the cost-benefit structure that everyone would face once he had
to make his decisions. Before the introduction of a competitive system of
security production it had been legal to participate in and support (state)
aggression. Now such an activity would be an illegal activity. Hence, given
one's conscience, which makes each of one's own decisions appear more
or less costly, i.e., more or less in harmony with one's own principles of cor-
rect behavior, support for a firm engaging in the exploitation of people un-
willing to deliberately support its actions would be more costly now than
before. Given this fact, it must be assumed that the number of people-
among them even those who otherwise would have readily lent their sup-
port to the state-who would now spend their money to support a firm
committed to honest business would rise, and would rise everywhere this
social experiment was tried. In contrast, the number of people still com-
mitted to a policy of exploitation, of gaining at the expense of others, would
fall. How drastic this effect would be would, of course, depend on the state
of public opinion. In the example at hand-the United States, where the
natural theory of property is extremely widespread and accepted as a private
ethic, the libertarian philosophy being essentially the ideology on which the
country was founded and that let it develop to the height it reached^-the
above-mentioned effect would naturally be particularly pronounced. Ac-
cordingly, security-producing firms committed to the philosophy of protect-
ing and enforcing libertarian law would attract the greatest bulk of public
support and financial assistance. And while it may be true that some people,
and among them especially those who had profited from the old order, might
continue their support of a policy of aggression, it is very unlikely that they
210 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
CHAPTER 1
CHAPTER 2
3. It should be noted that a person cannot intentionally not act, as even the
attempt not to act, i.e., one's decision not to do anything and instead remain
in some previously occupied position or state would itself qualify as an ac-
tion, thus rendering this statement aprioristically true, i.e., a statement that
cannot be challenged by experience, as anyone who would try to disprove
it thereby would have to choose and put his body willy-nilly to some specific
use.
analysis assumes validity. Terms don't matter; what counts is what the
natural position really is and implies as such. The following analyses are
concerned exclusively with this problem.
7. Note again that the term "aggression" is used here without evaluative
connotations. Only later in this treatise will I demonstrate that aggression as
defined above is indeed morally indefensible. Names are empty; what alone
is important is what It really is that is called aggression.
8. When I discuss the problem of moral justification in Chapter 7,1 will return
to the importance of the distinction just made of aggression as an invasion
of the physical integrity of someone and, on the other hand, an invasion of
the integrity of someone's value system, which is not classified as aggres-
sion. Here it suffices to notice that it is some sort of technical necessity for
any theory of property (not just the natural position described here) that the
delimitation of the property rights of one person against those of another be
formulated in physical, objective, intersubjectively ascertainable terms.
Otherwise it would be impossible for an actor to determine ex ante if any
particular action of his were an aggression or not, and so the social func-
tion of property norms (any property norms), i.e., to make a conflict-free in-
teraction possible, could not be fulfilled simply for technical reasons.
10. On the disutility of work and waiting cf. the theory of time-preference as
espoused by L v. Mises, Human Action, Chicago, 1966, chapters 5,18, 21;
the same, Socialism, Indianapolis, 1981, chapter 8; M. N. Rothbard, Man,
Economy and State, Los Angeles, 1970, chapters 6, 9; also: E. v. Boehm-
Bawerk, Kapital und Kapitalzins. Positive Theory des Kapitals, Meisenheim,
1967; F. Fetter, Capital, Interest and Rent, Kansas City, 1976.
On a critical assessment of the term "human capital," in particular of the
214 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
absurd treatment that this concept has had at the hands of some Chicago-
economists (notably G. Becker, Human Capital, New York, 1975), cf. A. Rub-
ner, The Three Sacred Cows of Economics, New York, 1970.
13. The superimposition of public on private law has tainted and com-
promised the latter to some extent everywhere. Nonetheless, it is not dif-
ficult to disentangle existing private law systems and find what is here called
the natural position as constituting its central elements-a fact which once
again underlines the "naturalness" of this property theory. Cf. also Chapter
8, n. 13.
NOTES TO CHAPTER 3 215
CHAPTER 3
is socialized.
6. Writes Mises, 'The essential mark of socialism is that one will alone acts.
It is immaterial whose will it is. The director may be anointed king or a dic-
tator, ruling by virtue of his charisma, he may be a Fuehrer or a board of
Fuehrers appointed by the vote of the people. The main thing is that the
employment of all factors of production is directed by one agency only" (L.
v. Mises, Human Action, Chicago, 1966, p.695).
10. Incidentally, this proves that a socialized economy will be even less
productive than a slave economy. In a slave economy, which of course also
suffers from a relatively lower incentive to work on the part of the slaves, the
slaveholder, who can sell the slave and capture his market value privately,
would not have a comparable interest in extracting from his slave an amount
of work which reduces the slave's value below the value of his marginal
product. For a caretaker of labor no such disincentive exists. Cf. also G.
Reisman, Government Against the Economy, New York, 1979.
11. Cf. H. H. Hoppe, Eigentum, Anarchie und Staat, Opladen, 1987, esp.
Chapter 5, 3.2.
12. To be sure, Russia was a poor country to begin with, with little accumu-
lated capital to be drawn on and consumed in an "emergency." On the
socio-economic history of Soviet Russia cf. B. Brutzkus, Economic Planning
NOTES TO CHAPTER 3 217
in Soviet Russia, London, 1935; also, e.g., A. Nove, Economic History of the
USSR, Harmondsworth, 1969; also S. Wellisz, The Economies of the Soviet
Bloc, New York, 1964.
