Hermeneia - Nr. 25/2020
Jon MILLS*
Toward a Theory of Myth
Abstract: Myth has a convoluted etymological history in terms of its origins,
meanings, and functions. Throughout this essay I explore the signification,
structure, and essence of myth in terms of its source, force, form, object, and
teleology derived from archaic ontology. Here I offer a theoretic typology of myth
by engaging the work of contemporary scholar, Robert A. Segal, who places fine
distinctions on criteria of explanation versus interpretation when theorizing about
myth historically derived from methodologies employed in analytic philosophy and
the philosophy of science. Through my analysis of an explanandum and an explanans,
I argue that both interpretation and explanation are acts of explication that signify
the ontological significance, truth, and psychic reality of myth in both individuals
and social collectives. I conclude that, in essence, myth is a form of inner sense.
Keywords: myth, truth, sign, meaning, creativity
The term ―myth‖ is derived from the Greek muthos (μῦθος),
meaning word, speech.1 The term was used frequently by Homer (see Odyssey
II.561; Iliad 9.443; 19.242) and other ancient poets, especially referring to
the mere word. It is also referred to as public speech (Odyssey, I.358) as well as
conversation. When combined with the word logos (λόγος), such as in the
compound muthologia (μυθολογία), myth becomes a discourse on narrative.
Myth as word, speech, discourse generically refers to the thing said, as fact, or
matter at hand, as well as the thing thought, the unspoken word, revealing its
purpose or design. This may be why the migration of the term was closely
associated with the process of thinking itself: i.e., in Old Slavic, mysle is
equated with thought, as is smūainim in Old Irish, hence I think, perhaps
derived from the Indo-European mudh-, to think, to imagine.
When Heidegger (1927) discusses the concept of logos and truth
(ἀλήθεια), he tells us that ―discourse‖ as logos ―lets something be seen‖ by
making it manifest and accessible to another party (§ 7, B). Like muthos,
logos is a convoluted concept that has acquired many different meanings
throughout the history of philosophy. Λόγος is customarily translated as
―reason,‖ ―meaning,‖ ―judgment,‖ ―intelligence,‖ ―concept,‖ ―word,‖
―definition,‖ ―assertion,‖ ―ground,‖ and ―relationship,‖ which means it
always succumbs to interpretation. Heidegger argues that its original, basic
* Emeritus Professor of Psychology & Psychoanalysis at the Adler Graduate Professional
School in Toronto; email:
[email protected]
37
Toward a Theory of Myth
signification is ―discourse.‖ In fact, Heidegger specifically refers to the logos
that transpires in the speech act between interlocutors as the space where
signification is acquired ―in its relation to something in its ‗relatedness‘‖ (p.
58). Here ―interpretation‖ unfolds within a ―relationship‖ where potential
multiple meanings surface from a clearing based on a certain setting forth,
exhibiting, laying out, recounting, and so forth, which transparently applies
to any discourse on myth.
On the Signification of Myth
The transliteration of muthos as myth has acquired various
significations, many of which have centered around a story, tale (see Odyssey
3.94; 4.324), saying, legend, or proverb. But unlike in Homer, where there
is no distinction of true or false narratives (Odyssey II.492), modern and
contemporary references to myth have acquired a pejorative meaning that
stand in relation to derived etymologies from antiquity where discourse on
myth began to be viewed as fiction and fable (Plato, Phaedo, 61b; Republic,
377a; Aristotle, Meteorology, 356b1). Like logos, muthos implies no reference
to the truth or falsity of a narrative,2 it is merely the reason, the ground of
discourse, as matter of fact. Perhaps this is why when Robert Segal (2004)
defines myth as ―a story‖ (p. 4), he refrains from passing judgment on the
truth or falsity of its claims (p. 6).
Given that words, hence myths, stand in relation to a string of
signifiers where meaning is always descended from and connected to other
signifiers in an ontic chain of relations to various experiential things that are
signified in thought, myth will always retain a mercurial sense of
undecidability. It is only when we assign a circumscribed determinate
meaning that is conventionally adopted as a linguistic signifier or semiotic
operative within a particular discourse, culture, or socio-symbolic structure
that such undecidability is occluded. But this is merely a formal imposition
of grammar that does not erase the aporia or uncertainty of the term itself
and its chthonic ambiguity of meanings left open to interpretation, impasse,
and deferral to a web of unconscious relations where semiotic properties are
virtually infinite and indeterminate. It is for this reason that we prescribe
social conventions of meaning and construct operational definitions in
order to provide a structural template of fixed determinations of the
signification of certain words, while all along ignoring the relativity and
fluidity of discourse. Here mythos is just as much an affront on truth as is
any other mode of discourse, including science, with the exception that
some discourses are more persuasive than others.
If we accept the premise that any discourse by definition imports an
overdetermination of meaning, where undecidability, relativity, and an
38
Hermeneia - Nr. 25/2020
Jon Mills
infinite chain of semiotic deferrals leave an etymological uncertainty, or
have undergone historical transmogrifications and variations when applied
to other languages and cultures that efface the true question of origins, then
the most we can hope for in detecting any original meaning is the derivative,
the trace. This leads us to ask, What is the essence of myth? Can it be
deconstructed, so to speak, or analyzed in a manner that can advance our
ways in which we theorize about the theory of myth?
