LOGICAL CRITICISM OF BUDDHIST DOCTRINES
1
LOGICAL CRITICISM OF BUDDHIST DOCTRINES
A Thematic Compilation
By Avi Sion PH.D.
© Copyright Avi Sion, 2017. All rights reserved.
Protected by international copyright conventions. No part of this book may be reproduced in any manner whatsoever,
or stored in a retrieval system or transmitted, without express permission of the Author-publisher, except in case of
brief quotations with due acknowledgement.
Self-published through Lulu; CreateSpace & Kindle.
Website: www.TheLogician.net. E-mail:
[email protected].
Logical Criticism of Buddhist Doctrines can be freely read online at avisionbuddhism and in
various other locations.
It can be purchased, in print and e-book editions, in Amazon.com, Lulu.com and many other
online booksellers.
The present document contains excerpts from this book, namely: The Abstract; the Contents;
and Sample text (Chapters 6 and 9:1-2).
Avi Sion (Ph.D. Philosophy) is a researcher and writer in logic, philosophy, and spirituality. He
has, since 1990, published original writings on the theory and practice of inductive and deductive
logic, phenomenology, epistemology, aetiology, psychology, meditation, ethics, and much more.
Over a period of some 28 years, he has published 27 books. He resides in Geneva, Switzerland.
It is very difficult to briefly summarize Avi Sion’s philosophy, because it is so wide-ranging. He
has labeled it ‘Logical Philosophy’, because it is firmly grounded in formal logic, inductive as
well as deductive. This original philosophy is dedicated to demonstrating the efficacy of human
reason by detailing its actual means; and to show that the epistemological and ethical skepticism
which has been increasingly fashionable and destructive since the Enlightenment was (contrary to
appearances) quite illogical – the product of ignorant, incompetent and dishonest thinking.
2
AVI SION
Abstract
Logical Criticism of Buddhist Doctrines is a ‘thematic compilation’ by Avi Sion. It collects in
one volume the essays that he has written on this subject over a period of some 15 years after the
publication of his first book on Buddhism, Buddhist Illogic. It comprises expositions and
empirical and logical critiques of many (though not all) Buddhist doctrines, such as
impermanence, interdependence, emptiness, the denial of self or soul. It includes his most recent
essay, regarding the five skandhas doctrine.
LOGICAL CRITICISM OF BUDDHIST DOCTRINES
3
4
AVI SION
LOGICAL CRITICISM OF BUDDHIST DOCTRINES
5
6
AVI SION
Sample text (chapters 6 and 9:1-2)
6 “Everything causes everything”
One doctrine fundamental to Buddhism is the idea that ‘everything causes everything’, or
‘everything is caused by everything’. This is the idea of universal codependence (or
interdependence); it is the idea that nothing exists independently of anything else, that all things
depend for their existence on all other things. This is, note well, a more radical thesis than the
claim, commonly found in most Western philosophies, that ‘everything has a cause (or a set of
causes)’.
On the surface, the Buddhist notion of universal causation seems conceivable, if not profound.
However, upon reflection it is found to be logically impossible – i.e. utter nonsense. This is made
evident in the following excerpts from past books.
1. The idea of co-dependence
The Buddhist idea of ‘co-dependence’ might be stated broadly as each thing exists only in
relation to others; and furthermore, since each other thing in turn exists only in relation to yet
others, each thing exists in relation to all the others. The relation primarily intended here is
causality, note. We tend to regard each thing as capable of solitary existence in the universe, and
ignore or forget the variegated threads relating it to other things. We ‘do not see the forest for the
trees’, and habitually focus on individual events to the detriment of overview or long view.
For example, consider a plant. Without the sunlight, soil and water it depends on, and without
previous generations of the same plant and the events that made reproduction possible and the
trajectories of each atom constituting and feeding the plant, and without the cosmic upheavals
that resulted in the existence of our planet and its soil and water and of the sun and of living
matter, and so forth ad infinitum, there would be no plant. It has no independent existence, but
stands before us only by virtue of a mass of causes and conditions. And so with these causes and
conditions, they in turn are mere details in a universal fabric of being.
The concept of co-dependence is apparently regarded by Buddhists as an inevitable outcome of
the concept of causality. But reflection shows, again, that this doctrine is only a particular thesis
within the thesis of causality. That is, though co-dependence implies causality, causality does not
imply co-dependence. Moreover, it is a vague thesis, which involves some doubtful
generalizations. The above-cited typical example of co-dependence suggests three propositions:
• everything has a cause (or is an effect),
• everything has an effect (or is a cause);
and perhaps the more radical,
• everything causes and is caused by everything.
The first two propositions are together what we call ‘the law of causality’. It has to be seen that
these propositions do not inevitably follow from the concept of causality. The latter only requires
LOGICAL CRITICISM OF BUDDHIST DOCTRINES
7
for its formation that some regularity of co-existence between events be found in experience, but
does not in itself necessitate that every event in experience be found to have regular co-existence
with some other event(s). The concept of causality is valid if it but has particular applications; the
law of causality does not automatically follow – it is merely a generalization from some
experiences with this property to all existents. There may well be things not found to have regular
co-existents, and thence by generalization assumed to have no cause and/or no effect. A universe
in which both causality and non-causality occur is quite conceivable. Furthermore, the first
proposition does not logically imply the second or vice versa – i.e. we may imagine things with
causes but no further effect, and things with effects but no preceding causes.
“Early Buddhists”, Cheng tells us, “believed in the principle of causality to be objectively,
necessarily, eternally and universally valid.” Many Western philosophers have concurred, though
not all. Today, most physicists believe that, on a quantum level at least, and perhaps at the Big
Bang, there are events without apparent cause. I do not know if events without effect are
postulated by anyone. In any case, we see that even on the physical level “chance” is admitted as
a possibility, if not a certainty. The law of causality can continue to serve us as a working
principle, pressing us to seek diligently for causes and effects, but cannot in any case be regarded
as an a priori universal truth. Causal logic has to remain open-minded, since in any case these
“laws” are mere generalizations – inductive, not deductive, truths.
Furthermore, the law of causality just mentioned is only at best a law of causation. Philosophers
who admit of volition1 cannot consistently uphold such a law as universal to all existents, but only
in the ‘mechanistic’ domains of physical and psychological events. With regard to events
involving the will, if we admit that a human being (or equivalent spiritual entity, a higher animal
or God) can ‘will’ (somehow freely produce) a physiological event (i.e. a physical movement in
his body) or a psychological event (i.e. an imagination, a mental projection), or even another soul
(at least in the sense of choosing to reproduce), we have to consider this as an exception to such
universal law of causation.
Also, if we consider that the Agent of will is always under the influence of some experience or
reason, we might formulate an analogical law of causality with reference to this. But influence is
not to be confused with causation; it does not determine the will, which remains free, but only
strengthens or weakens it, facilitating or easing its operation in a certain direction. Moreover, it is
not obvious that will cannot occur ‘nihilistically’, without any influence; it may well be free, not
only to resist influences but also to operate in the absence of any motive whatsoever. In the latter
case, the law of causality would again be at best a working principle, not a universal fact that
volition requires a motive.