14. On everyday life in Russia cf., e.g., H. Smith, The Russians, New York,
1983; D.K. Willis, Klass. How Russians Really Live, New York, 1985; S.
Pejovich, Life in the Soviet Union, Dallas, 1979; M. Miller, Rise of the Rus-
sian Consumer, London, 1965.
15. Cf. L Erhard, the initiator and major political exponent of post-war
economic policy, Prosperity through Competition, New York, 1958; and The
Economics of Success, London, 1968. For theoreticians of the German
"soziale Marktwirtschaft" cf. W. Eucken, Grundsaetze der Wirtschaftspolitik,
Hamburg, 1967; W. Roepke, A Humane Economy, Chicago, 1960; the same,
Economics of a Free Society, Chicago, 1963. For a critique of the West Ger-
man economic policy as insufficiently capitalist and ridden with inconsisten-
cies which would lead to increasingly socialist interventions in the course of
time cf. the prophetic observations by L v. Mises, Human Action, Chicago,
1966, p.723.
16. For comparative studies on the two Germanys cf. E. Jesse (ed.), BRD
und DDR, Berlin, 1982; H. v. Hamel (ed.), BRD-DDR. Die Wirtschaftssys-
teme, Muenchen, 1983; also K. Thalheim, Die wirtschaftliche Entwicklung
der beiden Staaten in Deutschland, Opladen, 1978.
An honest but naive empirically minded comparative study which il-
lustrates that at best, economic statistics has very little to do with reality as
perceived by acting persons is P. R. Gregory and R.C. Stuart, Comparative
Economic Systems, Boston, 1985, Chapter 13 (East and West Germany).
For a valuable critique of economic statistics cf. 0 . Morgenstern, National
Income Statistics: A Critique of Macroeconomic Aggregation, San Francis-
co, 1979. For an even more fundamental criticism cf. L v. Mises, Theory of
Money and Credit, Irvington, 1971, part II, Chapter 5.
CHAPTER 4
15. Traditionally, this approach has been favored, at least in theory, by or-
thodox Marxist socialism-in line with Marx' famous dictum in his "Critique
of the Gotha Programme," (K. Marx, Selected Works, vol. 2, London, 1942,
p.566), "from each according to his ability, to each according to his needs."
Economic reality, however, has forced the Russian-style countries to make
considerable concessions in practice. Generally speaking, an effort has in-
deed been made to equalize the (assumedly highly visible) monetary income
for various occupations, but in order to keep the economy going, con-
siderable difference in (assumedly less visible) nonmonetary rewards (such
as special privileges regarding travel, education, housing, shopping, etc.)
have had to be introduced.
Surveying the literature, P. Gregory and R. Stuart (Comparative
Economic Systems, Boston, 1985), state:"... earnings are more equally dis-
tributed in Eastern Europe, Yugoslavia and the Soviet Union than in the
United States. For the USSR, this appears to be a relatively new
phenomenon, for as late as 1957, Soviet earnings were more unequal than
the United States." However, in Soviet-style countries "a relatively larger
volume of resources... is provided on an extra market bases..." (p.502). In
conclusion: "Income is distributed more unequally in the capitalist countries
in which the state plays a relatively minor redistribute role... (United States,
Italy, Canada). Yet even where the state plays a major redistributive role
(United Kingdom, Sweden), the distribution of incomes appears to be slight-
ly more unequal than in the planned socialist countries (Hungary, Czechos-
lovakia, Bulgaria). The Soviet Union in 1966 appears to have a less
egalitarian distribution of income than its East European counterparts"
(p.504). Cf. also, F. Parkin, Class Inequality and Political Order, New York,
1971, esp. Chapter 6.
18. On the following cf. also R. Merklein, Griff in die eigene Tasche, H-
amburg, 1980; and Die Deutschen werden aermer, Hamburg, 1982.
20. Cf. on this A. Alchian, 'The Economic and Social Impact of Free Tuition"
in: A. Alchian, Economic Forces at Work, Indianapolis, 1977.
222 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
CHAPTER 5
1. On the following cf. in particular M. N. Roth bard's brilliant essay "Left and
Right: The Prospects for Liberty" in the same, Egalitarianism as a Revolt
Against Nature, Washington, 1974.
3. Cf. H. Pirenne, Medieval Cities. Their Origins and the Revival of Trade,
Princeton, 1974, Chapter5, esp. pp.126ff; alsocf. M. Tigarand M. Levy, Law
and the Rise of Capitalism, New York, 1977.
8. a . LTigarand M. Levy, Law and the Rise of Capitalism, New York, 1977.
10. Cf. F. A. Hayek (ed.), Capitalism and the Historians, Chicago, 1963.
12. In spite of their generally progressive attitude, the socialist left is not en-
tirely free of such conservative glorifications of the feudal past, either. In
their contempt for the "alienation" of the producer from his product, which
of course is the normal consequence of any market system based on
division of labor, they have frequently presented the economically self-suf-
ficient feudal manor as a cozy, wholesome social model. Cf., for instance,
K. Polanyi, The Great Transformation, New York, 1944.
16. On liberalism, its decline, and the rise of socialism cf. A. V. Dicey, Lec-
tures on the Relation Between Law and Public Opinion in England during
the Nineteenth Century, London, 1914; W. H. Greenleaf, The British Politi-
cal Tradition, 2 vols., London, 1983.