Toward a Theoretic Typology of Myth
What I am particularly interested in addressing are not specific
theories of myth, or specific myths themselves, but rather what constitutes a
good theory. As Segal (1999, p. 1) points out, myth is an applied subject that
always appeals to broader categories that are then in turn applied to the case
of myth. As a result, comparative and discipline-specific analyses of myth
tend to be dubious due to the arbitrary and turbid nature of the way in
which they vary in their approach to investigating myth. Furthermore, a
particular approach to theorizing already imports certain epistemological
assumptions about the very nature of the subject matter, such as what the
theory is supposed to do or be used for, or what it is about, or accounts for,
or signifies, what it is supposed to describe, and so on. For this reason,
many of the leading modern theorists of myth introduce explicit
presuppositions about the way things are in their very approach to myth,
such as myth is a subset of religion, accompanies ritual, serves a practical
function, is the primitive counterpart to science, or is a proto-logical view of
describing and explaining the physical world, the cosmos, gods, society, the
mind and human relations, the process of civilization, cultural artifacts and
values, and so forth. Here Segal (1999, p. 2) argues that comparative
theories of myth often engage answers to fundamental questions such as,
What is the (a) origin, (b) function, (c) subject matter or referent, and (d)
meaning of myth?
Let us attempt to expound upon this typology or principle of
categorization. First, What is myth about? Any reference to subject matter
already presupposes various ontological assertions, so let us begin with
origin. Origin is about foundations, archaic ground, hence history and
genesis. So whatever myth refers to, it must engage a point of origination,
which signifies both meaning and function, and is therefore overdetermined
in surplus and value on any discourse we adopt on myth. If we begin with
history and archaic ontology, where myth emerged, then we are by
definition adopting a discourse about being human even if we are attempting
to define a particular feature, function, and/or reason for positing myth. If
myth is always about something, then it imports ontology, namely, the
material world, culture, anthropology, cosmogony, the supernatural, and so
39
Toward a Theory of Myth
on despite the sociological and psychological functions they serve. So first
of all, myth is about ontology—what is purportedly real—even if only
symbolic or bears out to be a false claim.
The function of myth is varied, sociologically diverse, and ultimately
idiosyncratic to individual persons despite participating in common
collective beliefs and practices. Functions of myth may be designed to bind
social collectives, such as in religion, facilitate roles and rituals, or have
applied personal purposes and delineations, but they often serve a job or
pragmatic task, such as a utilitarian description, interpretation, observation,
deliberation, way of being, explanation, and/or expression of human
phenomena, even when the subject matter is not about the human being. In
this way, myth is about utility, service, helpfulness, and efficacy.
The meaning of myth can be (a) literal, (b) figurative, (c)
metaphorical, (d) symbolic, (e) semiotically circumscribed, such as in a
creed, doctrine, or ideology, and (f) imaginative, as suggested by its
etymology, which is always open to hermeneutics and fantasy. In this way,
myth can be personal and collective, hence universal regardless of its form
and content, and open to an infinite chain of significations, meaning
relations, and referents without being predetermined or confined in its
ostensive definition or purpose. In this way, both function and meaning
may be interdependent within a rubric of irreducibility. Although function
and meaning may operate outside of the ontic conditions of archaic ground,
they are not ontologically independent from origin. Following the principle
of sufficient reason, every event must stand in relation to an archaic object
that is derived from its origins, in this case, the phenomena of myth.
Critique of theory is often not discussed in the humanities: theory is
merely presumed according to discipline-specific norms. The same applies
to studies of myth, and theories about theoretics that are taken at face value
rather than critiqued for their disposition, structure, methodology,
epistemological verity, and viability as an explanatory model of knowledge.
This becomes even more nebulous if we concede that theory itself is a
limited medium to access the meaning of myth. Rather than critique the
value and limits of studies in mythology, we may see how sound theory is a
necessary requirement that guides research methodology. In general, theory
of myth should be:
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
40
descriptive,
coherent,
expository,
generalizable,
meaningful, and
pragmatic; namely, useful.
Hermeneia - Nr. 25/2020
Jon Mills
To what degree is theory and method arbitrary, contextual,
contingent, relative, personalized, exploratory––hence experimental, and
non-conclusive? Does theory only provide parameters for explanation and
meaning, or does it guide method? If so, are theory and method virtually the
same thing, or merely closely related even though they are subject to
categorical distinctions? If one is the framework in which meaning is
created and the other its application, then identity and similarity must be
differentiated by their modes of instantiation. When a method or
application is followed and posited to derive from and/or engender theory,
then the dialectical ontic nature of theory and method become more
difficult to differentiate as they are mutually implicative, and hence
interrelated. And if this is the case, how do they stand in relation to
individual and cultural differences, social and anthropological discrepancies,
historical and gender variances? And can a methodological approach to
myth, in theory, transpire without relying on theory? In other words, can a
methodology actually be executed devoid of any theoretic directing the
method or procedural actions themselves?