Let us now consider the more extreme statement that ‘everything causes and is caused by
everything’, which could be construed (incorrectly) as implied by co-dependence. To say this is
effectively to say paradoxically (as Nagarjuna would no doubt have enjoyed doing!) that nothing
causes or is caused by anything – for causality is a relation found by noticing regularities in
contrast to irregularities. If everything were regularly co-existent with everything, we would be
unable to distinguish causality in the first place. It follows that such an extreme version of the law
And at least some Buddhists seem to. For instance, the statement in the Dhammapada (v.165) that “by
oneself the evil is done, and it is oneself who suffers: by oneself evil is not done, and by one’s Self one becomes
pure. The pure and the impure come from oneself: no man can purify another” – this statement seems to imply
existence of a self with responsibility for its actions.
1
8
AVI SION
of causality is logically untenable. Causality cannot imply that ‘everything causes everything’ or
‘everything is caused by everything’ – and to deny the latter statements does not deny the
concept, note well. The concept is not derived from such a law, but independently from
observation of regularities in experience; our ability to discern such regularities from the mass of
experience implies that there are irregularities too; whence, such an extreme statement cannot be
consistently upheld. We must thus admit that things do not have unlimited numbers of causes or
effects.
Although ‘everything causes everything’ implies ‘co-dependence’, the latter does not imply the
former; so our refutation of the wider statement does not disprove co-dependence, only one
possible (extreme) view of it. My criticism of co-dependence would be the following. For a start,
the doctrine presented, and the illustrations given in support of it, do not use the term causality
with any precision. First, as we have suggested above, causality, is a broad term, covering a
variety of very distinct relations:
• causation or ‘mechanistic’ causality within the material and mental domains, and
causation itself has many subspecies;
• volition, or action by souls on the material or mental or spiritual domains, and will has
many degrees of freedom; and
• influence, which refers to limitations on volition set by material or mental or spiritual
entities.
The doctrine of co-dependence glosses over the profound differences between these different
senses of the terms ‘cause’ and ‘effect’, using them as if they were uniform in all their
applications.
Also to be included as ‘causal relations’ in a broader sense are the negations of these relations.
Even if some philosopher doubts one, two or all three of these (positive) relations, he would have
to consider them. Concepts of ‘chance’ or ‘spontaneity’ are not simple, and can only be defined
by negating those of causality; likewise, the concept of ‘determinism’ requires one of ‘free will’.
It is only in contrast to causality concepts, that non-causality can be clearly conceived.
Furthermore, co-dependence ignores that some things are not (positively) causally related to each
other, even if they may have (positive) causal relations to other things. That something must have
some cause or effect, does not imply that it has this or that specific thing as its cause or effect;
there are still things to which it is not causally related. If everything had the same positive causal
relation to everything, and no negative causal relation, there would be no such thing as causality,
nothing standing out to be conceived.
Secondly, if we consider chains (or, in discourse, syllogisms) of causal relations, we find that the
cause of a cause is not necessarily itself a cause, or at least not in the same sense or to the same
degree. For instance, with reference to causation, we can formally prove that if A is a complete
cause of B and B is a complete cause of C, then A is a complete cause of C. But if A is a
complete cause of B and B is a partial cause of C, it does not follow that A is at all a cause of C.
Similarly, when we mix the types of causality (e.g. causation and volition in series), we find that
causality is not readily transmitted, in the same way or at all. It is therefore logically incorrect to
infer transmission of causality from the mere fact of succession of causal relations as the theory
of co-dependence does.
Thirdly, those who uphold co-dependence tend to treat both directions of causal relation as
equivalent. Thus, when they say ‘everything is causally related to everything’, they seem to
suggest that being a cause and being an effect is more or less the same. But something can only
LOGICAL CRITICISM OF BUDDHIST DOCTRINES
9
be regarded as a cause of things occurring after it in time or below it in conceptual hierarchy, and
as an effect of things occurring before it or above it. Upstream and downstream are not
equivalent. Thus, ‘interdependence’ cannot be taken too literally, using ‘causal relation’ in a too
vague sense, without attention to the distinction between causal and effectual relationship.
Fourthly, the doctrine of co-dependence suggests or calls for some sort of law(s) of causality, and
as already discussed higher up, no universal or restricted law of causality is logically necessitated
by the concept of causality, although such a law may be considered a hypothetical principle to be
validated inductively. The concept of causality only requires that some causality occur, without
prejudicing how much. So, though co-dependence implies causality, causality does not imply codependence.
Fifthly, the concept of ‘co-dependence’ is upheld in contrast and opposition to a concept of ‘selfsubsistence’. Something self-subsistent would exist ‘by itself’, without need of origination or
support or destructibility, without ‘causal conditions’. Buddhism stresses that (apart perhaps from
ultimate reality) nothing in the manifold has this property, which Buddhism claims ordinary
consciousness upholds. In truth, the accusation that people commonly believe in the selfsubsistence of entities is false – this is rather a construct of earlier Indian philosophy.
People generally believe that most things have origins (which bring them into existence), and that
all things once generated have static relations to other existents (an infinity of relations, to all
other things, if we count both positive and negative relations as ‘relations’), and that things
usually depend for their continued existence on the presence or absence of other things (i.e. if
some of the latter come or go, the former may go too). What is doubtful however, in my view, is
the vague, implicit suggestion of the co-dependence doctrine, that while a thing is present, i.e.
during the time of its actual existence, it has a somehow only relative existence, i.e. were it not
for the other things present in that same moment, it could not stand.
This is not essentially a doctrine of relativity to consciousness or Subject (though Yogachara
Buddhism might say so), note well, but an existential incapacity to stand alone. This is the aspect
of co-dependence that the Western mind, or ordinary consciousness, would reject. In our world2,
once a thing is, and so long as it is, irrespective of the causes of its coming to be or the eventual
causes of its ceasing to be, or of other things co-existing with it in time and its relationships to
those things, or of its being an object of consciousness, it simply exists. It is a done thing,
unchangeable historical fact, which nothing later in time can affect. It cannot be said to ‘depend’
on anything in the sense implied by Buddhists, because nothing could possibly be perceived or
conceived as reversing or annulling this fact.
What Buddhism seems to be denying here is that ‘facts are facts’, whatever their surrounding
circumstances, and whether or not they are cognized, however correctly or imperfectly. It is a
denial that appearances, whatever their content and whether they be real or illusory, have
occurred. We cannot accept such deviation from the Law of Identity.
Such considerations lead me to the conclusion that ‘co-dependence’ is not easy to formulate and
establish, if at all. Nevertheless, I regard it as a useful ‘way of looking at things’, a valuable rough
and ready heuristic principle. Also, to be fair, I remain open to the possibility that, at some deep
level of meditative insight I have not reached, it acquires more meaning and validity.