20. Cf. on the following M. N. Rothbard, Power and Market, Kansas City,
1977, pp.24ff.
23. Cf. G. Reisman, Government Against the Economy, New York, 1979.
For an apologetic treatment of price-controls cf. J. K. Galbraith, A Theory of
Price Control, Cambridge, 1952.
24. G. Reisman, Government Against the Economy, New York, 1979, p. 141.
25. On the politics and economics of regulation cf. G. Stigler, The Citizen
and the State. Essays on Regulation, Chicago, 1975; M. N. Rothbard, Power
and Market, Kansas City, 1977, Chapter 3.3; on licenses cf. also M. Fried-
man, Capitalism and Freedom, Chicago, 1962, Chapter 9.
26. Cf. also B. Badieand P. Birnbaum, The Sociology of the State, Chicago,
1983, esp. pp.107f.
28. Cf. Badie and Birnbaum, The Sociology of the State, Chicago, 1983.
NOTES TO CHAPTER 5 227
CHAPTER 6
1. Cf. on the classical positlvist position A.J. Ayer, Language, Truth and
Logic, New York, 1950; on critical rationalism K. R. Popper, Logic of Scien-
tific Discovery, London, 1959; Conjectures and Refutations, London, 1969;
and Objective Knowledge, Oxford, 1973; on representative statements of
empiricism-positivism as the appropriate methodology of economics cf. e.g.
M. Blaug, The Methodology of Economics, Cambridge, 1980; T. W. Hutchin-
son, The Significance and Basic Postulates of Economic Theory, London,
1938; and Positive Economics and Policy Objectives, London, 1964; and
Politics and Philosophy of Economics, New York, 1981; also M. Friedman,
'The Methodology of Positive Economics," in: M. Friedman, Essays in Posi-
tive Economics, Chicago, 1953; H. Albert, Marktsoziologie und
Entscheidungslogik, Neuwied, 1967.
7. All of this has been brought home to Popperianism, mainly byT. S. Kuhn,
The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago, 1964; and it was then P.
Feyerabend who drew the most radical conclusion: to throw out science's
claim to rationality altogether, and to embrace nihilism under the banner
"everything goes" (P. Feyerabend, Against Method, London, 1978; and
Science in a Free Society, London, 1978). For a critique of this unfounded
NOTES TO CHAPTER 6 229
8. Cf. on this and the following A. Pap, Semantics and Necessary Truth,
New Haven, 1958; M. Hollis and E. Nell, Rational Economic Man,
Cambridge, 1975; B. Blanshard, Reason and Analysis, La Salle, 1964.
11. M. Hollis and E. Nell remark: "Since every significant statement is, for
a positivist, analytic or synthetic and none is both, we can ask for a clas-
sification .... We know of no positivist who has tried to produce empirical
evidence for statements of (the sort in question). Nor can we see how to
do so, unless by arguing that this is a matter of fact how people use terms
... which would prompt us to ask simply 'So what'?" (M. Hollis and E. Nell,
Rational Economic Man, Cambridge, 1975, p.110).
13. Cf. I. Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, in Kant, Werke (ed. Weischedel),
Wiesbaden, 1956, vol. II, p.45.
14. This, of course, is a Kantian idea, expressed in Kant's dictum that "reason
can only understand what it has itself produced according to its own design"
(Kritik der reinen Vernunft, in: Kant, Werke (ed. Weischedel), Wiesbaden,
1956, vol. II, p.23).
15. Cf. on this P. Lorenzen, "Wie ist Objektivitaet in der Physik moeglich";
230 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
20. Causality, then, is not a contingent feature of physical reality, but rather
a category of action, and as such, a logically necessary trait of the physical
world. This fact explains why in spite of the possibility explained above of
immunizing any hypothesis against possible refutations by postulating ever
new uncontrolled variables, no nihilistic consequences regarding the under-
taking of causal scientific research follow (cf. note 7 above). For if it is un-
derstood that natural science is not a contemplative enterprise but ultimately
an instrument of action (cf. on this also J. Habermas, Knowledge and Human
Interests, Boston, 1971, esp. Chapter 6), then neither the fact that
hypotheses can be immunized nor that a selection between rival theories
may not always seem possible (because theories are, admittedly, under-
determined by data) ever affects the permanent existence of the rationality
criterion of "instrumental success." Neither immunizing hypotheses nor
referring to paradigmatic differences makes anyone less subject to this
criterion in whose light every theory ultimately proves commensurable. It is
the inexorability of the rationality criterion of instrumental success which ex-
plains why-not withstanding Kuhn, Feyerabend et al.-the development of
the natural sciences could bring about an ultimately undeniable, constant
technological progress.
On the other hand, in the field of human action, where, as has been
demonstrated above, no causal scientific research is possible, where predic-
tive knowledge can never attain the status of empirically testable scientific
hypotheses but rather only that of informed, not-systematically teachable
foresight, and where in principle the criterion of instrumental success is thus
inapplicable, the spectre of nihilism would seem indeed to be real, if one
were to take the empiricist methodological prescriptions seriously.
