1
Empowerment Through Self‐Subordination?: Microcredit and Women’s Agency
Serene J. Khader
Forthcoming in Poverty, Agency, and Human Rights
Oxford University Press, Diana Meyers, ed.
Poverty can undermine people’s agency. The poor often face restricted options
and develop limited senses of what they can be and do. According to Deepa Narayan’s
famous Voices of the Poor study, the poor themselves characterize their condition as
one of acute powerlessness (Narayan 2000, 38‐40). It thus seems logical that successful
antipoverty interventions should enhance agency. The idea of a tight correlation
between reduced poverty and increased agency has been so widespread in the
development community that, until quite recently, traditional poverty indicators often
functioned as proxies for agency (Alkire 2007, 10‐11.)
Data from the last fifteen years on how antipoverty interventions affect women
have called this correlation into question (Alkire 2007, 10‐11). Antipoverty interventions
often yield mixed results for women’s agency and empowerment. For example, some
studies suggest that income interventions do little to change women’s actual
involvement in remunerated economic activity (Goetz and Sen Gupta 1996). Some also
show that income interventions do nothing to change women’s sense of inferior
entitlement to household resources or decisionmaking authority (Sen 1999; Osmani
1998; Cheston and Kuhn 2002,19). Other studies suggest that increasing women’s
access to paid work decreases their political participation (Batliwala and Dhanraj 2007,
24), that increasing women’s access to education can accompany increased support for
female genital cutting (Agot 2007, 290)i, and so on. Underlying the puzzlement about
this data seems to be a line of reasoning roughly like this: reducing poverty increases
agency, and women’s empowerment is the increase in women’s agency, so reducing
women’s poverty should empower women.
A popular explanation of why antipoverty interventions sometimes seem to fail
to empower women is that empowerment is a process (Kabeer 1999; Kabeer 2001; Agot
2007; Nagar and Raju 2003). According to this explanation, the issue is not that
antipoverty interventions have failed to empower women; it is that they have not gone
far enough to utterly transform gender relations. This explanation is applied to
situations where antipoverty interventions seem to leave women’s gender status
untouched and ones where they seem to worsen gender inequality. For example, Susy
Cheston and Lisa Kuhn (2002) remark that microcredit interventions in Ghana have not
changed prevailing views about whether women should be allowed to lead men.
However, Cheston and Kuhn express optimism that women’s participation in mixed
gender banks will lead to increased comfort with women’s leadership in the wider social
world (2002, 38). Naila Kabeer goes farther and argues that what appear to be
worsening gender relations may actually be part of empowering processes. According to
her, the upsurge in domestic violence the accompanies microcredit is men really
resisting their impending loss of power (2001, 65‐66). According to such narratives,
antipoverty interventions can constitute steps in the right direction even when they fail
to directly challenge gender hierarchy.
2
In this chapter, I call for skepticism of the idea that antipoverty interventions
contribute to women’s empowerment by enhancing their agency. My claim is not
categorical; I believe antipoverty interventions can empower women. I am more
interested in how readily we should apply “steps in the right direction” explanations to
cases where antipoverty interventions fail to bring about feminist change. I will argue
that such explanations fail to take the following fact seriously: that increases in women’s
agency can result from decreases in the egalitarianism of gender relations. This
possibility is generated by what I call the “self‐subordination social recognition paradox”
or “SSRP.” The paradox is that women can often gain welfare by complying with and
internalizing oppressive norms. Access to many goods depends on social recognition,
and, under patriarchy, women often have to subordinate themselves to achieve social
recognition. The popular understanding of agency ignores this paradox by failing to
distinguish what I call “welfare agency”(the ability to enhance one’s welfare) from
feminist agency (the ability to identify and change sexist norms). On the popular
definition of agency, agency is a single good whose increase tracks increases in a
person’s sense of herself as equal. The possibility of women gaining agency by
increasing their investment in sexist norms is of more than theoretical interest, as I will
show in a discussion of microcredit interventions in South Asia. Microcredit, by
materially rewarding female seclusion and the view of women as collateral, may offer
women new reasons to act according to, and endorse ,patriarchal expectations.
When I say that antipoverty interventions can strengthen the incentives for
women to internalize and comply with sexist norms, I do not simply mean that they
“reinforce” or fail to change oppressive gender expectations. I will revisit claims that
antipoverty interventions can be criticized for “reinforcing” or failing to change gender
subordination in my conclusion. My claim about how antipoverty interventions affect
women’s agency is stronger in one sense and weaker in another. It is weaker in this
sense: I am agnostic about whether to call antipoverty interventions that leave gender
inequality intact “failures.” But my claim is stronger in that it suggests that failing to
empower women can have worse consequences than simply leaving inegalitarian
gender relations intact. Interventions may strengthen patriarchal structures by giving
women new incentives to do what they dictate and see them as just. Poverty sometimes
gives women reason to question the dictates of patriarchy. Antipoverty interventions
can decrease the force of those reasons by increasing the rewards for patriarchally
prescribed behavior.
The chapter unfolds as follows. I argue in the first section that “right direction”
explanations rely on an understanding of women’s empowerment that is
counterintuitive, inconsistent with common usage, and that excludes the possibility of
women increasing their agency by growing in their acceptance of oppressive norms.
Specifically, the operative notion of women’s empowerment conflates empowerment
with individual women’s ability to enhance their welfare. In the second section, I argue
that, access to benefits often depends on social recognition, and patriarchy creates
sexist conditions of social recognition. The upshot is that women often gain social and
material benefits from complying with patriarchal norms—and, where social and
material rewards for complying with patriarchal norms align, women also gain senses of
3
coherence and self‐esteem from internalizing them. It follows that increases in women’s
welfare agency often provide women new incentives to accept patriarchy. In the third
section, I examine Kabeer’s now‐famous argument that microcredit empowers women. I
argue that her inadvertent conflation of feminist and welfare agency causes her
sanguine interpretation of the mixed data on women and microcredit. Kabeer says
microcredit increases perceptions of women’s value, but I believe we must acknowledge
the fact that women are valued for their increased ability to meet patriarchal
expectations. In the conclusion, I ask what general lessons about assessing antipoverty
interventions we might draw from my analysis.
1. Defining Women’s Empowerment
The claim that antipoverty interventions impel women’s empowerment by
enhancing their agency trades on a distorting conflation. This conflation is of
enhancements in individual women’s welfare agency with women’s empowerment. An
intuitive understanding of the idea of women’s empowerment, as well as common
usage of the term, suggests that the concepts are nonidentical.
Development theorists tend to agree that empowerment involves the use of
conscientizing processes to increase a person’s ability to pursue her welfare (Nagar and
Raju 2003; Malhotra, Shuler, and Boender 2002;Kabeer 1999).ii Though many
philosophers allow that a person can agentically decide not to value her welfare,
development theorists tend to attribute cases where people fail to value their welfare
to lacks of agency.iii Call knowledge that one’s welfare is of value, coupled with the
ability to pursue it “welfare agency.” It may seem that women’s empowerment occurs
when each woman in a group experiences enhanced welfare agency. This idea is
conceptually fraught, for reasons I will explain in a moment.
First, let us observe that—at least intuitively‐‐ women’s empowerment requires
women’s increased ability and desire to agitate for more egalitarian gender relations.