2
We can, incidentally, imagine a world where only one thing exists, without anything before it, simultaneous
to it or after it.
10
AVI SION
2. Conclusions of first phase of studies
It must be understood that this research has not been idle reshuffling of information and symbols.
It had both practical and theoretical purposes in mind.
The practical questions relate to everyday reasoning about causes and effects. One of the
principal questions we posed, you will recall, was whether the cause of the cause of something is
itself a cause of that thing or not, and if it is, to whether it is so to the same degree or a lesser
degree. This issue of causal (or effectual) chains is what the investigation of causal syllogism is
all about. What our dispassionate research has shown is that it is absurd to expect ordinary
reasoning, unaided by such patient formal reflections, to arrive at accurate results. The answer to
the question about chains is resounding and crucial: the cause of a cause is not necessarily itself
a cause, and if it is a cause it need not be one to the same degree. Once the scientific impact of
this is understood, the importance of such research becomes evident.
But this syllogistic issue has not been the only one dealt with. We have in the process engaged in
many other investigations of practical value. The definitions of the determinations causation by
means of matrixes can help both laypeople and scientists to classify particular causative
relations, simply by observing conjunctions of presences and absences of various items.
Generalizations may occur thereafter, but they should always be checked by further empirical
observation (at least, a readiness to notice; eventually, active experiment) and adjusted as new
data appears (or is uncovered).
Another interesting finding has been the clarification of the relationships between positive and
negative, absolute and relative causative propositions: for instance, that we may affirm partial
or contingent causation, while denying it of a particular complement. One very important
principle – that we have assumed in this volume, but not proved, because the proof is only
possible in the later phase of research – is that (absolute) “lone determinations” are logically
impossible. This means that we may in practice consider that if there is causation at all, it must
be in one or the other of the four “joint” determinations.
Another finding worth highlighting is that non-causation is denial of the four genera (or four
species) of causation, and before these can be definitely denied we have to go through a long
process of empirical verification, observing presences and absences of items or their negations in
all logically possible conjunctions. It is thus in practice as difficult to prove non-causation as to
prove causation! Indeed, to be concluded the former requires a lot more careful analysis of data
than the latter. Of course, in practice (as with all induction) we assume causation absent, except
where it is proved present. But if we want to check the matter out closely, a more sustained effort
is required.
With regard to the theoretical significance of our findings, now. By theoretical, here, I mean:
relevant to philosophical discussions and debates about causality. Obviously, so far we have only
treated causation, and said nothing about volition and allied cause-effect relations, so we cannot
talk about causality in its broadest sense.
What our perspective makes clear is that the existence of “causation” is indubitable, once we
apprehend it as a set of experiential yes or no answers to simple questions, leaving aside
references to some underlying “force” or “connection” (which might be discussed as a later
explanatory hypothesis). If we look upon causation in a positivistic manner, and avoid
metaphysical discussions that tend to mystify, it is a simple matter. Causation is an abstraction,
in response to phenomenologically evident data. It is a summary of data.
LOGICAL CRITICISM OF BUDDHIST DOCTRINES
11
It is not purely empirical, in the sense of a concept only summarizing presences of phenomena. It
involves a rational element, in that it also summarizes absences of phenomena. Affirmation may
only be acknowledgment of the empirically apparent. But negation, as I have stressed in my work
Phenomenology3, is a partly rational act (a question is asked: is the thing I remember or imagine
now present to my senses?), as well as a partly empirical act (the answer is no: I see or hear or
otherwise sense nothing equivalent to that image!). Absence does not exist independently like
presence, but signifies an empirically disappointed mental expectation.
Reading debates between philosophers (for example, David Hume’s discussions), one might get
the impression that non-causation is an obvious concept, while causation needs to be defined and
justified. But, as we have seen here, non-causation can only be understood and proven with
reference to causation. Before we can project a world without causation, we have to first
understand what we mean by causation, its different determinations, their interactions, and so
forth. But the moment we do that, the existence of causation is already obvious. However, this
does not mean that non-causation does not exist. Quite the contrary. Since, as we have seen, some
formal processes like syllogism with premises of causation are inconclusive, we may say that the
existence of causation implies that of non-causation! This finding has two aspects:
(a) The more immediate aspect is inferred from the fact that the cause of a cause of something is
not necessarily itself a cause of it: taking any two things at random, they may or not be
causatively related. This implication is valuable to contradict the Buddhist notion that
“everything is caused by everything”. But the possibility of independence from some things
does not exclude dependence on other things. Each of the two things taken at random may
well have other causes and effects than each other.
(b) A more radical aspect is the issue of spontaneity, or no causation by anything at all. We can
only touch upon this issue here, since we have only dealt with causation so far. But what our
formal study of causation has made clear is that we cannot say offhand whether or not
spontaneity in this sense is possible. There is no “law of causation” that spontaneity is
impossible, i.e. that “everything has a cause”, as far as I can see. Nothing we have come
across so far implies such a universal law; it can only be affirmed by generalization.
Spontaneity (chance, the haphazard) remains conceivable.
I think the point is made: that formal research such as the present one has both practical and
theoretical value. Let us now explain why the research undertaken so far is insufficient.
3. Conclusions of second phase of studies
The universal causation doctrine predicts that every existent has at least some causative
relation(s) to some other existents. This is usually understood in a moderate sense as only some
other things cause each thing, but Buddhism understands it more extremely as all other things
cause each thing. This ‘universal universal causation’ is referred to as the interdependence (or
codependence) of all things.
We normally suppose that only the past and present can cause the present or future; and indeed,
this principle should primarily be read that way. But some might go further and claim that time is
transcended by causation, and that literally everything causes everything; I am not sure Buddhism
3
This final chapter of Phase One was written in 2003, after publication of Phenomenology.
12
AVI SION
goes to that extreme. Note also that, in truth, Buddhism intends its interdependence principle
restrictively, as applicable only to dharmas, i.e. the transient phenomena constituting the world of
appearances; in the higher or deeper realm of the quiescent and undifferentiated “original ground”
there is no causation.
Be it said in passing, this version of “karmic law” must be distinguished from the narrower
statement, which most of us agree with, that actions have consequences. The latter does not imply
the former! More deeply, I think what the Buddhists really meant by their law of karma was that
each human (or other living) being is somewhat locked within recurring behavior patterns, very
difficult (or impossible) to get out of. This is another issue, concerning not causation but volition.
That is the sense of “the wheel”: our cultural and personal habits as well as our physical
limitations, keep influencing our behavior and are reinforced by repetition. Much meditation and
long-term corrective action are required to change them; they cannot be overcome by immediate
measures, by a sheer act of will. We are thus burdened by a “baggage” of karma, which we carry
out through our lives with usually little change; it may be lightened with sustained effort, but is
more likely to be made heavier as time passes.