However, not only are these prescriptions inapplicable to the social scien-
ces as empirical sciences (cf. on this H. H. Hoppe, Kritik der kausalwis-
senschaftlichen Sozialforschung, Opladen, 1983, esp. Chapter 2); as I show
here, contrary to the empiricist doctrine according to which everything must
be tried out before its outcome can be known, a priori knowledge regard-
ing action exists, and apodictically true predictions regarding the social
world can be made based on this a priori knowledge. It is this, then, that
proves all nihilistic temptations unfounded.
232 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
24. On the effects of minimum wages cf. also Y. Brozen and M. Friedman,
The Minimum Wage: Who Pays?, Washington, 1966.
25. On the effects of rent control cf. also C. Baird, Rent Control: The Peren-
nial Folly, San Francisco, 1980; F. A. Hayek et al., Rent Control: A Popular
Paradox, Vancouver, 1975.
CHAPTER 7
1. For such a position cf. A. J. Ayer, Language, Truth and Logic, New York,
1950.
On the emotivist position cf. C. L Stevenson, Facts and Values, New
Haven, 1963; and Ethics and Language, London, 1945; cf. also the instruc-
tive discussion by G. Harman, The Nature of Morality, New York, 1977; the
classical exposition of the idea that "reason is and can be no more than the
slave of the passions" is to be found in D. Hume, Treatise on Human Nature,
(ed. Selby-Bigge), Oxford, 1970.
4. For various "cognitivist" approaches toward ethics cf. K. Baier, The Moral
Point of View, Ithaca, 1958; M. Singer, Generalization in Ethics, London,
1863; P. Lorenzen, Normative Logic and Ethics, Mannheim, 1969; S. Toul-
min, The Place of Reason in Ethics, Cambridge, 1970; F. Kambartel (ed.),
Praktische Philosophie und konstruktive Wissenschaftstheorie,
Frankfurt/M., 1974; A. Gewirth, Reason and Morality, Chicago, 1978.
Another cognitivist tradition is represented by various "natural rights"
theorists. Cf. J. Wild, Plato's Modern Enemies and the Theory of Natural
Law, Chicago, 1953; H. Veatch, Rational Man. A Modern Interpretation of
Aristotelian Ethics, Bloomington, 1962; and For An Ontology of Morals. A
Critique of Contemporary Ethical Theory, Evanston, 1968; and Human
Rights. Fact or Fancy?, Baton Rouge, 1985; L Strauss, Natural Right and
History, Chicago, 1970.
9. It might be noted here that only because scarcity exists is there even a
problem of formulating moral laws; insofar as goods are superabundant
("free" goods) no conflict over the use of goods is possible and no action-
coordination is needed. Hence, it follows that any ethic, correctly con-
ceived, must be formulated as a theory of property, i.e., a theory of the
assignment of rights of exclusive control over scarce means. Because only
then does it become possible to avoid otherwise inescapable and unresolv-
able conflict. Unfortunately, moral philosophers, in their widespread ig-
norance of economics, have hardly ever seen this clearly enough. Rather,
236 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
like H. Veatch (Human Rights, Baton Rouge, 1985, p.170), for instance, they
seem to think that they can do without a precise definition of property and
property rights only to then necessarily wind up in a sea of vagueness and
ad-hoceries. On human rights as property rights cf. also M. N. Rothbard,
The Ethics of Liberty, Atlantic Highlands, 1982, Chapter 15.
12. This, for instance, is the position taken by J. J. Rousseau, when he asks
us to resist attempts to privately appropriate nature given resources by, for
example, fencing them in. In his famous dictum, he says, "Beware of listen-
ing to this impostor; you are undone if you once forget that the fruits of the
earth belong to us all, and the earth itself to nobody" ("Discourse upon the
Origin and Foundation of Inequality among Mankind" in: J. J. Rousseau,
The Social Contract and Discourses (ed. G. Cole), New York, 1950, p.235).
However, it is only possible to argue so if it is assumed that property claims
can be justified by decree. Because how else could "all" (i.e., even those
who never did anything with the resources in question) or "nobody" (i.e., not
even those who actually made use of it) own something-unless property
claims were founded by mere decree?!
13. On the problem of the deriveability of "ought" from "is" statements cf.
W. D. Hudson (ed.), The Is-Ought Question, London, 1969; for the view that
the fact-value dichotomy is an ill-conceived idea cf. the natural rights litera-
ture cited in note 4 above.
17. On the idea of structural violence as distinct from physical violence cf.
D. Senghaas (ed.), Imperialismus und strukturelle Gewalt, Frankfurt/M.,
1972.
The idea of defining aggression as an invasion of property vaiues also un-
derlies the theories of justice of both J. Rawls and R. Nozick, however dif-
ferent these two authors may have appeared to be to many commentators.