Every discipline has a set of theoretical orienting principles guiding
inquiry, research, and methodological process, whether presumptive or not.
Is this notion of criteria any different for the humanities versus the
empirical researcher? Perhaps this binary is unnecessary to evoke, for we
may make empirical observations on the social objectivity of the existence
of myth, but not necessarily on its cultural meanings, although we can
generally agree that the study of myth reflects the human, semiotic, and
hermeneutical sciences without devolving into the discourse of natural
science.
It was Dilthey (1883) who proposed the distinction between the
human sciences based upon investigating and understanding the
motivations and meanings inherent to the experiential subject or human
being versus that of the natural sciences, which is concerned with the
impersonal forces and organizations of nature. Whereas the
Geisteswissenschaften focus on the science of mental processes and social
systems within a class of human events, the Naturwissenschaften focus on the
domain of the natural world. Therefore, the bifurcation that is often forged
between the human and natural sciences takes as its premise that nature and
human experience are mutually exclusive categories. However, the
distinction lies in the methodology and discourse each discipline employs.
What was crucial for Dilthey in positing distinctions between the natural
and human sciences is the pivotal concept of ―lived experience‖ (Erlebnis),
the irreducibility of subjectivity that prereflectively (unconsciously)
encounters the immediate presence of reality, that which is present ―to me‖
as an internal sense, not as a given external object or datum of
consciousness, but as an immediate internal mediacy. Here the subject41
Toward a Theory of Myth
object distinction is obscured, if not sutured: Psyche is the lifeworld
(Lebenswelt).
Although this nature vs. human science differentiation was met with
criticism due to the fact that human subjectivity and sociality are part of the
natural world, and that critics (from neo-Kantians such as Wilhelm
Windelband and Heinrich Rickert, as well as Freud) would claim are equally
open to scientific scrutiny and can, in principle, find simpatico, this
categorical distinction has nevertheless often been employed to distinguish
the humanities from the physical sciences. But regardless of which approach
we adopt, we cannot evade making ontological assertions. To say that a
linguistic, semiotic, or scientific paradigm describes or explains a
phenomenon, even if mired in uncertainty and impasse, is to evoke a
referent that it is still about something. The mode of discourse does not
displace the signified object(s) in question. We cannot elude the question of
truth and realism no matter what discourse we adopt. Metaphysics always
has a way of coming back to bite our back.
The subject matter within a human science model is that of the
experiential person and collective social life contextualized within a genus of
human events; and impersonal aspects of the natural world are not typically
part of its scope or locus. But myth has very often been historically offered
as statements of explanation about the natural world. Yet, because human
sciences are interpretive and target the meaning of experience, by definition
they become hermeneutic. Because myth is necessarily predicated on human
speech and language, and involves the pursuit of understanding human
motivation and constructing meaning through interpretive intersubjective
exchange, it may be considered a hermeneutic science.
For Dilthey and others, interpretation, understanding (Verstehen), or
comprehension becomes a method for investigating the human sciences in
relation to life-contexts, while the natural sciences are confined to sensory
observation, description, testing, and explanation of causality and their
effects. However, this distinction is not devoid of certain problems
especially when rules or criteria for understanding may become opaque or
overlap, as they do in the social sciences where methods of
comprehensibility straddle the two methodological domains. Here it can be
argued that hermeneutics never fully escapes the charge of slipping into
relativism or recalcitrant subjectivism, given that, following certain rules of
discourse versus what someone ―really meant,‖ can easily be two different
things. The same applies to the scientific method where testability,
verification, and falsifiability are subject to epistemic interpretation rather
than pristine explanatory objectivity. Likewise, exegetical interpretation of a
text or deconstructive praxis, and the application of that interpretation, may
readily transform or alter it from its original meaning or purpose, even if we
presuppose a hermeneutic circle. In other words, the very act of translation
42
Hermeneia - Nr. 25/2020
Jon Mills
itself institutes reinterpretations of interpretations that can potentially spin
on in circularity or regress to a point that meaning is foreclosed from its
original signification.
Segal on Myth
Robert A. Segal is arguably one of the most accomplished
contemporary scholars of myth. Throughout his vast writings on the topic,
Segal‘s stylistic approach to theorizing about myth is to assume and
exegetically articulate the positions of various theorists on myth, particularly
those after the rise of modernity, only to add his own critique. He generally
shies away from taking a stance on the truth or falsity of myth, instead
focusing on its origin and function, but there is a tension in his thinking
influenced by his affinity for exactitude and science. Segal has largely
adopted methodologies derived from Anglo-American analytic philosophy,
logical positivism, and the philosophy of science with particular historical
resonances to Russell, A.J. Ayer, Quine, Kuhn, Popper, and Grünbaum,
which he has applied to his studies on myth, anthropology, and religion. He
particularly focuses on distinctions between explanation and interpretation
championed by R.G. Collingwood (1946), William Dray, Peter Winch, and
Gilbert Ryle (1971) as they are related to natural, social, and human science
categories.