If we logically examine the claim that “everything causes everything”, we see that if everything is
causatively connected to everything else, then nothing is without such connection to any other
thing, let alone without causative connection to anything whatsoever. That is, this doctrine is
effectively a denial that relative as well as absolute non-causation ever occurs, which no one in
Western culture would admit. To evaluate it objectively, let us look back on the findings in the
present volume.
First, in defense of the idea of interdependence, it should be recalled that when we discussed the
significance of the “last modus” in any grand matrix (modus #16 for two items, or #256 for three,
etc.), which declares any combination of the items concerned or their negations as possible (code
1 in every cell of the modus), we saw that there was an uncertainty as to whether this indicated
causation (or more broadly, connection) or its absence. If the last modus could be shown on
formal grounds to indicate causation in all cases, then all contingents in the universe would have
to be considered as causatively related to all others (i.e. any two contingents taken at random
could be affirmed as causatively related, specifically in the way of the partial contingent
determination, pq).
However, since such formal demonstration is lacking, and the idea is anyway disagreeable to
common sense (at least that of non-Buddhists), we estimated that the science of Logic had to keep
an open mind and grant the possibility of the alternative interpretation, namely that two items
may or may not be causatively related to each other (i.e. relative non-causation is possible), and
moreover that spontaneity (i.e. absolute non-causation) is at least conceivable in some cases.
However, in this context, the Buddhist thesis of interdependence, remains a legitimate formal
postulate. But note well, only a possible alternative hypothesis; and not a very probable one for
most observers (those of us who believe in freewill, for example; as well as physicists who reify
the Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle).
An important formal criticism we can level against the notion of interdependence is to ask what
manner or degree of causation is meant by it. The term ‘causes’ in ‘everything causes everything’
is used very vaguely. Is only causation intended, to the exclusion of volition? And if causation is
intended, surely this is meant broadly to include prevention? And are the different determinations
of causation admitted, i.e. strong (complete and/or necessary) as well as weak (partial and/or
contingent)? The definition of causation traditionally attributed to the Buddha is:
LOGICAL CRITICISM OF BUDDHIST DOCTRINES
13
“When this is, that is; this arising, that arises. When this is not, that is not; this ceasing,
that ceases.”
This definition would suggest that only complete necessary causation is intended. But other
discussions within Buddhism suggest that this definition is only intended as a paradigm, as the
most obvious case, and partial and contingent causation is also in practice admitted, as use of the
plural in the expression “causes and conditions” testifies. We may regard prevention as formally
subsumed by all these concepts, by negation of an item. Some discourses also seem to accept
volition, but this need not concern us here. Focusing, then, on causation in a broad sense, we may
make the following criticism.
If everything is causatively related to everything else, then the only conceivable kind of causation
would be weak (both partial and contingent). For strong causation (complete and/or necessary)
surely implies a certain exclusiveness of relationship between the items. If all items are involved
to some degree in the existence of a given item, then none of those causes can be claimed to
predominate. So finally, it seems to me, this Buddhist doctrine of multilateral causation requires
all bilateral causative relations to be weak, and ultimately abandons strong determinations
(including mixtures), and all the more so the strongest determination (which it originally rightly
claimed as the definition of causation).
One way to show that the interdependence theory implies specifically a ‘universal weak link’ is
as follows. If we claim interdependence to apply indiscriminately to all ‘things’, i.e. not only to
experiential things (dharmas), but also to abstract things, we fall into formal difficulties as soon
as we suppose some causative relations to be strong. For then such abstract relations (i.e.
causations) also count as ‘things’, and are therefore subject to interdependence. We might thus
ask how a cause can be complete or necessary when that relationship is itself dependent on some
yet other cause: we are forced to contradict our premise and conclude that the cause is not as
complete or necessary as it seemed.
I suppose the proposed state of affairs (universal interdependence) is formally conceivable,
although I do not see on what grounds we could possibly allow such rejection in one fell swoop
of a large number of moduses (i.e. all alternative moduses concerning the strong determinations).
Unless a reasonable formal or empirical ground is provided, there is no justification in such a
radical measure: it would constitute prejudice. The Buddhist claim is of course based on a
meditative experience; but since this is esoteric, not readily available to all observers at will, we
must remain critical and view it as speculative. We cannot categorically eliminate it on firm
rational grounds, but we cannot just take it on faith.
It should be realized that causation is a conceptual object, not a percept. Before we can discern a
causative relation between two or more percepts (and all the more so between concepts) we have
to distinguish the percepts from each other (and conceptualize them by comparison and contrast
of many percepts, in the case of concepts). Also, causation refers to negation, which is a product
of rational as well as empirical factors. Thus, if we approach the issue of causation with respect to
the phenomenological order of things, we must recognize that it is a rather high-level abstract,
although of basic importance in the organization of knowledge. It is not something we just
directly see or otherwise sense. For this reason, we may remain skeptical that there is some flash
of insight that would instantly reveal the causal relations of all things in the universe.
14
AVI SION
Thus, while the interdependence doctrine apparently does not give rise to formal inconsistency,
we have good reason to doubt it with reference to normal human knowledge development.
Causation is ordinarily known only gradually, through painstaking observation and analysis of
particular data, always subject to review and revision as new data makes its appearance and
possible contradictions are encountered. Our minds are not omniscient or rigidly deductive, but
cumulative and flexibly inductive: we proceed by trial and error, constantly adjusting our
positions to match up with new input and logical insight. Therefore, we cannot rely on sweeping
statements, like that about interdependence, without being very careful.
Of course, some philosophers would argue back that causation as such is a man-made illusion,
since pure experience only reveals undifferentiated presence. Differentiation into ‘distinct’
percepts, and finding that some sought things are ‘absent’, and conceptualization on the basis of
‘similarities and differences’, are all acts of reason. Indeed, if all perceived appearances are
regarded as mere wave motions in a single, otherwise uniform substrate of existence (the ‘original
ground’ of Buddhists or the Unified Field of physicists), then the boundaries we think we
perceive or conceive for individuated things are in fact mere fictions, and all things (including
even our fantasies about causation) are ultimately One in a very real sense.
So let us keep an open mind either way, and cheerfully move on. I just want to add one more
small set of reflections, which the Buddhist idea of interdependence generated in me. This idea is
often justified with reference to causal chains4. I tried therefore to imagine the world as a large
body of water, like Lake Geneva say. According to this theory, supposedly, a disturbance
anywhere in the lake eventually ripples through the whole lake, to an ever-diminishing degree but
never dampening to zero. I then translated this image into the language of causal chains, for
purposes of formal evaluation.
Looking at the results of macroanalysis, one would immediately answer that the Buddhist
expectation is wrong. As we have seen, a cause of a cause of something is not necessarily itself a
cause of that thing; and even if it is a cause, it may be so to a lesser degree. Many first figure
syllogisms yield no causative conclusion, although their premises are compatible. Some do yield
a conclusion, but that conclusion is often weaker in determination than the premises. Thus, we
have formal reasons to doubt the idea of interdependence, if it is taken to imply that ‘a cause of
cause of something is itself in turn a cause of that thing’.