For how could he think of his so-called difference-principle-"Social and
economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are... reasonably ex-
pected to be to everyone's-including the least advantaged one's-ad-
vantage or benefit" (J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, 1971,
pp.60-83; see also pp.75ff)-as justified unless Rawls believes that simply by
increasing his relative wealth a more fortunate person commits an aggres-
sion, and a less fortunate one then has a valid claim against the more for-
tunate person only because the former's relative position in terms of value
has deteriorated?! And how could Nozick claim it to be justifiable for a
"dominant protection agency" to outlaw competitors, regardless of what
their actions would have been like (R. Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia,
New York, 1974, pp.55f)? Or how could he believe it to be morally correct
to outlaw so-called nonproductive exchanges, i.e., exchanges where one
party would be better off if the other one did not exist at all, or at least had
nothing to do with it (as, for instance, in the case of a blackmailee and a
blackmailer), regardless of whether or not such an exchange involved physi-
cal invasion of any kind (ibid., pp.83- 86), unless he thought that the right
existed to have the integrity of one's property vaiues (rather than its physi-
cal integrity) preserved?! For a devastating critique of Nozick's theory in
particular cf. M. N. Rothbard, The Ethics of Liberty, Atlantic Highlands, 1982,
Chapter 29; on the fallacious use of the indifference curve analysis,
employed both by Rawls and Nozick, cf. the same, 'Toward a Reconstruc-
tion of Utility and Welfare Economics," Center for Libertarian Studies, Oc-
casional Paper No. 3, New York, 1977.
18. Cf. also M. N. Rothbard, The Ethics of Liberty, Atlantic Highlands, 1982,
238 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
p.46.
20. It should be noted here, too, that only if property rights are conceptual-
ized as private property rights originating in time, does it then become pos-
sible to make contracts. Clearly enough, contracts are agreements between
enumerable physically independent units which are based on the mutual
recognition of each contractor's private ownership claims to things acquired
prior to the agreement, and which then concern the transfer of property tit-
les to definite things from a specific prior to a specific later owner. No such
thing as contracts could conceivably exist in the framework of a late-comer
ethic!
NOTES TO CHAPTER 8 239
CHAPTER 8
2. On the theory of the state cf. M. N. Rothbard, 'The Anatomy of the State,"
in: the same, Egalitarianism As A Revolt Against Nature, Washington, 1974;
For A New Liberty, New York, 1978; and The Ethics of Liberty, Atlantic High-
lands, 1982; H. H. Hoppe, Eigentum, Anarchie und Staat, Opladen, 1987;
cf. also A. Herbert, The Right and Wrong of Compulsion by the State (ed. E.
Mack), Indianapolis, 1978; H. Spencer, Social Statics, London, 1851; F. Op-
penheimer, The State, New York, 1926; A. J. Nock, Our Enemy, the State,
240 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
Delevan, 1983; cf. also J. Schumpeter's remark directed against then as now
prevalent views, notably among economists, that 'the theory which con-
strues taxes on the analogy of club dues or the purchase of a service of,
say, a doctor only proves how far removed this part of the social sciences
is from scientific habits of minds" (J. Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and
Democracy, New York, 1942, p. 198).
4. D. Hume, Essays, Moral, Political and Literary, Oxford, 1971, p. 19; cf.
also E. de La Boetie, The Politics of Obedience: The Discourse of Volun-
tary Servitude, New York, 1975.
5. The classical exposition of the idea that in the "state of nature" no distinc-
tion between "just" and "unjust" can be made and that only the state creates
justice is to be found in T. Hobbes, Leviathan, Oxford, 1946. That this
"positivistic" theory of law is untenable has been implicitly demonstrated in
Chapter 7 above. In addition, it should be noted that such a theory does
not even succeed in doing what it is supposed to do: in justifying the state.
Because the transition from the state of nature to a statist system can of
course only be called justified (as opposed to arbitrary) if natural (pre-statist)
norms exist that are the justificatory basis for this very transition.
For modern positivists cf. G. Jellinek, Allgemeine Staatslehre, Bad Hom-
burg, 1966; H. Kelsen, Reine Rechtslehre, Wien, 1976; for a critique of legal
positivism cf. F. A. Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty, 3 vols., Chicago,
1973-79.
6. For the classical exposition of this view of politics cf. N. Machiavelli, The
Prince, Harmondsworth, 1961; cf. also Q. Skinner, The Foundations of
Modern Political Thought, Cambridge, 1978.
7. Cf. on this and the following, M. N. Rothbard, Power and Market, Kansas
City, 1977, pp.182f.
10. On the problem of a free market production of law and order cf. Chap-
ter 10 below.
13. F. Oppenheimer, System der Soziologie, Vol. II, Der Staat, Stuttgart,
1964. Oppenheimer sums up the peculiar, discriminatory character of state-
provided goods, in particular of its production of law and order, in this way
(pp.322-323): 'the basic norm of the state is power. That is, seen from the
side of its origin: violence transformed into might. Violence is one of the
most powerful forces shaping society, but is not itself a form of social inter-
action. It must become law in the positive sense of this term, that is, sociolo-
gically speaking, it must permit the development of a system of 'subjective
reciprocity': and this is only possible through a system of self-imposed
restrictions on the use of violence and the assumption of certain obligations
in exchange for its arrogated rights. In this way violence is turned into might,
and a relationship of domination emerges which is accepted not only by the
rulers, but under not too severely oppressive circumstances by their sub-
jects as well, as expressing a 'just reciprocity.' Out of this basic norm secon-
dary and tertiary norms now emerge as implied in it: norms of private law,
of inheritance, criminal, obligations, and constitutional law, which all bear
the mark of the basic norm of power and domination, and which are all
designed to influence the structure of the state in such a way as to increase
economic exploitation to the maximum level which is compatible with the
continuation of legally regulated domination." The insight is fundamental
that "law grows out of two essentially different roots (...): on the one hand,
out of the law of the association of equals, which can be called a 'natural'
right, even if it is no 'natural right,' and on the other hand, out of the law of
violence transformed into regulated might, the law of unequals."