Although Segal generally analyzes why myths arise and examines the
purpose they serve, he also becomes preoccupied with how theorists offer
either interpretations or explanations about the structure and verity of myth.
For example, the views of Tylor and Frazer who claim that myth is the
primitive counterpart to modern science make myth incompatible with
science, which is assumed to be true, and so hence makes myth false,
despite the fact that they both serve different functions. Myth here is taken
literally. By contrast, the view of myth as anything but archaic or
prescientific either sidesteps the question or else makes myth true, but only
true symbolically or psychologically. In other words, this form of truth only
applies to human nature or society, but not the physical world. Eliade,
Malinowski, Bultmann, Jonas, Freud, and Jung would mainly fall into this
camp. So here myths are not about material reality, only psychic reality;
whether individual or collective is a matter of emotional identification with
the subject matter mediated through imagination.
Regardless of the historical origins and functions of myth, much of
Segal‘s analyses revolve around myth as an explanation of the world,
whether antiquated, incorrect, or simply a false claim in relation to science is
moot. But why does myth have to meet the challenge of science? Science
merely explains while myth may serve many functions science cannot. But
this all depends upon what we mean by science, hence to know (< Lat.
43
Toward a Theory of Myth
scientia, from scire, to understand). In the social sciences—psychoanalysis for
instance, to offer a theory that explains psychological conditions and states
of mind within social collectives, myth attempts to present the complexity
of intrapsychic, intersubjective, and communal arrangements within a given
culture, an unconscious manifestation of the need to make the unconscious
conscious. For psychoanalysis, myth reveals in disguised forms all of
humanity‘s desires, conflicts, defences, emotions, traits, dispositions,
longings, and complexes that expose the personal and collective plight of
humankind. Here myth has psychological significance for masses and
functions in psychic economy unconsciously. Myth serves to symbolize
culture and the symbolic value inherent in culture. In this way, myth as
functionalism serves the overdetermined systems of society, and provides
regulation to constant change, such that there is order, purpose, and
structure to sociocultural networks via the narrative. A narrative in turn
provides meaning, which is at once open to interpretation, even when
attempts at explanation fail. Yet the notion of explanation is itself
controversial.
For Segal (2014a), ―Explanation provides causes. Interpretation
provides meanings‖ (p. 25). In comparing Max Weber, Clifford Geertz, and
Paul Ricoeur, he notes an ―ontological‖ difference between explanation and
interpretation: causality is physical, while meaning is mental or psychical.
Although Weber (1968, v1, pp. 4-5; 21-21) collapses the distinction and
makes mentation a causal process in its own right, akin to psychoanalysis,
whereas psychic meaning is determinative, Geertz maintains a division on
their incompatible ways in which they account for intentional behavior and
their consequential effects. For Geertz (1973, p. 43), interpretation applies
to a particular, while explanation applies to a universal or generality. Ricoeur
(1981, pp. 155, 158, 161), on the other hand, wants to maintain the
reconcilable compatibility or consilience between explanatory and
interpretive methodologies because they harmonize one another and
provide answers to different questions, at once explanatory as well as
interpretive (Segal, 2014a, p. 29). In the end, Segal believes that Ricoeur‘s
conciliatory attempt fails because he fails to keep the distinctions apart:
reconciling meanings with causes becomes our task at hand, and Segal
(2014a, p. 33) seems to be more comfortable with reducing meaning to
cause.
According to Segal (2014b), ―Any explanation starts with the effect
and works backwards to the cause‖ (p. 93). But why should explanation
predicate causality? For Segal (2009, pp. 69-72), if I read him correctly, an
explanation is a reference to ―proof‖ and ―causality,‖ which requires
―testing,‖ hence a privileging of empiricism, objectivity, and the scientific
method, while other theories of explanation may rest on metaphysical
foundational principles wedded to logic, non-contradiction, and internally
44
Hermeneia - Nr. 25/2020
Jon Mills
coherent argumentation. Sometimes theories of explanation clash with one
another, especially when they do not conform to the tenets of scientific
experimentation, testability, verification, falsifiability, validity, replication,
and reliability of measures. But this privileging of one method over another
may simply be begging the question of a master discourse on method,
especially when science reiterates its own ideologies when it fails to explain
phenomena outside of its narrow scope of empirical observation,
description, and experimentation that cannot control for variables,
environments, and measurements that fall outside of the laboratory (Mills,
2015). That is why myth is part of the humanities and not the natural
sciences.
As the gadfly of the Jungian world, Segal has offered a sustained
critique of Jung. Recently he has applied his scheme of scientific critique
using the categories of explanation versus interpretation to interrogate
Jung‘s theory of myth, but it is the scheme that I wish to examine here
rather than Jungian theory, as I find it applicable to any critique of myth.