All the same, I thought, thinking of the movement of disturbances in the lake, there is some truth
in the contention. I then thought that maybe we should conceive of ‘orders of causation’ – and
postulate that even “if A causes B and B causes C, but nevertheless A does not syllogistically
cause C” is true in a given case in terms of first-order causation, it can still be said that A causes
C in second-order causation. And we could perhaps continue, and declare that if the latter
(meaning, causes a cause of) is not applicable in a given case, we could appeal to a third order of
causation, etc. We might thus, in an attempt to give credence to all theories, explain the Buddhist
notion as involving a diluted sense of ‘causation’.
This idea seemed plausible for a while, until I got into microanalysis. In the latter approach,
conclusions are given in terms of alternative moduses. There is no room for a fanciful, more
abstract, additional order of causation: the result would be identical, still the same number (one or
more) of legitimate alternative moduses. No useful purpose would be served in inventing new
4
See for instance Thich Naht Hanh, The Heart of Understanding.
LOGICAL CRITICISM OF BUDDHIST DOCTRINES
15
(narrower or broader) sets of alternative moduses, and giving such groups new names. We could
only at best regard all moduses in a grand matrix (other than the first, composed of all zeros) as
indicative of some ‘causation’ (in a maximal sense), and so say that any alternative modus found
at the conclusion of a syllogistic intersection is ‘residual causation’.
But having reached this bottom line, we see how trite the suggestion is.
4. Conclusions of third phase of studies
We should also here mention the cognitive role of alleged laws of causation. We have already
briefly discussed laws relating to space and time.
In times past, it seems that some degree of sameness between cause and effect was regarded as an
important law of causation. Upon reflection, the proponents of this criterion for causation
probably had in mind that offspring have common features with their parents. But apparently,
some people took this idea further and supposed that the substance (and eventually some other
characteristics) of cause and effect must be the same. But though this criterion may be applicable
to biology or other specific domains (e.g. the law of conservation of matter and energy in physics
could be so construed), it is not generally regarded as universal. Formally, I see no basis for it.5
The law of causation most often appealed to (at least in Western thought) is that ‘everything has a
cause’. But though it is evidently true of most things that they have causes, and the belief in this
law often motivates us to look for or postulate causes (i.e. even if none is apparent, we may
assume one to exist), we have not in our study found any formal grounds to affirm such a law as
universal. Admitting the fact of causation does not logically force us to admit its universality.
This does not prove that it is not empirically universal; and it does not prevent us from
formulating such universality as an adductive hypothesis. In any case, today, as evidenced by
quantum physics and big-bang cosmogony, it seems generally assumed by scientists that this law
is indeed not universal (which does not mean it is not very widely applicable).
I wonder anyway if it was ever really regarded as universal. I would say that in the 19 th Century,
this law was assumed universal for physical phenomena – but not necessarily for mental
phenomena; human volition was generally taken to be an exception to the rule, i.e. freedom of the
will was acknowledged by most people. Paradoxically, in the iconoclastic 20 th Century, while the
said law of causation was denied universality for material things, every effort was made to affirm
it as regards human beings and thus forcefully deny freedom of the will 6. Intellectual fashions
If we want to go more deeply in the history of ‘laws of causation’, we would have to mention, among
others, the Hindu/Buddhist law of karma, according to which one’s good and bad deeds sooner or later have desirable
or undesirable consequences, respectively, on oneself. It is the popular idea that ‘what goes around must come
around’. Though I would agree this is sometimes, frequently or even usually empirically true, we must admit that it
does not always seem confirmed by observation – so it is at best a hopeful generalization (to a life after this one)
intended to have positive moral influence. In any case, I see no formal basis for it. The same can be said concerning
reward or punishment by God – though it might well be true, it is not something that can readily be proved by
observation or by formal means; an act of faith is required to believe in it (I do, on that basis). In any case, the latter
can hardly be called a ‘law of causation’, since the free will of God is thought to be involved in bringing about the
effect.
6
Actually, both these changes were (I suggest) consciously or subconsciously motivated by the same evil
desire to incapacitate mankind. Their proponents effectively told people: “you cannot control matter (since it is
ultimately not subject to law) and you cannot control yourself (since you have no freewill) – so give up trying”.
5
16
AVI SION
change, evidently. But as far as I am concerned, while I admit the possibility that this law may
not-be universally true of matter, I have no doubt that it is inapplicable to the human will7.
Another alleged law of causation that should be mentioned here (because of the current interest in
it, in some circles) is the Buddhist notion that ‘every thing is caused by everything’. As I have
shown in the present volume, this idea of universal ‘interdependence’ is logically untenable. It is
formally nonsensical. Indeed, if you just think for a moment, you will realize (without need for
complex formal analysis) that to affirm interdependence is to deny causation, or at least its
knowability. Every concept relies on our ability to distinguish the presence and absence of the
thing conceived; if it is everywhere the same, it cannot be discerned. I think the Buddhist
philosopher Nagarjuna can be said to have realized that; and this would explain why he ultimately
opted for a no-causation thesis. However, that does not mean that causation can logically be
denied: as already explained earlier, it cannot.
Well, then. Are there any ‘laws of causation’? Of course there are, a great many! Every finding
concerning the formal logic of causation in this volume is a law of causation, a proven law. For
instance, the fact that not all positive causative syllogisms yield a positive conclusion of some
sort is an important law of causation, teaching us that a cause of a cause of something is not
necessarily itself a cause of that thing.
9. Impermanence
1. Impermanence: concept and principle
Buddhist meditators attach great importance to the principle of impermanence. They consider that
if one but realizes that “everything is impermanent”, one is well on the way to or has already
reached Realization.
However, the principle proposed by Buddhism should (in my view) be approached more critically
than its proponents have hitherto done. They have taken for granted that such a principle is
immediately knowable, in the way of a direct experience, and have not given enough attention to
the epistemological issues this notion raises.
To be sure, we can and do commonly have direct experience of some impermanence: that of
present changes. Whereas we might rationally analyze change in general (when it occurs) as an
instant replacement of one thing by its negation, many phenomena of change evidently occur in a
present moment (an extended amount of time). If, for example, you watch a dog running, you are
People who believed this nonsense (including its advocates) were influenced by it to become weaker human beings.
Virtue was derided and vice was promoted. We see the shameful results of this policy all around us today.
7
I argue this issue elsewhere, in my Volition and Allied Causal Concepts. It should be mentioned that an
analogue to the law of causation is often postulated, consciously or not, for the mind. We tend to think that every act
of volition has a cause, in the sense of being influenced or motivated, by something or other. Though largely true,
this assumption taken literally would exclude purely whimsical volitions; thus, I tend to doubt it, for reasons
explained in my said book. In any case, do not confuse this ‘law of influence’ with the ‘law of causation’ here
discussed. These are very distinct forms of causality, which cannot be lumped together.