When women are empowered, they act—or believe it is worth acting—in ways that
challenge women’s subordination. To say this is not to deny that women’s
empowerment comes in degrees; one may, for instance, start by questioning women’s
subordination in the political arena but not in the home‐‐ or one may have only an
inchoate sense that women’s subordination is wrong. My point is that interventions that
do nothing to affect the subordination of women, or women’s awareness of their own
subordination, do not empower women. Nor do interventions that increase women’s
subordination.
Though the term “women’s empowerment” is not used consistently in
development discourse, both mainstream and radical development actors use it in a
way that suggests that it entails opposition to gender hierarchy. Even the language of
the third Millenium Development Goal treats the goals of empowering women and
eliminating gender inequality as linked (United Nations). Most empowerment theorists
explicitly discuss women’s empowerment as involving action and/or conscientization
toward the end of decreasing sexist oppression (Nagar and Raju 2003; Mayoux 1998;
Swain 2007; Sen 1993 (cited in Malhotra, Shuler, and Boender 2002); Holvoet 2005).iv
Call the type of agency that challenges sexist norms‐‐ the type needed for women’s
empowerment‐‐ “feminist agency.”
4
The logical points that distinguish feminist and welfare agency are dual. First, an
agent’s welfare agency can be enhanced without her feminist agency being enhanced. I
may have more food in my stomach than I used to, for instance, and still give my
husband the best food—all the while believing this is the right thing to do. Second, an
agent’s welfare agency may be enhanced through decreases in her feminist agency.
Consider the case of women in South Asia who comply with sexist food distribution
norms to keep male relatives happy— and do so in contexts where their access to
virtually all goods depends on male guardianship.v Assume that these women are not in
a position to alter the “patriarchally risky”vi features of their society and thus decide to
stop wasting their time questioning their validity. These women reduce their feminist
consciousness and gender‐role violating actions to increase their welfare agency. Their
access to food, income, and security depend on their fulfilling subordinate gender roles.
If these two points are correct, the logical relationship between feminist and welfare
agency is this: they are nonidentical but may overlap. The same action may increase
both feminist and welfare agency—as in, say, the choice to leave an abusive husband in
a context where this does not expose a woman to further violence or cause economic or
social death.
The claim that it is sometimes not in women’s welfare interests to increase their
feminist agency may seem paradoxical. It may seem to entail the view that sexist norms
do not harm women. Here we need to remember that a norm is sexist primarily in virtue
of its harming women as a group (Frye 1983; Cudd 2006). To say that women can gain
welfare agency from complying with sexist norms is not to say that they gain it from the
existence of those norms. It is to say instead that, if the conditions under which the
norms obtain are fixed (which it is sometimes reasonable for women to assume),
individual women gain welfare agency from complying that they would not get from
resisting. It is certainly true that individual women usually experience negative effects
from complying with oppressive norms. But we need to remember—and a longer
discussion of this fact will be the topic of the next section—that patriarchal societies
often make behavior with inherently negative welfare effects a prerequisite for
accessing other goods that are also constitutive of welfare. Following Uma Narayan
(2002), I term this phenomenon “harm‐benefit bundling.” Take the case of a woman
who feeds superior food to her husband and suffers poor nutrition as a result. If
insisting on an equal claim tofood will result in the loss of male guardianship‐‐ and thus
potential loss of income, shelter, and safety—compromising her nutrition is probably a
welfare‐maximizing move. Of course, the real problem here is the structural constraint
on women’s options. But this does not change the fact that, if changing the structure is
out of a woman’s power, she can advance her welfare by doing what patriarchy
prescribes.vii
If an action may enhance a woman’s welfare agency while undermining her
feminist agency, successful antipoverty interventions may not always be as innocent as
they initially seem. We should be skeptical of the idea that successful antipoverty
interventions are always—or even usually— a) steps toward women’s empowerment or
b) neutral with respect to it. That women can gain welfare agency by trading away
feminist agency means that enhancing women’s welfare agency can happen at the
5
expense of women’s empowerment. We need to ask why recent empowerment
theorists insist that successful antipoverty interventions are either steps in the right
direction or, at worst, unrelated to women’s status.
The answer seems to lie in the mechanisms by which empowerment is supposed
to occur. Antipoverty interventions are supposed to work on people’s self‐concepts.
According to many empowerment theorists, antipoverty interventions empower women
by expanding their senses of what they are capable of. The pre‐empowered person
characteristically holds two attitudes—one toward herself and the other toward the
world. The attitude toward herself involves low self‐worth stemming from general self‐
devaluation. The attitude toward the world is one of uncritical acceptance of the power
status quo—a sense that gender inequality is just a part of the natural order of things.viii
Antipoverty interventions empower women, because a newfound sense of worth and/
or desire to question causes or manifests skepticism of patriarchal values. Arguments to
this effect abound in the microcredit literature. Kabeer argues that microcredit
increases women’s experience of being valued by others, and this causes women to
perceive themselves as capable of bargaining with their husbands (1998; 2001). Cheston
and Kuhn (2002,29‐30) argue that microcredit helps women gain greater senses of self‐
efficacy—even when this is simply increased efficacy at fulfilling traditional roles. They
assert that increased self‐efficacy often translates into a desire to challenge oppressive
structures. Linda Mayoux argues that women entrepreneurs have increased confidence
and skills and that the visibility of such women can increase women’ overall status
(2007, 39). Even skeptics seem to share the view that antipoverty interventions would
empower women if they successfully changed women’s beliefs about what they are
capable of. These theorists tend to argue—not that microcredit has negative impacts on
women’s self‐concepts—but rather that microcredit fails to empower women when it
fails to work on their self‐concepts. Simeen Mahmud argues that microcredit does not
expand women’s sense of what they are capable of because it tracks them into poorly
compensated tasks they were already doing anyway (2003,602‐603).
I believe this widely‐held view‐‐ that antipoverty interventions that enhance
women’s senses of self will increase their desire to change patriarchy—is based on two
faulty assumptions about agency. The first is what I call the “cumulative assumption.”
This assumption is that agency is an internally undifferentiated good whose quantity
necessarily increases when new options appear. When I speak of agency as internally
undifferentiated, I do not mean that an agent’s set cannot comprise distinct options.
The cumulative assumption, to the extent that it offers a theory of how new options
affect existent ones, treats options as distinct from one another.
Instead, the idea that agency is internally undifferentiated has two important
implications. First, new options do not affect agency primarily by changing its quality;
they change only the amount of agency present. Second, increases in agency should, in
principle, impel a process that leads to improvements across an agent’s life. An inability
to agitate for welfare in some domain of life reflects insufficient agency rather than a
lack of something distinct. Theorists who expect self‐worth to eventually permeate all
domains of a woman’s life seem beholden to the idea that more agency will become
feminist agency. Logically, the problem with the cumulative assumption is that it sees
6
options as self‐sufficient and thus lacks a concept of opportunity cost. It denies that new
options and beliefs about the self may eviscerate, or decrease the appeal of, others. As I
have mentioned, patriarchy rewards women for complying with it. Part of what this
means is that new options for welfare can remove incentives to resist patriarchy. I will
make this point more fully in the section on microcredit, but here is one example. In a
context that valorizes female seclusion, giving women opportunities to access income
without leaving the home decreases the appeal of challenging norms that demand
women’s seclusion.