14. Only the fact that democracy has become a sacred cow in modern
politics can explain why the extent to which the idea of majority rule is rid-
242 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
den with inner contradictions is almost generally overlooked: first, and this
is already decisive, if one accepts democracy as justified, then one would
also have to accept a democratic abolishment of democracy and a substitu-
tion of either an autocracy or a libertarian capitalism for democracy-and
this would demonstrate that democracy as such cannot be regarded as a
moral value. In the same way it would have to be accepted as justified if
majorities decided to eliminate minorities until the point at which there were
only two people, the last majority, left, for which majority rule could no longer
be applied, for logico-arithmetic reasons. This would prove once again that
democracy cannot in itself be regarded as justifiable. Or, if one did not want
to accept these consequences and instead adopted the idea of a constitu-
tionally limited, liberal democracy, one would at the same time have to admit
that the principles from which these limitations are derived must then be
logically more fundamental than the majority rule-and this again would point
to the fact that there can be nothing of particular moral value in democracy.
Second, by accepting majority rule it is not automatically clear what the
population is to which it should be applied. (The majority of which popula-
tion is to decide?) Here there are exactly three possibilities. Either one ap-
plies the democratic principle once again with regard to this question, and
decides to opt for the idea that greater majorities should always prevail over
smaller ones-but then, of course, there would be no way of saving the idea
of national or regional democracy, as one would have to choose the total,
global population as one's group of reference. Or, one decides that deter-
mining the population is an arbitrary matter-but in this case, one would have
to accept the possibility of increasingly smaller minorities seceding from
larger ones, with every individual being his own self-determining majority,
as the logical end point of such a process of secession-and once again the
unjustif iability of democracy as such would have been demonstrated. Third,
one could adopt the idea that selecting the population to which the majority
principle is applied is neither done democratically nor arbitrarily, but some-
how differently--but then again, one would have to admit that whatever this
different principle that would justify such a decision might be, it must be
more fundamental than the majority rule itself, and majority rule in itself must
be classified as completely arbitrary. Cf. on this M. N. Rothbard Power and
Market, Kansas City, 1977, pp.189ff., H. H. Hoppe, Eigentum, Anarchie und
Staat, Opladen, 1987, Chapter 5.
18. L Spooner describes the supporters of the state as falling into two
categories: "1. Knaves, a numerous and active class, who see in the govern-
ment an instrument which they can use for their own aggrandizement or
wealth. 2. Dupes-a large class, no doubt-each of whom, because he is al-
lowed one voice out of millions in deciding what he may do with his own
person and his own property, and because he is permitted to have the same
voice in robbing, enslaving, and murdering others, that others have in rob-
bing, enslaving and murdering himself, is stupid enough to imagine that he
is a 'free man,1 a 'sovereign,' that this is a 'free government,' 'the best govern-
ment on earth,' and such like absurdities" (L Spooner, No Treason. The
Constitution of No Authority, Colorado Springs, 1973, p. 18).
CHAPTER 9
2. On the function of profit and loss cf. L v. Mises, Human Action, Chicago,
1966, Chapter 15; and "Profit and Loss," in: the same, Planningfor Freedom,
South Holland, 1974; M. N. Rothbard, Man, Economy and State, Los An-
geles, 1970, Chapter 8.
10. Thus states J. W. McGuire, Business and Society, New York, 1963,
pp.38-39: "From 1865 to 1897, declining prices year after year made it dif-
ficult for businessmen to plan for the future. In many areas new railroad links
had resulted in a nationalization of the market east of the Mississippi, and
even small concerns in small towns were forced to compete with other, often
larger firms located at a distance. At the same time there were remarkable
advances in technology and productivity. In short it was a wonderful era for
the consumer and a frightful age for the producers especially as competi-
tion became more and more severe."
11. Cf. on this G. Kolko, The Triumph of Conservatism, Chicago, 1967; and
Railroads and Regulation, Princeton, 1965; J. Weinstein, The Corporate
Ideal in the Liberal State, Boston, 1968; M. N. Rothbard and R. Radosh
(eds.), A New History of Leviathan, New York, 1972.
246 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
12. G. Kolko, The Triumph of Conservatism, Chicago, 1967, pp.4-5; cf. also
the investigations of M. Olson, The Logic of Collective Action, Cambridge,
1965, to the effect that mass organizations (in particular labor unions), too,
are not market phenomena but owe their existence to legislative action.
13. On the following cf. L v. Mises, Socialism, Indianapolis, 1981, part 3.2;
and IHuman Action, Chicago, 1966, Chapters 25-26; M. N. Rothbard, Man,
Economy and State, Los Angeles, 1970, pp.544ff; pp.585ff; and "Ludwig von
Mises and Economic Calculation under Socialism," in: L Moss (ed.), The
Economics of Ludwig von Mises, Kansas City, 1976, pp.75-76.
14. Cf. F. A. Hayek, Individualism and Economic Order, Chicago, 1948, esp.
Chapter 9; I. Kirzner, Competition and Entrepreneurship, Chicago, 1973.