LOGICAL CRITICISM OF BUDDHIST DOCTRINES
17
not personally experiencing this sight as a series of successive stills of the dog in different
positions, but as one continuous series of moves.
A good meditation on such evident impermanence is meditation on water8. One sits or stands
calmly in front of a body of water (the sea, a river, a lake, a puddle), watching the movements on
its surface – reflections on it, waves or wavelets, currents, droplets of rain, listening to the sounds.
I find this practice both soothing and a great source of understanding about life.
But we must keep in mind that the concept of impermanence covers a wider range of experiences
than that: it includes changes not sensible in a present moment, but only inferred over time by
comparing situations experienced in distinct moments, whether contiguous or non-contiguous.
Such inferences imply a reliance on memory, or an interpretation of other present traces of past
events. Still other changes are known even more indirectly, through predominantly conceptual
means.
Generally speaking (i.e. including all sorts of experience under one heading): we first experience
undifferentiated totality, and then (pretty much automatically) subdivide it by means of mental
projections and then conceptually regroup these subdivisions by comparing and contrasting them
together. Buddhist philosophy admits and advocates this analysis: the subdivision and
conceptualization of the phenomenological given is, we all agree, ratiocination (i.e. rational
activity); it is reason (i.e. the rational faculty) that mentally “makes” many out of the One.
It follows from this insight (we may now argue) that impermanence cannot be considered as a
primary given, but must be viewed as derived from the imagined subdivision and conceptual
regrouping of the initially experienced whole. Even to mentally isolate and classify some directly
experienced particular change as “a change” is ratiocination. All the more so, the
“impermanence” of each totality of experience, moment after moment, is an idea, obtained by
distinguishing successive moments of experience; i.e. by relying on memory, and comparing and
contrasting the experience apparently remembered to the experience currently experienced.
The latter act, note well, requires we cut up “present experience” into two portions, one a
“memory” (inner) appearance and the other a more “currently in process” (inner and/or outer)
appearance. This is rational activity; so, “impermanence” is in fact never directly experienced
(contrary to Buddhist claims). Unity phenomenologically precedes Diversity; therefore, the
experience of diversity cannot logically be considered as disqualifying the belief in underlying
unity.
This argument is not a proof of substance, but at least serves to neutralize the Buddhist denial of
substance. It opens the door to an advocacy of substance9 by adductive means, i.e. in the way of a
legitimate hypothesis to be confirmed by overall consideration of all experience and all the needs
of its consistent conceptualization.
The Greek philosopher Heraclites must have practiced this meditation, when he reportedly wrote “you
cannot step into the same river twice”. This meditation is commonly practiced, even unwittingly. Other similarly
natural meditations consist in watching rain falling, wind blowing through trees, clouds shifting in the sky,
candlelight flickering, or the sparks and flames of a camp or chimney fire. “Watching” of course here means, not just
being aware of sights (shapes and colors), but also awareness of sounds, touch-sensations, temperatures, textures, etc.
9
Note well that an issue within the thesis of substance is whether we advocate a single, undifferentiated
substance, or a multiplicity of distinct substances. To admit of substance is not necessarily to uphold the latter,
pluralist view. In Physics, the unitary substance view would be that matter is all one substance, vibrating in a variety
of ways.
8
18
AVI SION
Note well that I am not here denying validity to the concept of impermanence, but I am only
reminding us that “impermanence” is a concept. Being a concept based on experience of change,
it is indeed a valid concept. This is true whether such change be considered as real or illusory: it
suffices that such change appears phenomenologically for a concept of it to be justified.
The principle of impermanence is more than that the mere concept. It is a generalization of that
concept. It is not a mere statement that change exists – it is a statement that only change exists,
i.e. that everything is continually changing and there is no underlying rest. Now, such a general
proposition logically can simply not be validated with reference to experience alone. There is no
epistemologically conceivable way that, sitting in meditation, the Buddha would be able to
experience this (or any other) principle directly.
This principle (like any other) can indeed conceivably be validated as universal, but only by
adductive methodology. It must be considered as a hypothesis, to be tested again and again
against all new experiences, and compared to competing hypotheses as regards explanatory value.
The result is thus at best an inductive truth, not a pure experience or a pure deduction from
experience.
Furthermore, in addition to the generalization from particular experiences of change to a
metaphysical principle of the ubiquity of change, the principle of impermanence involves a
second fundamental generalization. Since it is a negative principle, it involves the act of
generalization inherent in all negation; that is, the generalization from “I found no permanence in
my present experience” to “There was no permanence to be found in my present experience”.
While the conclusion of negation by such generalization is not in principle logically invalid, it is
an inductive, not a deductive conclusion. It stands ab initio on a more or less equal footing with
the competing speculation that there might well be an underlying permanence of some sort. The
latter positive hypothesis could equally well be (and sometimes is) posited as a postulate, to be
gradually shown preferable to the negative assumption using adductive means.
Even within meditation, note, constancies do appear side by side with changing phenomena, if we
pay attention to them. Thus, for instance, if I meditate on water, I may reflect on the inconstancy
of its surface; but I may also reflect on the underlying constancy (during my period of meditation,
at least) of the horizon or shoreline, or of rocks in or around it, or simply of the fact of water, or
its color and consistency, etc. I may, moreover, later discover that water is uniformly composed
of H2O.
Seen in this light, the status of the principle of impermanence is considerably less sure. To
present such a principle as an absolute truth knowable directly or obtained by some sort of
infallible analysis of experience would be dishonest.
All this is not said to annul the important moral lessons to be drawn from observation of
impermanence. A “principle” of impermanence may still be proposed, if we take it as heuristic,
rather than hermeneutic – i.e. as a useful “rule of thumb”, which helps us realize that it is useless
to attach importance to mundane things, and enjoins us to strive for higher values. Beauty is
passing; pleasures are ephemeral. Life is short, and there is much spiritual work to be done…
With regard to predication of impermanence, it is relevant to ask whether the concrete data
(experiences, appearances) referred to are phenomenal or non-phenomenal, i.e. whether they can
be physically or mentally seen, heard, felt, smelt or tasted, or instead are intuited. To indicate that
the data at hand is phenomenal, and so particularly transient, does not in itself exclude that
relatively less transient non-phenomenal data might also be involved behind the scenes. That is,
LOGICAL CRITICISM OF BUDDHIST DOCTRINES
19
while current objects might be perceivably transient, it does not follow that the one perceiving
them is equally transient.
Of course, whether the data is phenomenal or not, it may still be transient. However, transience
has degrees. Data may be merely momentary, or it may appear more continuously over a more
extended period of time. The issue here is not “transient or eternal”, as some Buddhist
philosophers seem to present it. The issue is “momentary or continuous” – with the eternal as the
extreme case of continuity. It is analytically erroneous to ignore or exclude offhand periods of
existence that are longer than a mere ‘moment’ of time and shorter than ‘eternity’.