The operative notion of agency in development discourse, in addition to suggesting
that agency is internally undifferentiated, suggests that it requires specific motivational
content. Increases in agency move a person toward the view that she has equal value. I
call this assumption “the substantive assumption,” because it sees agency as
culminating in a person’s adoption of certain substantive moral beliefs. The idea seems
to be that, the more effective a person’s welfare agency becomes, the more she will
adjust her self‐concept toward equality. One way this might work is by expanding
women’s senses of what they are capable of. When women discover they can engage in
activities that patriarchy tells them they are unfit for, they begin to question patriarchy.
Consider Cheston and Kuhn’s (2002, 29‐30) claim that women who are effective at
meeting their welfare needs will develop increased self‐esteem.This, in turn, is
supposed to cause dissatisfaction with sexist limitations on their lives. Consider also
Kabeer’s argument that women who bring income into households start believing they
have a right to ask for what they need within them (2001, 71). The problem with the
substantive assumption, when applied broadly, is that it denies that women can gain
self‐esteem and self‐efficacy by believing in the appropriateness of their subordination
and fulfilling subordinate roles well. For instance, a woman who is provides superior
food to her male relatives without complaint is likely to be regarded a good wife with a
particular talent for self‐discipline. Thinking I am getting better at feminine self‐denial is
unlikely to lead me to believe that women and men are equal.
2. The Self‐Subordination Social Recognition Paradox
The understanding of agency described above excludes the possibility that
women’s incentives to accept patriarchy can increase with their welfare agency.
Correlations between increased welfare agency and increased collusion with patriarchy
are likely to be common in patriarchal societies for reasons I will describe in this section.
The subordination‐social recognition paradox occurs because of a structural feature of
patriarchal societies. The SSRP is as follows: people’s access to social status, their ideas
about what they should become, and their access to material benefits often depend on
how well they meet social expectations. In patriarchal societies, women often need to
meet sexist social expectations to increase their welfare. For instance, women in the
contemporary United States are often penalized professionally for failing to conform to
patriarchal beauty standards. This means that they can increase their access to income
and social recognition (both objective goods) by wearing makeup and heels, being thin,
and so forth.
In the development context, the SSRP means interventions may simultaneously
increase women’s access to welfare and their incentives to accept patriarchal norms.
7
Interventions may do so by increasing the material or social rewards of patriarchally
prescribed behavior. Interventions may also strengthen the links between psychological
goods, such as self‐coherence and self‐respect, and acceptance of patriarchal beliefs.
Since the attainment of these psychological goods often enhances both objective
welfare and subjective happiness, this means that antipoverty interventions may go
farther than incentivizing compliance with sexist norms. They may incentivize their
internalization. Both complying with and internalizing oppressive norms can increase
women’s welfare agency.
Women’s incentives to internalize patriarchal norms are strongest when the
social and material rewards for acting on the basis of them align. Social benefits include
things like status, affiliation, approval, and love. In patriarchal societies, sexist norms
dictate the behavior required of “good women.” Women who comply with such norms,
especially those who do so particularly well, receive status and praise (or at least
protection from certain forms of criticism). The rewards of being a “good woman” often
extend beyond the glow of others’ approbation. How a person is perceived by others
often affects her ability to meet her material needs. As we have discussed, in poor
societies with high levels of patriarchal risk, women’s ability to access food, shelter, and
safety depends heavily on their marriageability and ability to keep male family members
happy (Agarwal 1997). This means that social benefits are often gateways to material
ones. A woman who is seen as a “good woman” will be well‐positioned to meet her
material needs.
But it is one thing to claim that women can benefit from behaving as “good
women” and another to claim that they can benefit from endorsing the ideology
surrounding that behavior. Women stand to benefit from internalizing oppressive norms
under conditions where they benefit both socially and materially from complying with
them. Under such conditions, internalizing oppressive norms facilitates development of
a coherent self‐concept. It is theoretically possible for a person to comply with sexist
norms for purely instrumental reasons. So, for instance, a woman may give better food
to her husband only to keep him happy while simultaneously rejecting the view that this
is what good woman should do. But a lifetime of “going through the motions” could also
be a lifetime of suffering, compromised self‐efficacy, and difficulty identifying one’s true
commitments. Some of the reasons that we can expect difficulty from a life of doing one
thing and believing another stem from general psychological mechanisms over which we
exert little control. We persuade ourselves that we are personally responsible for
positive outcomes of our behavior more than negative ones, we attempt to protect
reasons for optimism about our futures, we attempt to avoid cognitive dissonance, and
so forth (Cummins and Nistico 2002). Further, and more important to my overall
argument, psychological coherence enhances a person’s welfare agentic capacities. A
woman who can support her self‐efficacy by internalizing sexist views about herself has
self‐interested reasons to do so.
As Rawls observes in his explanation of the value of the primary good of (the
social basis of) self‐respect, it is difficult to pursue any plan of life without believing
oneself or one’s projects are of value. It is also difficult to pursue any plan of life one
thinks it is impossible to effectively pursue (1978, 441).ix For Rawls, a person’s sense
8
that her self and projects are of value supplies motivation for pursuing those projects.
Rawls also claims that self‐respect has a social basis. He thereby emphasizes how
difficult it is for us to remain motivated to pursue our projects absent social affirmation
of their (and our) value. An agent who repeatedly hears that her projects are worthless
may begin to believe it. In patriarchal societies, women learn that projects that would
promote their equality lack value. The woman who refuses to provide superior nutrition
to her husband, for example, is likely to be criticized, gossiped about, and worse. She
may grow to believe that she is defective (because she fails to meet standards of good
womanhood)‐‐ or that her project of criticizing sexist norms is morally suspect (because
the people around her treat her moral perspective as alien). Under such circumstances,
a woman can preserve self‐worth and motivation by internalizing sexist norms and
making her projects consistent with them.
In addition to providing motivation to pursue her projects, endorsing oppressive
norms can be an agent’s easiest path to maintaining a coherent self‐concept. As Diana
Meyers argues, “a reflective commitment to a set of values” can serve to “protect us
from others’ scorn” (1989, 212). If we believe our own evaluations to carry special
weight or our projects to be objectively valuable, we are not required to refashion our
self‐concepts every time others judge us. Though Meyers’ point applies most readily to
cases where an agent’s values clash with the dominant ones, it also points to the way
scorn from others may threaten an agent’s sense of identity—the sense that she is a
stable entity who cares about certain things. Acting against her deeply held beliefs to
avoid penalty, as does the agent who complies with oppressive norms without
internalizing them, may cause her to question whether she is really committed to what
she says she is committed to. Such uncertainty may cause her to act in inconsistent ways
that undermine her ability to achieve ends—welfare‐promoting or otherwise.x
Third, an agent’s sense of self‐efficacy depends partly on her ability to act
successfully in accordance with her principles. Compliance with oppressive norms often
demands behavior with painful effects. The life of the woman who has to conform to
oppressive norms often involves repeatedly subjecting oneself to suffering. The woman
who believes the suffering is unjustified but inevitable is also reminded daily that the
world is unfair and unchangeable. Adjusting one’s beliefs about what is justified is a way
of protecting oneself against the pain and self‐efficacy losses likely to come with
repeated failure.xi
My goal in the last few paragraphs has been to reveal an implication of the SSRP
that may not be initially apparent‐‐ that, under patriarchal conditions, a woman can
increase her welfare agency by internalizing oppressive norms. Part of my argument
that microcredit is less empowering than it initially seems will be that it furnishes new
reasons to believe in the moral acceptability of patriarchal norms. My point has
emphatically not been to show that internalizing oppressive norms is praiseworthy—or
even that it will usually yield welfare increases. The number of women who will benefit
from internalizing oppressive norms is limited. One reason is simple interpersonal
variation. It is clear that a woman who would not feel herself without a feminist identity
stands to gain less by internalizing sexist norms than one who has mixed feelings about
gender oppression. A second reason is that the force of the incentives to internalize
9
sexist norms varies. This type of variation is a function of differences in social structures
rather than individuals. The incentives to internalize patriarchal norms are likely to be
particularly weak when the rewards for complying are intermittent, difficult to access,
or not uniform. For instance, a woman may improve her shot at marrying into a higher
social class by being unusually attractive and dutiful. However, if this outcome is unlikely
for a given woman—and she knows this on some level—she has reason to protect her
self‐esteem by continuing to believe that beauty and duty are not true measures of a
person’s worth.