Segal (2014b, pp. 82-84) believes that any good theory that is scientific must
be testable, and that we simply cannot assume tenets or propositions
without arguing for them. Nothing serious or worthy of merit is to be
presupposed. Nor are they applicable (hence generalizable) without solid
grounds for accepting them. And they must be predictive, not post hoc or
ex post facto constructions. At the very least, an internal criteria must be met
that satisfies the framework of a good theory, and this is what I would
impart to internal consistency that is coherent and non-contradictory, which
conforms to the parameters of what I would consider to be a sound theory
of myth. But a certain degree of external criteria must also be met, according
to Segal, to make it generalizable, hence valid. Not only is a good theory
applicable and subject to the probabilistic laws of predictability, any test
would have to address the viability of the theory: here testability
automatically assumes the theory will be subject to scrutiny. Will it pass
muster? Segal is also demanding evidence. No proposition is proof of
itself. Nothing can be predicated into existence, let alone assume others will
buy its applicability, meaningfulness, or pragmatic value. Evidence is
inexorable. It is an essential requirement, a necessary condition for any
theory to be true. But is it a sufficient condition? And what about
predictability? Should this be a defining theory of myth like it is of science?
Is this not a category mistake?
Segal (2014b) makes an important claim: ―an interpretation must be
supported by an explanation‖ (p. 83). But we may ask, Why? And if so, is
there any real difference between the two? Segal singles out the criterion of
―persuasiveness‖ as a central feature in how a theory is applied. It seems to
me that both an interpretation and an explanation must satisfy the criterion
of persuasiveness if a theory is to have any merit. For Segal (1992), as for
45
Toward a Theory of Myth
the hermeneuticists, an interpretation applies to meaning, while an
explanation applies to the question of origin—why a myth was created and
lasts. But a meaningful interpretation may also apply to an explication of the
accounts of origin. They need not be binary categories or antinomies. They
may be mutually implicative and ontically interdependent, what Segal calls
―interlocking.‖ There is no need to cleave them off from each other as they
are both operative within any meta-representational framework that
addresses the meaning, origin, and function of theory.
When Segal (2014b) defines the meaning of ―explanation,‖ he is
referring to ―the account—of mind, the world, culture, or society—that is
presupposed by the interpretation‖ (p. 83). So here explanation and
interpretation are not bifurcated even though we could argue that an
interpretation is an attempt to provide a meaningful explication of events or
a state of affairs, while an explanation is a cryptic form of interpretation
disguised as certitude. In the end, Segal insists that a good theory of myth
be justified, is generalizable, and predictive, not simply the ability to
interpret a story.
From Explanandum to Explanans
An explanandum describes a phenomenon to be explained, not the
phenomenon itself, while an explanans seeks to adduce an answer or
explanation to account for the phenomenon—its reason(s), purpose,
origins, and so forth. While the explicandum is that which gets explicated, the
explicans is that which gives the explication. Although an explanation
attempts to account for the coming into being of a phenomenon, it is more
than that. It always implies, if not literally evokes, the question of causality
by attempting to explain the ground or preconditions that bring something
about, such as certain antecedent events or the necessary conditions (not
sufficient ones) that are temporally and materially a priori. So contrary to
predicate or propositional logic, which is merely concerned with the
meaning of words or expressions and their formal systemic relations and
operations, or statements that make something comprehensible, an
explanans is much more far-reaching—it is about ontology.
On the one hand, an interpretation is an attempt to describe a
phenomenon, on the other, an explanation attempts to offer more, that is,
how and why a phenomenon occurs. But so does an interpretation—each
are about explication. So how does an interpretation differ from an
explanation? When applied to the question of myth, I argue that both
interpretive and explanatory models are equally making ontological claims,
even if they are tarrying in epistemic uncertainty when it comes to the
question of causality. Recall that for the ancients, a cause (αιτία) was the
46
Hermeneia - Nr. 25/2020
Jon Mills
reason or explanation for something happening, which is always
overdetermined.
If myth is a declarative attempt to make phenomena
comprehensible, then we must contend that it is offering an explanation of
phenomena, even if contestable, or it would not have any currency to grant
meaning to the human mind. Whether it is true or false is another issue, one
we should adjourn for now. The prowess of myth over the eons seems to
coalesce into many different meaning structures that wed interpretation,
explanation, emotion, feeling, aesthetics, parable, morality, spirituality, and
higher rational insights into a psychic medium that is historically and
culturally enshrined within the development of human civilization. To say
that myth is merely about one thing, or serves merely functions—
psychological, sociological, anthropological, and so on—is to miss the point
that myth is ultimately about ontology, about what it signifies, that which is
ultimately real, even if presented as fiction or fantasy. In other words, the
imaginary is real. And anytime we evoke the notion of what is really real, we
cannot bracket or suspend the question of determinism. But why should we
grant the narrative—the ―story‖—the status of offering a theory of
causality? Why should we assume an explanans has anymore epistemological
weight or verity to phenomenal description—to the explanandum? Does not
an explanation have multiple threads, multiple significations, hence an
overdetermination and surplus of meaning and value, not to mention
causal-semiotic strands of deferral to an infinite chain of associations and
signifiers? This logically implies that no single explanation is ever complete
or unequivocally valid, rather only a partial attempt at conceptualizing and
describing phenomena.