Moreover, as already pointed out, the underlying claim that all phenomena, or for that matter all
non-phenomenal events, are transient is not something that can be directly observed – but can
only be based on generalization. There is no a priori logical necessity about such ontological
statements – they are epistemologically bound to be inductive. Even if all appearances
experienced by me or you so far seem transient, there might still be eternal existents our own
transience makes us unable to observe.
Conversely, only an eternal being could experience eternity – and it would take such a being… an
eternity to do so (not a mere few hours, days or years of meditation)!10 This however does not
exclude the possibility of ascribing eternity to certain things on conceptual deductive grounds.
For example, I can affirm the laws of thought to be eternally true, since they are incontrovertible;
or again, I can affirm all contradictions or exclusions of a middle to be eternally false.
Furthermore, Buddhists implicitly if not explicitly ascribe some sort of eternity to the existential
ground in or out of which all transient phenomena bubble up. That is, although particular
existents may well all be transient, the fact of existence as such is eternal. Therefore, their
argument is not really intended as a denial of any permanence whatsoever (as it is often
presented), but more moderately as a denial of permanence to particular existents, i.e. to
fragments of the totality. And of course, in that perspective, their insight is right on.
2. Not an essence, but an entity
Buddhist philosophers have stressed the idea of impermanence, with a view to deny the existence
of “essences” in both the objective and subjective domains. However, an impermanent essence is
not a contradiction in terms. This means that the question of essences is more complex than
merely an issue of impermanence. Several epistemological and ontological issues are involved in
this question. We have indicated some of these issues in the preceding chapters.
10
I am not sure of the truth of this statement of mine. I have in the past argued (among other reasons so as to
provide an argument in favor of the doctrine that God can tell the future) that this issue hinges on the span of time an
onlooker can perceive in one go. The higher one is spiritually placed, the longer a ‘moment’ of time covers. God,
who is “above it all”, at the peak of spiritual perspective, can see all time (all the things we class under the headings
of past, present and future) as the present moment. Proportionately, when we humans meditate, the present is longer,
i.e. the ‘moment’ of time our attention can include at once is enlarged. Thus, one (conceivably) need not wait forever
to experience eternity, but may ultimately do so through spiritual elevation. This may be the “eternal now”
experience many people have reported having. Note additionally that, if we accept this hypothesis, we have to apply
it not only to external events (i.e. phenomenal physical and mental experiences) but also to inner experience (i.e.
intuitions of cognitions, volitions and valuations by self). The latter is more difficult, more problematic, because it
implies that one’s own being and experience is already consumed, i.e. all telescoped into the present. Still, why not.
20
AVI SION
With regard to the objective domain, comprising the material and mental objects of experience,
i.e. the phenomena apparently experienced through the senses or in the mind – their reasoning is
that we never perceive firm “essences” but only constantly changing phenomena; whence, they
conclude, the objects we refer to are “empty”.
In reply, I would say that it is true that many people seem to imagine that the “entities” we refer
to in thought (e.g. a dog) have some unchanging core (call it “dog-ness”), which remains constant
while the superficial changes and movements we observe occur, and which allow us to classify a
number of particulars under a common heading (i.e. all particular dogs as “dogs”).
But of course, if we examine our thought processes more carefully, we have to modify this
viewpoint somewhat. We do “define” a particular object by referring to some seemingly constant
property (or conjunction of properties) in it – which is preferably actual and static, though (by the
way) it might even be a habitual action or repetitive motion or a mere potential.
Note too, there may be more than one property eligible for use as a definition – so long as each
property is constant throughout the existence of that object and is exclusive to it. The defining
property does not shine out as special in some way, and in some cases we might well arbitrarily
choose one candidate among many.
However, defining is never as direct and simple an insight as it may at times seem. It requires a
complex rational activity, involving comparison and contrast between different aspects and
phases of the individual object, and between this object and others that seem similar to it in some
respects though different from it in others, and between that class of object and all others. Thus,
the property used as definition is knowable only through complex conceptual means.
Therefore, our mental separation of one property from the whole object or set of objects is an
artifice. And, moreover, our referring to all apparently similar occurrences of that property as
“one” property gives the impression of objective unity, when in fact the one-ness is only in the
mind of the beholder (though this does not make it unreal). In short, the definition is only an
abstraction. It indeed in a sense exists in the object as a whole, but it is only distinguishable from
the whole through cognition and ratiocination.
The material and mental objects we perceive are, therefore, in fact nothing other than more or less
arbitrary collections of phenomena, among which one or more is/are selected by us on various
grounds as “essential”. The “essence” is a potential that can only be actualized relative to a
rational observer; it has no independent actual existence when no observer is present. Definition
gives us a mental “handle” on objects, but it is not a substitute for them.
An entity is not only its definition. An entity is the sum total of innumerable qualities and events
related to it; some of these are applicable to it throughout its existence (be that existence transient
or eternal) and some of them are applicable to it during only part(s) of its existence (i.e. have a
shorter duration). Although the defining property must be general (and exclusive) to the object
defined, it does not follow that properties that are not or cannot be used for definition cease to
equally “belong to” the object.
It is inexcusably naïve to imagine the essence of an entity as some sort of ghost of the object
coterminous with it. In fact, the entity is one – whatever collection of circumstances happens to
constitute it. The distinction of an essence in it is a pragmatic measure needed for purposes of
knowledge – it does not imply the property concerned to have a separate existence in fact. The
property selected is necessarily one aspect among many; it may be just a tiny corner of the whole
entity.
LOGICAL CRITICISM OF BUDDHIST DOCTRINES
21
We may thus readily agree with Buddhists that named or thought-of objects are “empty”; i.e. that
it is inaccurate to consider each object as really having some defining constant core, whether
phenomenal or non-phenomenal. But the Buddhists go on from there are apply the same
reasoning to the Subject (or soul) – and this is where we may more radically disagree.
They imply that the Subject of cognitions is itself cognized by way of phenomena, i.e. like any
other object. This idea of theirs has some apparent credibility due to the fact that they confuse the
Subject with his ‘inner’, mental phenomena11. But though such phenomena are indeed internal in
comparison to physical phenomena sensed in the body or further out beyond it, they are strictly
speaking external in comparison to the “soul”.
Anyone who reflects a little would not regard, say, the stuff of a dream he had as himself. His
self-awareness is the consciousness of something more inward still than the stuff of imaginations.
He is the one experiencing and generating the imaginations. The soul is not a phenomenon – it
has no smell, taste, solidity, tune or color; it is something non-phenomenal.
The self is not perceived as an object in the way of mental phenomena (as the Buddhists suggest),
but is intuited directly in the way of a Subject apperceiving itself (at least when it perceives other
things, or when it expresses itself through volition or valuation). Our soul is not a presumed
“essence” of our mental phenomenal experiences; it is an entirely different sort of experience.