Similarly, and more important for my argument about antipoverty interventions,
incentives to internalize patriarchal norms are weaker when long and short‐term
rewards, or social and material rewards for complying with oppressive norms diverge.
Internalizing sexist norms is a particularly promising path to agentic coherence when an
agent is rewarded consistently and uniformly for conforming. Internalization will then
produce consistency between the agent’s beliefs about what is acceptable and the
external reinforcement she receives. External reinforcement is most uniform when
social and material rewards accrue to the same patriarchally prescribed behaviors.
Consider the case of a woman who gives superior food to her husband and who is not
terribly poor (and thus does not fall below some nutritional threshold). She is held up as
an example for women in her community and succeeds in attaining economic security
by capturing her husband’s favor. Suppose also there is no other way for her to gain an
equal level of income, security, or social recognition. This woman, if she believes sexist
food norms are unjustified, will be subject to cognitive dissonance, a lack of self‐efficacy,
and a sense of moral failure. She can do away with these threats to her agency and
sources of suffering by internalizing sexist norms. (To say this is not to deny that there is
an inherent harm in the sense of oneself as unequal; it is only to say that the harm is
outweighed by the other benefits.)
However, the rewards of internalization would differ if the material and social
rewards of complying with sexist food distribution norms diverged. Suppose
urbanization and globalization have changed men’s earning power such that women can
no longer count on men to provide for them effectively (as Mead Cain, Syeda Rokeya
Khanam, and ShamsunNahar (1978) argue they actually have in much of South Asia).
Suppose also that it is still widely believed that women should prioritize their husbands’
nutrition. It is far less clear that a woman living under these conditions stands to benefit
from internalizing patriarchal norms. Part of the reason is that this may lead her to
engage in welfare‐undermining behavior—to depend on her husband when there are
better ways of securing food and shelter (goods it might be worth risking social
ostracism to attain).xii Another reason internalizing patriarchal norms promises to be
less beneficial is that it requires suppressing impulses toward basic survival.
It may seem that, by treating women’s beliefs about patriarchy as partly
responsive to incentives, I assume that our normative attitudes are constantly shifting
or within our cognitive control. To respond to the concern about cognitive control, we
can note that changes to our beliefs about ourselves may, but need not, occur
consciously. The more troubling concern is about the relative stability most people’s
self‐concepts have achieved by adulthood. It may seem that people form self‐concepts
10
early in life, and they are not so mercurial as to change with social tides. I agree that
people rarely cast off their self‐concepts in adulthood. However, an agent can alter her
self‐concept in response to social conditions without completely rejecting her previous
views. Though adults typically have more robust and coherent self‐concepts than
children, the struggle for self‐integration is lifelong—and, for most of us, never fully
achieved. Adult women may become more or less attached to certain norms without
radically altering their self‐concepts. Moreover, if a woman’s self‐concept has always
been internally ambivalent despite containing some allegiance to patriarchal values,
identifying with previously unendorsed patriarchal norms can increase her self‐
coherence.
3. Does Microcredit Empower Women?
I have elaborated the SSRP as follows: women can gain welfare agency from
complying with and internalizing sexist norms, and the incentives to internalize sexist
norms are highest when women are both socially and materially rewarded for
complying with them. I now turn to discussing reasons for worry that microcredit
interventions align the social and material rewards of accepting sexist norms.
Microcredit is supposed to increase the perception of women’s value (by themselves
and others), but , as the SSRP reminds, women can gain increased value by getting
better at meeting , and believing in, patriarchal social expectations.
In the most comprehensive look at the data on women and microcredit in South
Asia to date, NailaKabeer attempts to reconcile contradictory conclusions about its
empowerment potential (1998, 2001). According to her “right direction” explanation,
the data that is usually adduced to show that microcredit fails to empower women
either relies on the wrong indicators or can be reinterpreted as evidence of women’s
empowerment. I believe that Kabeer’s inadvertent commitment to the cumulative and
substantive assumptions about agency causes her to misassess the cases in her dataset
that involve women’s increasing self‐subordination. The mechanisms through which
Kabeer sees women’s empowerment as occuring always involve enhanced ability to
meet oppressive social expectations. Kabeer underestimates the implications of this for
future gender relations. First, however, we should get clear about what Kabeer’s
findings are and which feminist critiques of microcredit she challenges.
The popular media have, nearly univocally , celebrated microcredit (Poster
and Salime 2002, Narayan 2005,Batliwala and Dhanraj 2007). However, a swirling
controversy has developed within feminist development studies. One set of feminist
criticisms is about the role microcredit plays in perpetuating global inequalities. For
instance, Winifred Poster and Zakia Salime (2002) argue that microcredit creates the
impression that it is a lack of credit—rather than an unjust global economic order—that
causes poverty in the global South. Uma Narayan (2005) argues that microcredit
programs serve an ideological function by masking the devastating effects of the
International Financial Institutions on the poor. I am sympathetic to these critiques of
the structural discursive effects of microcredit, but they are out of the scope of Kabeer’s
analysis—and mine.
Kabeer is interested in feminist critiques that assert that microcredit fails to
empower women. The studies that purport to show this use diverse indicators of
11
empowerment—all of which, however, are associated with the normative goal I called
“feminist agency” in the first section. Some studies suggest a positive correlation
between a woman’s loan recipient status and the level of domestic violence to which
she is exposed (Shuler, Hashemi, and Badal 1998; Aktaruzzaman and Guha‐Khasnobis
2012). Anne‐Marie Goetz and Rina Sen Gupta (1996) find that a large percentage of
recipients in Bangladesh transferred loans to their husbands and many had no idea what
had happened to their loans. Kabeer (1998) herself finds that some women loan
recipients are not involved in economically productive activity at all.
Nathalie Holvoet (2005, 86) sand Aminur Rahman (2001) observe that women are
frequently “forced” by their husbands to take out loans. Montgomery, Bhattacharya,
and Hulme (1986) note that, in most cases, microcredit does not change the gender
division of labor within households.