The Truth of Myth and the Myth of Truth
Eliade (1963) adopts a particular view held by archaic societies that
myth means a ―true‖ story, whether literally or a narrative believed to be
true by relevant social collectives, which holds sacred socioreligious
significance of transcendental spiritual value explicating ―beginnings‖ or the
coming into existence of reality itself by supernatural provenance. Since the
Western epistemological turn in modernity, and the hermeneutical narrative
turn in more contemporary postmodern times, we may concede that our
understanding and consensus of the meaning of ―truth‖ remains hotly
contested. Whether we adopt Eliade‘s affinities for supernaturalism or not,
his position that myth narrates sacred history is itself an explanation, for it
attempts to delineate a causal factor in positing an account of ―creation‖—
the ground of archaic ontology from which myth arises. Here Eliade may be
accused of obfuscating truth with reality.3 One person‘s truth may be their
47
Toward a Theory of Myth
psychic reality subject to relativism, illusion, projection, and fantasy, if not
delusion, hence their phenomenal experience of the world, while another
demands that reality must conform to the stronghold of objective
(demonstrated and proven) empirical and material facts in order to be flown
under the banner of truth, a debate we do not have to continue at length
here.
If interpretive and explanatory models are used to describe and lend
understanding to phenomena, which always evoke the question of ontology,
as I argue, then they inevitably engage the questions of truth and
epistemology, even if unintended or silent on the matter. What does this
imply? This would suggest that any discourse on myth simultaneously
speaks about epistemic verity and/or the truth or falsity of its predications
or claims. But what do we mean by truth? If mythos and logos cannot elude
the question of truth, then would not any discourse on truth equally imply
that a certain mythology is at play? The myth that there is Truth, as if it
were a single, unified condition, entity, or unquestionable empirical state of
affairs that transcends all phenomenal realities and fulfills every epistemic
criterion imaginable is simply a fantasy. If this were otherwise, then no one
would be debating the question, scope, and meaning of truth. It would
simply be accepted as given, as part of our natural thrownness. As I have
critiqued elsewhere (Mills, 2014), discourse on truth is not about
―correctness‖ or so-called empirical facts, rather it is about what
phenomenally appears in the real world of ontic relations. Both the methods
of interpretation and explanation are making propositional assertions about
truth-claims, and truth-claims stand in relation to what they ultimately
signify or represent, namely, onto-phenomenal conditions.
Truth may be better understood by revisiting the ancient notion of
aletheia (ἀλήθεια), where truth is defined as a process of disclosedness or
unconcealedness. Truth appears as the manifestation of particularized
expressions of the psyche-in-society that have their source in an
unconscious ontology teleologically motivated to disclose itself. This applies
to myth, or humanity would never have invented such discourse to begin
with, for it speaks to a collective need to understand and recapitulate
archetypal experience of-and-in the world. Here the very conditions for
truth to be disclosed must be conditioned on unconscious experience. Myth
as disclosure through discourse reveals the unconcealed longings of the
human race to describe, interpret, and explain human experience that could
not be articulated otherwise before the age of reason and science. But even
today, such mythic language can never be replaced by the antiseptic
discourse of science, for staid or stolid approaches to explicating lived
experience never live up to the psychological needs for satisfaction,
48
Hermeneia - Nr. 25/2020
Jon Mills
emotionality, and enjoyment. It is a primal phenomenon arising from the
pulsional desire to interpret, expatiate, and know the world.
The truth of myth is both a universal and particularized form of
disclosedness—an appearance of a much more complex process that may
only reveal itself a bit at a time as partial unconcealment—as event, a
moment, an instance. We must graft more meaning structures onto our
interpretations to expand and complicate them, where there are richer and
more robust and variegated theories that fall under the categorical rubric of
what we call explanation. For example, the theory of evolution is an
interpretation of human origin, but is it not an unqualified explanation,
albeit plausible and scientifically probable. It is very much a scheme or set
of hypotheses that have explanatory power. Evolutionary biology may very
well be a necessary condition but not a sufficient one to explain human
origins. The same equally applies to myth. Myth, like religion, attempts to
answer to origins—to ontology—as does physics and evolution, only on the
condition that it is a narrative about origins, hence an interpretation of
human experience and valuation—itself a phenomenon or appearance of
our psychic expressions signifying something that is purportedly attempting
to transcend human subjectivity, namely, archaic ontology. But given that
myth is universal to humanity, only the particularities vary, any theory of
myth must concede that it is merely a partial explanans of the explanandum.
Can a myth be true, or is it by definition false? Notice the binary
logic involved in the question, presuming that the predicate ―true‖ is valued
over that which is ―false.‖ This question always stands in relation to
epistemology and the discursive or procedural methods we adopt, as well as
the definitions we attribute to the signifier ―truth.‖ Is truth merely about
correctness, internal consistency, logical form? If so, this conforms to a
theory of discourse we as collectives or cultures define through semantic or
linguistic convention. Or is it about fact? But how do we determine fact and
evidence independent of human consensus? Even scientific models of
metaphysical realism that profess to ―discover‖ truth and ―natural laws‖
cannot escape from our human subjectivity in offering interpretations of
those laws, even when submitted to rigorous testing exposing the problems
of verification, falsification, replication, reliability, validity, observation
selection effects, anthropic bias, and refutation of conjectures. All constants
evolve, change, mutate, and rematerialize in other forms—the
transmogrification of reality. From physics to myth, humanity cannot help
but invent and reinvent its own so-called truths. Explanation is as much a
myth at explicating causality as is science; yet the matter becomes not truth,
but rather plausibility based on statistical probabilities and predictive
validity, the gambling intellect that places value in attempting to predict
possible future conditions and events. Science predicts as it explains, while
myth is an explanation of interpretation, itself predictable.