Of course, it could still be argued that – even granting that acts of cognition, volition and
valuation are non-phenomenal events, known by self-intuition – such acts are mere momentary
events, which do not necessarily imply an underlying non-phenomenal continuity (an abiding
self). Admittedly, the fact that we cannot physically or mentally see, hear, smell, taste or touch
the acts of the self does not logically imply that the self is abiding.
However, note that this last is an argument in favor of the possibility that the self may be
impermanent – it does not constitute an argument against the existence of a self (whether lasting
or short-lived) underlying each act of cognition, volition or valuation. That is, these functions are
inconceivable without someone experiencing, willing and choosing, even if it is conceivable that
the one doing so does not abide for longer than that moment.12
To deny that cognition, volition and valuation necessarily involve a self is to place these apparent
events under an aetiological régime of natural determinism or spontaneity. That subsumes willing
under mechanistic causation or chance happenstance – i.e. it effectively denies the existence of
freewill.
11
See the Buddhist doctrine of the Five Component-Groups. In this doctrine, the fourth and fifth groups,
comprising the “determinants” and the “cognitive faculty”, are particularly misleading, in that cognition, volition and
valuation, the three functions of the self, are there presented without mention of the self, as ordinary phenomenal
events. That is, the doctrine commits a petitio principii, by depicting psychic events in a manner that deliberately
omits verbal acknowledgment of the underlying self, so as to seem to arrive at the (foregone) conclusion that there is
no self. No explanation is given, for instance, as to how we tell the difference between two phenomenally identical
actions, considering one as really willed by oneself, and the other as a reactive or accidental event – for such
differentiation (which is necessary to gauge degrees of responsibility) is only possible by means of self-knowledge,
i.e. introspection into one’s non-phenomenal self, and they have dogmatically resolved in advance not to accept the
existence of a cognizing, willing and valuing self.
12
Note well that I am careful to say the possibility that the self is impermanent; which does not exclude the
equal possibility that the self is permanent. The mere fact that the cognitions, volitions and valuations of the self are
impermanent does not by itself allow us to draw any conclusion either way about the permanence or impermanence
of the self. Additional considerations are needed to draw the latter conclusion.
22
AVI SION
Similarly, it implies that there is no more to knowing than the storing of symbols in a machine (as
if the “information” stored in a computer has any knowledge value without humans to cognize
and understand it, i.e. as if a computer can ever at all know). And again, it implies that valuing or
disvaluing is no more relevant to a living (and in particular sentient) being than it is to a stone.
The effective elimination of these three categories (i.e. knowing, willing and valuing) by
Buddhists (and extreme Materialists, by the way) is without logical justification, because in total
disaccord with common experience.
The confusion may in part be caused or perpetuated by equivocation. Because we often use the
word “mind” – or alternatively, sometimes, “consciousness” – in a loose, large sense, including
the soul, it might be assumed that the soul is similar to mental phenomena in its substance. But
the soul and mind are only proximate in a spatial sense, if at all. The soul is not made of mental
stuff or of consciousness – the soul uses consciousness to observe mental and physical events
(and, indeed, its intimate self).
The self or soul is not an abstraction from mental or physical phenomena. It receives and
cognizes mental and material information (and it indirectly chooses and wills mental and material
events) – but it is not identical with such information (or events).
Only intuited events of cognition, volition and valuation can be considered as truly parts of, and
direct responsibilities of, the soul. And even here, it would be inaccurate to necessarily equate the
soul to these functions. Such a positivistic approach is a hypothesis to be adopted inductively
only if we find no good reason to adopt the alternative hypothesis that the soul is more than the
evidence of its functioning.
Thus, the inevitable impermanence of the phenomenal world cannot be construed as necessarily
implying a similar impermanence for the self. Even granting that material and mental objects are
“empty”, it does not follow that the self is a non-entity, i.e. non-existent as a distinct unit. The self
is not a material or mental substance or entity – but it is a non-phenomenal substance and entity.
We may legitimately label that distinct substance ‘spiritual’ and that entity ‘soul’.
Note well that such labeling does not preclude the idea, previously presented, that the individual
soul’s individuation out from the universal spiritual substance or universal soul is ultimately
illusory. We may thus well consider the soul as impermanent in its individuality, while regarding
its spiritual substance as eternal.
Upon reflection, this is pretty much the way we view the phenomenal realm, too – as consisting
of impermanent illusory individual entities emerging in a permanent real universal substratum.
Their illusoriness is mainly due to the conventionality of their individual boundaries.
At this stage, then, we find ourselves with two ‘monistic’ domains – the one giving rise to
material and mental phenomena and the other giving rise to spiritual entities (souls). Obviously,
such double ‘monism’ is not logically coherent! We therefore must assume that these two
apparently overlapping domains are really ultimately somehow one and the same.
So, we have perhaps come full circle, and our opinions end up pretty much coinciding with the
Buddhists’ after all. We ought perhaps to lay the stress, instead, on our difference with regard to
continuity.
According to Buddhist theory, the self has no continuity, i.e. our self of today is not the same
person as our self of yesterday or of tomorrow. In this perspective, they are causatively
connected, in the sense that earlier conglomerations of phenomena constituting a self ‘cause’ later
ones – but there is no thread of constancy that can be identified as the underlying one and the
LOGICAL CRITICISM OF BUDDHIST DOCTRINES
23
same entity. It is not a case of mere succession of totally discrete events; but there is no essential
identity between the events, either.
However, many (myself included) object to this theory on various grounds. While we may admit
that one can logically regard selfhood (i.e. being a Subject and Agent) as punctual at every instant
without having to assume its extension over a lifetime, we must realize that such an assumption
removes all logical possibility of a concept of moral responsibility for past actions.
If one is no longer ever the same person as the person committing a past virtuous or vicious act,
then no good deed may be claimed by anyone or rewarded, and no crime may be blamed on
anyone or punished. Ex post facto, strictly speaking, the doer of any deed no longer exists.
Similarly, looking forward, there is nothing to be gained or lost by any Agent in doing anything,
since by the time any consequences of action emerge the Agent has already disappeared.
In such a framework, all personal morality and social harmony would be completely destroyed.
There would be no justification for abstaining from vice or for pursuing virtue. Even the pursuit
of spiritual realization would be absurd. Of course, some people do not mind such a prospect,
which releases them from all moral obligations or responsibility and lets them go wild.
It is very doubtful that Buddhism (given its overall concerns and aims) supports such a nihilist
thesis13. In any case, such a viewpoint cannot be considered credible, in the light of all the above
observations and arguments.
© Copyright Avi Sion, 2017. All rights reserved.
Protected by international copyright conventions. No part of this book may be reproduced in any manner whatsoever,
or stored in a retrieval system or transmitted, without express permission of the Author-publisher, except in case of
brief quotations with due acknowledgement.
Logical Criticism of Buddhist Doctrines can be freely read online at avisionbuddhism and in
various other locations.
It can be purchased, in print and e-book editions, in Amazon.com, Lulu.com and many other
online booksellers.
13
Although the Buddhist philosopher Nagarjuna seems to relish it.