Kabeer argues that the data above are consistent with the view that microcredit
empowers women. Her argument has two parts. First, she argues that these data
demonstrate only that microcredit has failed to completely transform the patriarchal
conditions of women’s lives. Her reasoning is that the critical studies rely on end‐state,
rather than processual, indicators (Kabeer 2001, 66). Empowerment is a spectrum, and
determining whether women are becoming empowered is a matter of asking whether
they are moving in the right direction on the spectrum—not asking whether they have
arrived. Indicators like domestic violence and women’s control over loans could be
evidence that women are more empowered than they were before—even if they have
not “arrived.” (Domestic violence could be a move in the right direction because it is
signals threats to men’s power (Kabeer 2001, 65‐66)). Second, Kabeer argues that
women loanees see themselves as empowered, and that this should urge us to look for
indicators of empowerment that can do justice to their experiences (1998,18). The
women Kabeer interviewed expressed a particular set of reasons for valuing
microcredit. Other community and family members perceived women as having greater
worth, and women valued themselves more. Kabeer argues that this is expressed in
women’s increased bargaining power within households. Using household bargaining
ability as an empowerment indicator allows Kabeer to directly challenge the indicators
used by the microcredit critics. Where the critics focus on things like female “control,”
of loans, accounting processes, etc., Kabeer argues that focusing on control requires us
to ignore incremental growth in women’s involvement in decisionmaking.
Kabeer’s idea that microcredit increases women’s sense of self‐worth and the
value others attach to them is striking. It suggests an unusual mechanism of
empowerment—and one that triggers worries related to the SSRP. This is why: a
person’s sense of her own value and her value in the eyes of others are likely a function
of her ability to fulfill her prescribed role. If the person’s assigned role is subordinate,
increases in her value will probably track increases in her success at complying with and
internalizing oppressive norms. To put it starkly, saying that an oppressed person has
become empowered through gaining social value could just be another way of saying
that a person is (or is perceived as) getting better at accepting her subordination. Of
course, this is true only if prescribed roles do not become less hierarchcal as a result of
antipoverty interventions. It seems true that a large number of the women in Kabeer’s
12
sample have experienced changed gender expectations with regard to household
bargaining power and enterprise management. These are largely women from the
economically better off social strata.
For some women in Kabeer’s study, however, there is no reason to suppose that
microcredit has weakened patriarchal social expectations. There is reason to suspect
that the higher value placed on women comes from their increased ability either to
meet longstanding sexist expectations or to meet new versions of such expectations
that seem to have been generated by microcredit. I begin with examples of the second
type of case—women becoming successful at meeting new oppressive expectations. An
astonishing fact about many women in Kabeer’s sample (2001, 73) and those in some
other studies (Holvoet 2001), is that their value in the eyes of others seems to have
increased without their participation in any element of loan use. In other words, some
women turn loans over to male family members and do not participate at all in deciding
what is done with them. Yet these same women say that their husbands value them
more, that they are more socially accepted, and so forth. Though it is a minority of
women who report total male control of loans, it is also unclear why many of the
women who do participate in loan use are valued more. Specifically, it is not clear that
the increased valuation has to do with more egalitarian conceptions of what women can
and should do. A number of women appear to experience increased value for reasons
that have nothing to do with, or are tenuously related to, being perceived as more
competent entrepreneurs, managers, or decisionmakers.
What explains the new value placed on women, if it is not a newfound respect
for what women’s capabilities? Two alternative explanations suggest themselves—one
more pernicious than the other, but neither terribly sound evidence for concluding that
microcredit is empowering. The less pernicious mechanism seems to be the reduction of
scarcity within the household. According to the women in Kabeer’s study, men’s
inabilities to meet their households’ basic needs produces interfamilial tension that
often culminates in violence (2001, 70; 1998,39, 49‐51). The potentially more pernicious
mechanism involves the valuing of women because they are means of access to loans.
One interviewee offers the following analysis of the effect of loans in her community,
“Now husbands think, if we beat up our wives, they won’t give us loans, we won’t
survive” (Kabeer1998, 51). Though this woman also asserts that her own husband places
a higher value on her because she works now, Kabeer’s own analysis of this woman’s
testimony includes the idea that men value women because of the fear that loans will
dry up. There is evidence that has emerged since Kabeer’s study that men view women
as something like collateral since the advent of microcredit (Hoffman and Gnanou 2007,
9). In the researchers’ words, “in places where loans are perceived as being more easily
obtained by women, men use women to gain access to loans.” Fauzia Erfhan Ahmed,
who conducted a recent study of men in Grameen bank loanee households, found that
many husbands whose wives take out loans continue to view the loans as their own
property (2008a, 554).
Kabeer seems convinced that these new attributions of value to women are
steps in the right direction. Part of the reason seems to be an implicit commitment to
the substantive assumption about agency. That Kabeer thinks that increased value by
13
others is empowering, and not simply welfare‐enhancing, suggests that she believes
increasing women’s perceptions of their own value means challenging women’s
acceptance of patriarchy. But there are important reasons to doubt that this is true
about the cases at hand. Neither the case of the loan reducing scarcity nor the case of
women as collateral suggests an increase in women’s value because of any new beliefs
about what women are capable of. Assuming that gender inequality is supported largely
by views about differences in men’s and women’s capacities, there is little logical reason
the changed perceptions of women should militate against it. Indeed, conditions of
reduced scarcity may remove reasons to question women’s exclusion from formal
sector work (and I will return to this point in a moment).
There is also reason to worry that the perception of women as collateral arises
from new incentives to invest in conservative gender ideology. The idea of women as
sources of external capital is nothing new in South Asian societies with histories of
dowry. Hoffman and Nanou make this connection to dowry explicitly. “Loans may
represent a form of dowry. If their wives do not manage to obtain such a loan, this may
constitute a source of tension and violence within the household. This is equally the
case where the husband who has appropriated the loan for himself no longer has the
means to recover the capital” (200 , 9). In other words, microcredit interventions may
reward men for manipulating women and reward women for learning to negotiate
within this manipulation. Even if microcredit produces short‐term welfare gains for
women, it simultaneously gives men reasons to accept an existing sexist view—namely
of women as points of access to property. Women also have new reasons to accept this
view of themselves; the best way to keep their husbands happy is to help them secure
loans. They gain agency to access income and perhaps freedom from violence, but since
this agency comes from obsequious behavior, it is potentially welfare agency gained
through self‐subordination.
This worry that microcredit can strengthen patriarchal views of women as
property is exacerbated by certain perceptions of microcredit on the part of rural South
Asian populations. Research in Bangladesh describes some men as feeling that
microcredit is externally imposed by NGOs and the government whose interest is in
corrupting women (Ahmed 2008a, 554). One man in Ahmed’s study, which documents a
variety of different male responses to microcredit, says, “We know that the Grameen
bank is against Islam. Women go there to show their legs. But we are forced to allow
them to stay on as loanees because we are poor. As soon as we are financially stable I
will ask my wife to quit the bank” (Ahmed 2008a, 552). Such men’s goal under these
circumstances is to use the NGOs for to access income while minimizing women’s
corruption. This subsection of men experiences financial dependency on their wives as
humiliating—a point which offers further reason to worry about resurgences of gender
conservatism. Ahmed even relates the story of a woman who tearfully withdraws from
the Grameen bank after ten years because her husband has declared that they have
finally earned enough money to stop compromising her honor in this way (2008b). If
there is something new that women are capable of after microcredit, it is bringing in
money, but this capacity is seen as contingently linked to the goals of the government
and NGOs‐‐ rather than revelatory of previously ignored facts about women’s nature.