49
Toward a Theory of Myth
The Essence of Myth
A proper theory of myth must have several components. We have
identified four thus far: (1) referent, (2) origin, (3) meaning, and (4)
function. Setting aside the subject matter, let us start with origin, and I will
compare this to archaic ontology appropriating Aristotle‘s categorization of
causality as our guide. I wish to avoid the, at times, simplistic
(parsimonious) models of science, but they are subsumed in a more
comprehensive explication of determinism, or more appropriately,
overdetermination (Mills, 2013), so I will include them here without
succumbing to reductionism.
A myth must have a (1) source, (2) force, (3) form, (4) object, and (5)
goal. Because mythology is archetypal, that is, it is rooted in the archaic
development of civilization and language, it is by definition a human
invention, hence a cultural phenomenon that makes attempts to explain via
consciousness (interpretation) origins, that is, the cosmos, gods, Being, and
so forth. Although the source is, strictly speaking, mediated through human
cognition, it attempts to answer to the question of fundamental ontology.
The force or essence of myth is process, or the revealed organizing principles
behind the narrative. The form is the organizational style, typology,
categorization, formula, patterning, and/or genre of the story, often
poetical, metaphorical, aesthetic, moralistic, and brimming with latent
meanings, usually revolving around the development of characters and plot
within metanarratives and meta-representations. As human linguistic
inventions, they are psychologically mediated through imagination, so
imaginal properties suffuse mythic structure. The object of myth refers to
contents, properties, place, context, contingencies, and fantasies, as by
contemporary definition myth is a fictional or illusory product of the
imagination, although it can be taken as real, literate, material, significatory,
and/or suggestive of a greater transcendental object or reality. But to a
minor degree, the object of myth (the overarching narrative or metastructure) is intimately linked with its goal, namely, its purpose. The purpose
or aim is both to interpret and explain—hence to assign meaning and value
to—the narrative.
Myth furthermore discloses an intent or telos, even if supple, hence
revealing the agency behind the story. Here the meaning of myth reveals the
emotional mind, and often has aesthetic and ethical dimensions and utilities
in conveying a message(s) that reverberates in the psyche and in social
collectives through identificatory unconscious resonances. Hence a myth
conveys or expresses the human soul. It is only the human being who can
generate and understand myth, even if professed to be about genesis or
come from an original cause outside the human mind.
50
Hermeneia - Nr. 25/2020
Jon Mills
As human creation, myth may be said to be socially constructed as
the ethos and expression of culture, or it can be solely individualistic,
subjective, and private. Although it is unconsciously motivated, and
displaces the vast array of human affects, conflicts, desires, defenses,
fantasies, and their compromises, it ultimately has a telos, purpose, or
objective, the goal of which is to communicate internal experience,
discharge pulsions, contain anxiety, and engender meaning that usually
transcends mere conscious intent. Here myth is overdetermined, that is, it
provides meta-meaning and has multiple functions that resonate on many
parallel processes of mentation.
With stipulations, it may also be argued that meaning and function
are equiprimordial, but without equating the two or collapsing them into the
same category: while all functions convey meaning they may not be
meaningful. They may be understood, have a practical structure, reason, and
so forth, but they may offer little or no psychological solace. Functions may
serve a purpose or have practicalities but may be devoid of value to the
psyche. Myths logically must transcend mere function, or they would cease
to lose all value, unless we were to concede that masses remain largely
unconscious of their need for myths and simply are conditioned sheep in
the meadow. But even if we were to yield this hypothesis, the sociological
organizations that promulgate and keep mythic discourse alive speak to
greater communal narratives of how myth serves both utility and meaning
in collectives, or it would have disappeared from socialization practices
altogether. The prime example is religion. Religion will never disappear
because it serves equiprimordial needs and meaning for humanity.
Myth is an inherent and indispensable aspect of human civilization
that disperses its particularities into the social fabric of every culture, which
has its own regional contents, contexts, and intent, yet it cannot stand
outside of its own origins, namely, human consciousness, even when its
subject matter is about cosmos, theos, and prebeginnings. Yet given that
consciousness is conditioned by unconscious process, following Freud and
Jung, we may conclude that myth is a collective unconscious projection of
its own mythical character. Because myth is the exteriorization of interiority,
myth becomes the realization of archaic unconscious ontology. As the selfexternalization of its own internal lived-value, conscious identification with
myth both validates and fulfills the felt-qualia of one‘s living interior or
feeling soul.