16. Cf. on the following in M. N. Rothbard, Man, Economy and State, Los
Angeles, 1970, Chapter 10, esp. pp.586ff; also W. Block, "Austrian Monopo-
ly Theory. A Critique," in: Journal of Libertarian Studies, 1977.
17. L v. Mises, Human Action, Chicago, 1966, p.359; cf. also any current
textbook, such as P. Samuelson, Economics, New York, 1976, p.500.
NOTES TO CHAPTER 9 247
18. Cf. M. N. Rothbard, Man, Economy and State, Los Angeles, 1970, Chap-
ter 10, esp. pp.604-614.
19. M. N. Rothbard, Man, Economy and State, Los Angeles, 1970, p.607.
20. L v. Mises, "Profit and Loss," In: Planning for Freedom, South Holland,
1974, p. 116.
CHAPTER 10
2. lbid.,p.4.
4. Cf. on the following M. N. Rothbard, Man, Economy and State, Los An-
geles, 1970, pp.883ff; and 'The Myth of Neutral Taxation," in: Cato Journal,
1981; W. Block, "Free Market Transportation: Denationalizing the Roads,"
in: Journal of Libertarian Studies, 1979; and "Public Goods and Exter-
nalities: The Case of Roads," in: Journal of Libertarian Studies, 1983.
of consumption. Hence, the state would have to take over the provision of
such goods. (A movie theater, for instance, might only be half-full, so it might
be "costless" to admit additional viewers free of charge, and their watching
the movie also might not affect the paying viewers; hence the movie would
qualify as a public good. Since, however, the owner of the theater would
be engaging in exclusion, instead of letting free riders enjoy a "costless" per-
formance, movie theaters would be ripe for nationalization.) On the
numerous fallacies involved in defining public goods in terms of non rival-
rous consumption cf. notes 12 and 16 below.
7. Cf. on this W. Block, "Public Goods and Externalities," in: Journal of Liber-
tarian Studies, 1983.
10. Cf. for instance, the ironic case that W. Block makes for socks being
public goods in "Public Goods and Externalities," in: Journal of Libertarian
Studies, 1983.
11. To avoid any misunderstanding here, every single producer and every
association of producers making joint decisions can, at any time, decide
whether or not to produce a good based on an evaluation of the privateness
or publicness of the good. In fact, decisions on whether or not to produce
public goods privately are constantly made within the framework of a market
economy. What is impossible is to decide whether or not to ignore the out-
come of the operation of a free market based on the assessment of the de-
gree of privateness or publicness of a good.
12. In fact, then, the introduction of the distinction between private and
public goods is a relapse into the presubjectivist era of economics. From
the point of view of subjectivist economics no good exists that can be
categorized objectively as private or public. This, essentially, is why the
second proposed criterion for public goods, i.e., permitting nonrivalrous
consumption (cf. note 6 above), breaks down, too. For how could any out-
side observer determine whether or not the admittance of an additional free
rider at no charge would not indeed lead to a reduction in the enjoyment of
250 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
13. Cf. P. Samuelson, 'The Pure Theory of Public Expenditure," in: Review
of Economics and Statistics, 1954; and Economics, New York, 1976, Chap-
ter 8; M. Friedman, Capitalism and Freedom, Chicago, 1962, Chapter 2; F.
A. Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty, vol. 3, Chicago, 1979, Chapter 14.
15. Cf. on this argument M. N. Rothbard, 'The Myth of Neutral Taxation," in:
Cato Journal, 1981, p.533. Incidentally, the existence of one single anar-
chist also invalidates all references to Pareto-optimality as a criterion for
economically legitimate state action.
16. Essentially the same reasoning that leads one to reject the socialist-
statist theory built on the allegedly unique character of public goods as
defined by the criterion of nonexcludability, also applies when instead, such
goods are defined by means of the criterion of nonrivalrous consumption
(cf. notes 6 and 12 above). For one thing, in order to derive the normative
statement that they should be so offered from the statement of fact that
goods which allow nonrivalrous consumption would not be offered on the
free market to as many consumers as could be, this theory would face ex-
actly the same problem of requiring a justifiable ethics. Moreover, the
utilitarian reasoning is blatantly wrong, too. To reason, as the public goods
theorists do, that the free-market practice of excluding free riders from the
252 A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism:
Economics, Politics, and Ethics
17. The most prominent modern champions of Orwellian double talk are J.
Buchanan and G. Tullock (cf. their works cited in note 3 above). They claim
that government is founded by a "constitutional contract" in which everyone
"conceptually agrees" to submit to the coercive powers of government with
the understanding that everyone else is subject to it, too. Hence, govern-
ment is only seemingly coercive but really voluntary. There are several evi-
NOTES TO CHAPTER 10 253
18. M. N. Rothbard, Man, Economy and State, Los Angeles, 1970, p.887.
19. This, first of all, should be kept in mind whenever one has to assess the
validity of statist-interventionist arguments such as the following, by J. M.
Keynes ('The End of Laissez Faire," in: J. M. Keynes, Collected Writings,
London 1972, vol. 9, p.291): 'The most important Agenda of the state relate
not to those activities which private individuals are already fulfilling but to
those functions which fall outside the sphere of the individual, to those
decisions which are made by no one if the state does not make them. The
important thing for government is not to do things which individuals are
doing already and to do them a little better or a little worse: but to do those
things which are not done at all." This reasoning not only appears phony,
it truly is.