14
Of course, none of these points conclusively demonstrates that Kabeer is wrong
about microcredit moving these women toward empowerment. But it is surprising that
she sees men’s continued power as evidence of partially changed patriarchy rather than
resurgent patriarchy. Her failure to raise these questions seems symptomatic of a more
general difficulty. Kabeer, at least in her interpretations of data, struggles to account for
the possibility that interventions might increase women’s incentives to invest in
patriarchy. In theoretical discussions of empowerment, Kabeer frequently notes that
patriarchal structures create incentives for women and that we cannot determine in
advance whether agency increases will produce the desired empowerment effects
(Kabeer 1999, 442). But, when interpreting her data, Kabeer seems not to consider the
possibility that new incentives to accept patriarchy may arise. We might explain this
oversight‐‐and her certainty that the moves in question are moves toward
empowerment—with reference to something like the cumulative assumption. Increases
in women’s welfare, rather than sometimes having gender‐related opportunity costs,
always add to women’s overall agency. Kabeer’s optimism seems to stem from
inadvertent commitment to the cumulative assumption about agency—understanding
new options as agency‐enhancing, rather than potentially agency‐decreasing in some
areas, or as changing the background conditions under which welfare agency can be
exercised.
We see Kabeer’s implicit commitment to the cumulative assumption more
clearly when we consider the theoretical contortions required to make sense of another
set of cases. These are cases where women’s increased value comes from increased
ability to meet longstanding patriarchal expectations. Some of the poorest women in
Kabeer’s sample decided to abandon jobs as fieldworkers or domestic servants. These
women valued loans because they allowed them to work from their homes. To
understand why they prefer home‐based labor, it is important to remember that their
society ties women’s honor to seclusion. One woman says, “Isn’t it better to work in
your own house than to work in someone else’s to fill your stomach? You stay at home,
you raise some ducks and hens for yourself and you make some profit. Isn’t it bad when
people say ‘She goes to work in some people’s houses?” (Kabeer 1998, 66). In their
previous employment, hese women faced social penalties for violating purdah
constraints. They felt their choice was between working in occupations that would cause
them to be seen by other community members and thus losing honor and status‐‐or
preserving their honor by starving at home. There were non honor‐related reasons for
women to prefer seclusion, most notably the physical difficulty of work in the fields and
the desire not to be someone else’s servant. However/ the women themselves
consistently cite the desire to gain honor as a major motivation for their workforce
withdrawal. Women with the lowest economic status, Kabeer notes, chose home‐based
labor after microcredit largely to avoid shame.
Drawing on my earlier ideas about the subordination‐social‐recognition paradox,
we can understand microcredit as having affected the poorest women’s incentives in
two ways. First, it has increased the rewards for engaging in seclusion. Second, by
realigning the social and material rewards of complying with patriarchal norms,
microcredit has incentivized internalizing the belief that purdah is morally acceptable.
15
Before microcredit, the only way to avoid or mitigate severe material deprivation was to
violate purdah norms. This offered self‐interested reasons to question the validity of
those norms. That there is greater incentive to violate purdah through one’s actions
when one is extremely poor is borne out by research demonstrating that well‐to‐do
women tend to adhere to purdah most strictly (Holvoet 2005, 85‐86). One of Kabeer’s
informants says that, when she used to engage in agricultural labor with her husband,
“if people try to make me feel ashamed of my work, I do not feel ashamed. . . I will work
myself, I will feed myself, I will carry whatever load I have to” (Kabeer 1998,67).
Describing her life after microcredit, she states that there is no dishonor in work. But
she also justifies her exit from the fields, thus, “my value has gone up from before, I feel
ashamed, and people say, ‘she has improved so much, how can she still go do this
work’” (Kabeer 2001,70)? This particular woman’s narrative strongly suggests that it is
not only her conformity with purdah that is changing; her beliefs about its
appropriateness are as well. Kabeer seems to want to describe this fact only in terms of
a failure to alter existing gender relations. She writes of how “purdah continues to
constrain” and is “resilient” (Kabeer 2001, 69). But she seems reluctant to take seriously
the possibility that microcredit could have increased the power of purdah or women’s
acceptance of it.
Kabeer recognizes that these women who withdraw from work outside the
home pose the most serious challenge to her positive view about microceredit. Her
attempt to deal with the challenge is, I believe, unsatisfactory because of the theoretical
contortions it requires. She argues that increased purdah is a step towards women’s
empowerment because the women in question value the changes microcredit has
allowed (Kabeer 2001,70). The women viewed their previous state as humiliating; they
are now less humiliated. Without denying that these women’s lives are better without
having to experience degradation and ostracism, we can note that Kabeer’s claim that
the purdah is empowering because the women want it is question‐begging. It is
question‐begging in two ways. First, as I have argued in my work on adaptive
preferences, it is unclear why the judgments of a person who does not see oppressive
norms as harmful should be treated as definitive about how to evaluate the
retrenchment of those norms (see Khader 2011, 2012, 2013). If empowerment requires
increases in feminist agency, those who lack feminist consciousness may not be the
most reliable indicators of its presence of absence.
Second, if I am correct that feminist agency and welfare agency are separate—
and that welfare agency can come at the cost of feminist agency—all these women are
saying when they say that microcredit has improved their lives is that they have more
welfare agency. Increased welfare agency is not the same thing as increased feminist
agency, and saying otherwise denies the SSRP. Kabeer demonstrates awareness that
women have to adhere to restrictive gender norms to increase welfare. She writes that
the poorest women opt for purdah to increase their social standing (Kabeer 2001, 71).
She calls this paradoxical, but to simply call it paradoxical is to undertheorize the
implications of women’s increased participation in purdah. Rather than simply saying
that women value increased participation in female seclusion, we need to acknowledge
that microcredit gives them new welfare‐based reasons to engage in and accept it—and
16
we need to ask serious questions about what the long‐term gender effects of this will
be.
It may be argued that I am holding Kabeer to a standard of empowerment that
she herself does not hold.xiiiKabeer explicitly defines empowerment as an increase in the
conscious ability to make strategic life choices (1999; 2001,81). On Kabeer’s stated view,
the women’s choice to enter purdah is empowering because the women gain a choice
they previously lacked. Where they previously felt compelled to violate purdah because
of economic necessity, they now get to decide whether to accept it (2001,81). However,
this comment is at odds with her other repeated assertions about empowerment—
especially her repeated assumption that having real choices means learning to challenge
doxa (1990, 441). Doxa are views that reinforce social inequality by making inequality
appear to be the natural order of things. It is not clear how empowerment can
simultaneously require challenging doxa and be achieved when a woman endorses
patriarchal norms more thoroughly than she used to.xiv More importantly, however, our
question is whether microcredit is empowering—not whether it is empowering on
Kabeer’s definition. If women’s empowerment were reducible to the expansion of
welfare agency or the giving women whatever they happen to value, Kabeer’s claim that
increased purdah is empowering could be logically valid. But it would be based on a
notion of women’s empowerment that is highly counterintuitive and that does not seem
to be motivating the bulk of feminist literature on the topic. As I argued in the first
section, most writing on women’s empowerment suggests that it requires a move away
from oppressive gender relations.