Hence qua myth annuls any claim to pure epistemology and
objectivity, even in science, because models of human knowledge by
necessity contain their own mythic structure. Here the meaning-making
powers of myth find their way into every conceivable venue in which we
construct, explain, and experience the world. Because myth is always the
expression of human imagination, and specifically unconscious fantasy, we
51
Toward a Theory of Myth
may conceive of myth, like the dream, as a symptom of humanity. Myth
communicates something to us and for us, hence it has a sense. Not only
does it have a function, meaning, and purpose, it makes sense. In its
essence, myth is a form of inner sense.
Notes
1 Initiated in the 19th Century, and now in its 9th revised edition, Liddell and Scott‘s GreekEnglish Lexicon is generally considered among classicists to be the finest compilation to date
of the classical works of antiquity where the etymological sources of ancient words derive
and correspond to contemporary linguistics and modes of discourse. All references to
μῦθος begin on p. 1151, Vol. 2.
2 See Anderson (2004, p. 61) for a discussion.
3 Eliade (1963) asserts that ―the myth is regarded as a sacred story, and hence a ‗true
history,‘ because it always deals with realities. The cosmogonic myth is ‗true‘ because the
existence of the World is there to prove it; the myth of the origin of death is equally true
because man‘s mortality proves it‖ (p. 6). Here we may say that Eliade is conflating myth
with an actual portrayal of history and that such a portrayal conveys actual realities, which
needs defined and demonstrated, hence proved. A myth may be true insofar as it is an
artifact of culture, but it does not mean that it signifies a true reality apart from the
experience of the subject or social collective. And just because the world exists does not
make the myth real or true apart from the believer. The existence of the world does not
remotely prove the reality of the myth other than it is an anthropological occasion or
psychological projection. Projections do not necessarily correspond to objective reality.
And just because we are mortal and die, does not mean that a myth of the origins of death
proves it any more than the biological fact that we cease to be, as any anatomist or
mortician will tell you.
References
Anderson, Albert A. (2004). Mythos, Logos, and Telos: How to Regain the Love of
Wisdom. In
A.A., Anderson, S.V. Hicks, & L. Witkowski (Eds.), Mythos and Logos: How to Regain the Love
of Wisdom. Amsterdam: Rodopi.
Aristotle. Meteorology. In J. Barnes (Ed.). The Complete Works of Aristotle. 2 Vols. (The revised
Oxford trans.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1984, pp. 555-625.
Collingwood, R.G. (1946). The Idea of History. T.M. Knox (Ed.). New York: Oxford
University Press.
Dilthey, W. (1883/1923). Introduction to the Human Sciences. R.J. Betanzos, Trans. Detroit:
Wayne State University Press, 1979.
Eliade, Mircea (1963). Myth and Reality. New York: Harper & Row.
Geertz, Clifford (1973). The Interpretation of Cultures. New York: Basic Books.
Heidegger, M. (1927). Being and Time. J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson (Trans.). San Francisco:
Harper Collins, 1962.
Homer.
(800
B.C.E.).
The
Odyssey.
Samuel
Butler
(Trans).
https://classics.mit.edu/Homer/odyssey.html
_____ The Iliad. Samuel Butler (Trans). https://classics.mit.edu/Homer/iliad.html
Liddell, H.G. & Scott, R. (1843). A Greek-English Lexicon. 2 Vols. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
52
Hermeneia - Nr. 25/2020
Jon Mills
Mills, Jon. (2015). Psychoanalysis and the Ideologies of Science. Psychoanalytic Inquiry,
35:24–44.
_____ (2014). Truth. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association, 62(2), 267-293.
_____ (2013). Freedom and Determinism. The Humanistic Psychologist, 41(2), 101-118.
Plato. Phaedo. In The Collected Dialogues of Plato, eds. E. Hamilton & H. Cairns.
Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1961, pp. 40-98.
_____ Republic. In The Collected Dialogues of Plato, eds. E. Hamilton & H. Cairns. Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1961, pp. 575-844.
Ricoeur, Paul (1981). Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences. Trans. & Ed., J.B.
Thompson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ryle, Gilbert (1971). Collected Papers. 2 Vols. London: Hutchinson.
Segal, Robert A. (2014a). Weber, Geertz, and Ricoeur on Explanation and Interpretation.
Bulletin for the Study of Religion, 43(1), 25-33.
_____ (2014b). Explanation and Interpretation. In R.A. Jones (Ed.), Jung and the
Question of Science, pp. 82-97. London: Routledge.
_____ (2009). Religion as Ritual: Roy Rappaport‘s Changing Views from Pigs of the
Ancestors (1968) to Ritual and Religion in the Making of Humanity (1999). In M.
Stausberg (Ed.), Contemporary Theories of Religion: A Critical Companion, pp. 66-82.
London: Routledge.
_____ (2004). Myth: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
_____ (1999). Theorizing About Myth. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press.
_____ (1992). Explaining and Interpreting Religion. New York: Lang.
Weber, Max (1968). Economy and Society, Vol. 1. Trans., E. Fischoff; Eds., G. Roth & C.
Wittich. New York: Bedminster Press.
53