21. Incidentally, the same logic that would force one to accept the idea of
the production of security by private business as economically the best solu-
tion to the problem of consumer satisfaction also forces one, as far as moral-
ideological positions are concerned, to abandon the political theory of
classical liberalism and take the small but nevertheless decisive step (from
there) to the theory of libertarianism, or private property anarchism. Clas-
sical liberalism, with L. v. Mises as its foremost representative in this cen-
tury, advocates a social system based on the fundamental rules of the
natural theory of property. And these are also the rules that libertarianism
advocates. But classical liberalism then wants to have these laws enforced
by a monopolistic agency (the government, the state)-an organization, that
is, which is not exclusively dependent on voluntary, contractual support by
the consumers of its respective services, but instead has the right to
unilaterally determine its own income, i.e., the taxes to be imposed on con-
sumers in order to do its job in the area of security production. Now,
however plausible this might sound, it should be clear that it is inconsistent.
Either the principles of the natural property theory are valid, in which case
the state as a privileged monopolist is immoral, or business built on and
NOTES TO CHAPTER 10 255
26. Cf. the literature cited in note 21 above; also: B. Leoni, Freedom and
the Law, Princeton, 1961; J. Peden, "Property Rights in Celtic Irish Law," in:
Journal of Libertarian Studies, 1977.
29. Contrast this with the state's policy of engaging in battles without having
everyone's deliberate support because it has the right to tax people; and
ask yourself if the risk of war would be lower or higher if one had the right
to stop paying taxes as soon as one had the feeling that the state's handling
of foreign affairs was not to one's liking!
30. And it may be noted here again that norms that incorporate the highest
possible degree of consensus are, of course, those that are presupposed
by argumentation and whose acceptance makes consensus on anything at
all possible, as shown in Chapter 7.
31. Again, contrast this with state-employed judges who, because they are
paid from taxes and so are relatively independent of consumer satisfaction,
can pass judgments which are clearly not acceptable as fair by everyone;
and ask yourself if the risk of not finding the truth in a given case would be
lower or higher if one had the possibility of exerting economic pressure
whenever one had the feeling that a judge who one day might have to ad-
judicate in one's own case had not been sufficiently careful in assembling
and judging the facts of a case, or simply was an outright crook.
Cambridge, 1967.
1952.
1978.
1966.
REFERENCES 261
1960.
and Friedman, R. The Tyranny of the Status Quo. New York, 1984.
1985.
Frankfurt/M., 1983.
dianapolis, 1981.
1978.
Hohmann, H. H., Kaser, M., and Thalheim, K. (eds.). The New Economic
1983.
1978.
1976.
REFERENCES 265
Keynes, J. M. The End ofLaissez Faire (Collected Writings, Vol. IX). Lon-
don, 1972.
heim, 1966.
REFERENCES 267
Paul, R. and Lehrman, L The Case for Gold. San Francisco, 1983.
Studies, 1977.
Pirenne, H. Medieval Cities. Their Origins and the Revival of Trade. Prin-
ceton, 1978.
York, 1972.
L. Moss (ed.). The Economics of Ludwig von Mises. Kansas City, 1976.
Washington, 1974.
Frankfurt/M., 1979.
Springs, 1973.
1975.
Strauss, L Natural Right and History. Chicago, 1970.
Tannehill, M. and Tannehlll, L The Market for Liberty. New York, 1984.
Tigar, M. and Levy, M. Law and the Rise of Capitalism. New York, 1977.
Wild, J. Plato's Modern Enemies and the Theory of Natural Law. Chicago,
1953.
1978.
Index
Note: A figure in parentheses following a page number indicates the number of a reference note on that page.
Senghaas, D., 237 (17) Toulmin, S., 231 (19), 233 (4)
Singer, M., 231 (10), 233 (4) Treue, W., 227 (31)
Skinner, Q., 241 (6) Trivanovitch, V., 227 (32)
Smith, A., 69 Tullock, G., 244 (4), 248 (3), 251 (14),
Smith, H., 217 (14) 252(17)
Soares, M., 218 (6) Veatch, H., 233 (4), 234 (6), 235 (7),
Sombart, W., 227 (30) 236 (9)
Spencer, H., 239 (2) Vonnegut, K., 219 (12)
Spooner, L, 239 (1), 243 (18) Wagner, R., 244 (4)
Sterba, J., 238 (19) Weber, M., 215 (2)
Stevenson, C. L, 233 (1) Weinstein, J., 245 (11)
Stigler, G., 226 (25) Wellisz, S., 217 (12)
Strauss, L, 233 (4) Wicksell, K., 251 (14)
Stuart, R. C , 217 (16), 220 (15) Wild, J., 233 (4)
Szalai, A., 221 (17) Williams, B., 219 (14)
Tannehill, M. and L, 255 (22), Willis, D. K., 217 (14)
257(34) Windmoeller, E., 217(17)
Templeton, K. S., 219 (13, 14) Woolridge, W. C , 255 (22)
Tigar, M., 222 (3), 223 (8) Wright, D. McC, 223 (11), 224 (15),
Thalheim, K., 217 (13, 16) 225 (18)
Thirlby, J. F., 212 (5) Zapf, W., 221 (19)