4. Conclusion
We need a theoretical understanding of women’s empowerment that that
acknowledges that women’s welfare can increase without resulting in empowerment.
This is because of the conditions described in the self‐subordination social recognition
paradox. Patriarchal societies structure women’s options so that they can benefit from
complying with and internalizing patriarchal norms. One important upshot of this for
development ethics is that enhancing women’s ability to achieve welfare can strengthen
patriarchal structures. Giving women opportunities to enhance their welfare by getting
better at fulfilling and accepting subordinate roles may consolidate patriarchy and
women’s relationship to it. There are practical reasons we should think seriously about
the long‐term gender‐related opportunity costs that may ensue from just making
individual women’s lives better—as is shown by the examples of microcredit producing
the view of women as collateral and causing increased acceptance of purdah.
What does the fact that women can gain welfare agency by compromising their
feminist agency imply about evaluating development interventions? Let us begin with
what it does not imply. It certainly does not imply that inspiring feminist consciousness
in women is always more important than increasing their welfare. We should be wary of
sacrificing women’s basic welfare at the altar of equality—of saying that the lives of the
poor women who preferred purdah to social ostracism and backbreaking agricultural
labor were better before. Nor does it imply that antipoverty interventions that do not
decrease sexism are failures. Development practice involves complicated on‐the‐ground
17
judgments, and incremental changes, and there may be no imaginable intervention in a
given case that would reliably decrease incentives to support patriarchy.
Though this is not the place to offer a theory of how to measure empowerment,
my analysis here asks us to be attentive to two important possibilities. First, as a variety
of feminist empowerment theorists have argued, increases in women’s welfare, self‐
esteem, and so forth do not imply a decrease in the power of patriarchal forces. Second,
interventions that do not focus on changing gender roles may do more than simply
leave gendered power structures intact. There are opportunity costs to interventions
that may give women new reasons to accept patriarchy. Rather than assuming that
women’s empowerment always increases when they have more opportunities, we need
to see that interventions restructure opportunities and incentives. They change the
long‐term landscape within which women seek empowerment—and this means we
cannot be sanguine about which direction women’s empowerment is moving just
because women are better off. The woman who is forced by her husband to withdraw
from the Grameen Bank after ten years is arguably better off economically‐‐ but returns
to a gender landscape in which many men in her community feel they need to defend
their masculinity in the face of humiliation. The woman who enters purdah now because
she can participates in creating a gender landscape where poor women are less critical
of seclusion.
Rather than assuming women who can do more‐‐ or who have greater self‐
esteem‐‐ will change gender relations, we need to ask about gender‐related opportunity
costs and imagine strategies for mitigating them. For instance, Ahmed recommends that
the Grameen bank should enlist particularly progressive husbands to train others who
fear threats to their wives’ honor or their own power (Ahmed 2008b). Holvoet
recommends that adding groups that are long‐term and focused on consciousness‐
raising to microcredit packages. She postulates that it will increase the likelihood that
women will translate their new household bargaining power into a critique of patriarchy
(2005, 97). The SSRP suggests that antipoverty interventions focused on women,
because they enhance women’s welfare under oppressive conditions, risk consolidating
women’s relationship to patriarchy. To evaluate whether antipoverty interventions are
steps in the right direction, we need long‐term vigilance—not just about whether
women’s lives are improving, but also about how the gender landscape in which they
exert agency is changing.
i
The female genital cutting case may not, strictly speaking, involve an antipoverty
intervention failing to empower women. According to Agot, girls and families opted for
cutting because of a lack of economic opportunities. Interventions gave them education
but not employment, so marriageability became the best means to income.
ii
In her influential definition of empowerment, Kabeer (1999; 2001) distinguishes choices
from strategic life choices. I believe Kabeer sees strategic life choices as those that
would significantly enhance a person’s ability to access welfare.
iii
A prominent example is Kabeer’s (199) assertion that women’s apparent contentment
with injustice is likely caused by an inability to call patriarchal norms into question.
18
iv
In an influential study, Anju Malhotra, Sidney Shiller, and Carol Boender argue that
diverse theorists of women’s empowerment share a conception of empowerment as the
expansion of the ability to make choices important to achieving welfare (2002, 5‐6). It
may therefore seem that the operative conception of women’s empowerment focuses
on welfare agency rather than feminist agency. However, virtually all of the theorists
cited by Malhotra, Shiller, and Boender define empowerment as involving challenges to
existing power structures—and they often explicitly mention challenging gendered
ones. Perhaps Malhotra, Shiller, and Boender omit the focus on gender because they
believe choices about gender are one subset of strategic life choices. I explain why that
view is untenable in the next paragraph of the paper’s text. Further, the feminist
development theorists who are puzzled by the mixed results of antipoverty
interventions seem committed to the idea that women’ s empowerment requires the
enhancement of feminist agency. Their evidence that the results of antipoverty
interventions are problematic is usually the existence of unchanged or worsened gender
relations. They fault antipoverty interventions for failing to change women’s belief that
they deserve a lesser share of household goods, for failing to change the gender division
of labor, for increasing men’s violence against women, etc.
v
Bina Agarwal (1997) argues that women’s compliance with sexist food distribution
norms under such circumstances is self‐interested.
vi
Cain et. al (1979) describe societies as having differing levels of “patriarchal risk”
depending on the welfare and status losses women stand to incur if they are not
attached to male affines.
vii
I have made this argument more fully elsewhere (see Khader 2013), but collective
action problems make the range of cases where women can reasonably believe that
changing their behavior is not going to change sexist norms quite large.
viii
Development discourses frequently characterize the pre‐empowered person as
uncritically accepting of the power status quo. Kabeer argues that those who are not yet
empowered treat widely held beliefs as though they are beyond question (1999, 440‐
441). DFID describes the pre‐empowered as seeing themselves as passive objects of the
choices of others (Appleyard 2002, 13). Rowlands argues that women’s empowerment
involves increases in the perception of the self as “able and entitled to make decisions”
(1997, 14). Oxaal and Baaden argue that empowerment requires developing the ability
to critically assess one’s own situation in order to transform society (1997, 6).
ix
Rawls specifically discusses self‐respect rather than self‐esteem. However, those who
argue that the two concepts are distinct tend to argue that, since Rawls focuses on the
view that one’s self and one’s projects are worthy—rather than whether one has
successfully lived up to one’s principles‐‐ he means something closer to self‐esteem.
x
Boxill (1976) argues that, under oppressive conditions, it can be difficult for people to
maintain clarity about their own motives over time. Benson (1999) argues that
oppressive socialization can cause women to experience some of their desires as alien
and thus experience difficulty knowing which motives they identify with.
xi
Amartya Sen argues that learning to ignore the injustice of the world can be a way of
preserving subjective wellbeing (2002, 634).
19
xii
Studies show that the poor themselves tend to rank social ostracism as one of the
worst parts of their plight (Narayan 2000; Kabeer 2001). This fact should give us
(theorists) pause before assuming that the risks associated with social ostracism are
minor or automatically less morally urgent than losses of health, shelter, and so forth.
One reason social inclusion may be of high value is that affiliation and social recognition
ensure stable access to other goods. This view of the value of affiliation and social
recognition is consistent with the sociological theory my subordination social
recognition paradox; according to it, relations with others are the gateways to a variety
of goods constitutive of welfare.
xiii
On at least one occasion Kabeer seems to doubt whether empowerment requires
increases in feminist agency. See 1998 (12‐13).
xiv
Kabeer may be able to consistently assert that empowerment is defined as the mere
having of choices and that it requires the challenging of doxa. Doing so would require
asserting that a person who scrutinizes patriarchy and believes in patriarchy more
intensely after the scrutiny has experienced an increase in empowerment. But there are
a number of occasions where Kabeer claims that a choice is somehow not real if it
reinforces women’s subordination (see 1999, 441 for instance). Further, Kabeer argues
that choices whereby women reinforce their subordination are more likely to reveal
welfare tradeoffs restrictive societies impose on them than women’s true beliefs (1999;
1998, 28).
20
References
Agarawal, Bina. 1997. Bargaining and gender relations: within the household and
beyond.” Feminist Economics 3 (1): 1‐51
Agot, Kawango. 2007. Women, culture and HIV/AIDS in Sub‐Saharan Africa: What does
the empowerment discourse leave out? In Global empowerment of women:
Responses toglobalization and politicized religions. ed. Elliott. New York:
Routledge.
FauziaErfhan. 2008. Hidden opportunities: Islam, masculinity, and poverty alleviation.
International Journal of Feminist Politics 10(4): 542‐562
‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐.2008. Microcredit, men, and masculinity.NWSA Journal 20 (2): 122‐155.
Alkire, Sabina.2007.Concepts and measures of agency. Oxford Poverty and Human
Development Initiative Working Paper.
Aktaruzzaman,Khondker and BasudebGuha‐Khasnobis. 2012. Microcredit and domestic
violence: A regression discontinuity approach. Available at SSRN:
http:,,ssrn.com,abstract=2156086 or http:,,dx.doi.org,10.2139,ssrn.2156086.
Appleyard, Susan. 2002. A rights‐based approach to development: What the policy
documents of the UN, development cooperation agencies, and NGOs say.OHCHR
Human Rights Policy Roundtable Background Paper.
Batliwala,Srilantha and DeepaDhanraj. 2007. Gender myths that instrumentalize
women: A view from the Indian front line. InFeminisms in development:
Contradictions, contestations, and challenges. London: Zed.
Benson, Paul. 1999. Feeling crazy: Self‐worth and the social character of responsibility.
In Relational autonomy. New York: Oxford.
Boxill, Bernard. 1976. Self‐Respect and protest. Philosophy and Public Affairs 6 (1): 58‐
69.
Cheston,Susy and Lisa Kuhn. 2002. Empowering women through microfinance. UNIFEM.
Cudd Ann. 2006. Analyzing Oppression. New York: Oxford.
Cummings , Robert A and Helen Nistico. 2002. Maintaining life‐satisfaction: The role of
positive cognitive bias. Journal of Happiness Studies 3: 37‐69.
Frye , Marilyn. 1983. The Politics of Reality. Freedom CA: The Crossing Press.
Goetz, Anne‐Marie and Rina Sen Gupta. 1996. Who takes the credit? Gender, power,
and control over loan use in rural credit programs in Bangladesh. World
Development 24(1): 45‐63.
Hoffman Elisabeth and Kamala Marius‐Gnanou. 2007. Credit for women: A future for
men? ADA Dialogue37: 7‐11
Holvoet, Nathalie. 2005. The impact of microfinance on decision‐making
agency: Evidence from South India. Development and Change 36(1): 75–102
Kabeer, Naila. 2001. Conflicts over credit: re‐evaluating the empowerment potential of
loans to women in rural Bangladesh. World Development 29(1): 63‐84.
—.1998. ‘Money can’t buy me love’? Re‐evaluating gender, credit, and empowerment in
rural Bangladesh.IDS Discussion Paper 363. Sussex: Institute for Development
Studies.
21
‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐.1999. Resources, agency, achievements: Reflections on the measurement of
women’s empowerment. Development and Change 30(3): 435‐464.
Khader, Serene J 2013 “Can Women’s Compliance With Sexist Norms Be Self‐
Interested?” Unpublished Manuscript on File with Author
‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐. 2013 Identifying adaptive preferences in Practice: Lessons from Postcolonial
Feminisms. Journal of Global Ethics.
‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐. 2012. Must theorizing about adaptive preferences deny women’s agency?
Journal of Applied Philosophy 29 (4): 302‐317.
‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐. 2011. Adaptive Preferences and Women’s Empowerment. New York: Oxford.
Mahmud, Simeen. 2003. How empowering is microcredit? Development and Change
34(4): 577‐605.
Malhotra,Anju, Sidney Shuler, and Carol Boender. 2002. Measuring women’s
empowerment as a variable in development. Background Paper Prepared for the
World Bank Workshop on Poverty and Gender.
Mayoux, Linda. 2001. Tackling the downside: Social capital, women’s empowerment,
and microfinance in Cameroon. Development and Change 32: 435‐464.
Meyers , Diana. 1991.Self , society , and personal choice. New York: Columbia.
Montgomery, Richard,Debapriya Bhattacharya, and David Hulme. 1986. Credit for the
poor in Bangladesh: the BRAC Rural Development Programme and the
Government Thana Resource Development and Employment Programme. In
Finance Against Poverty, ed. Hulme and Mosley.London: Routeledge.
Narayan, Deepa. 2000. Voices of the poor volume 1: Can anybody hear us? New York:
Oxford.
Narayan Uma. 2005. Informal sector work, microcredit, and women’s
empowerment: A critical overview. Unpublished manuscript on file with author.
‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐. 2002. Minds of their own: Choices, autonomy, cultural practices, and other
women. A mind of one’s own: Feminist essays on reason and objectivity, ed.
Louise M. Antony and Charlotte E. Witt. Boulder, Colorado: Westview.
Osmani,Lutfun. 1998. The impact of microcredit on the relative well‐being of women.
IDS Bulletin29 (4): 31‐38.
Oxaal, Zoe and Sally Baden. 1997. Gender and empowerment: Definitions, approaches,
and implications for policy. Swedish International Development Agency.
Rawls , John. 1978. A theory of justice.Cambridge: Harvard.
SenAmartya. 1990. Gender and cooperative conflicts. In Persistent inequalities: Women
and world development, ed.Irene Tinker. Oxford: Oxford.
‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐.2002.Rationality and Freedom. Cambridge: Belknap.
Shuler,Sidney Ruth, Syed A. Hashemi, and Shamsul Huda Badal. 1998. Men’s violence
against women in rural Bangladesh: Undermined or exacerbated by microcredit
programs? Development in Practice 8(2): 148‐57.
Swain, Ranjula.2007. Can microfinance empower women? ADA Dialogue 37:61‐82.
United Nations.2013. Goal 3: Promote Gender Equality and Empower Women.
http:,,www.un.org,millenniumgoals,gender.shtml (accessed February 3, 2013).
22