Philosophy in Classical India
Recent years have seen the beginning of a radical reassessment of the
philosophical literature of ancient and classical India. The analytical techniques
of contemporary philosophy are being deployed towards fresh and original
interpretations of the texts. This rational, rather than mystical, approach
towards Indian philosophical theory has resulted in a need for a work which
explains afresh its central methods, concepts and devices. This book meets
that need. Assuming no prior familiarity with the texts, Jonardon Ganeri
offers new interpretations which bring out the richness of Indian theory and
the sophistication of its methods. Original in both approach and content,
Philosophy in Classical India contains many new results, analyses and
explanations.
Discussing a diverse range of key Indian thinkers, Ganeri asks: What is the
goal of their philosophical project and what are the methods of rational inquiry
used in their pursuit? Recognising reason as the instrument of all philosophers,
this book studies the active rational principles that drive classical Indian
philosophy. The philosophers discussed here form a network of mutual reference
and criticism, influence and response, and in their work one finds a broad
vein of critical rationality in which reason is at once used constructively and
to call itself into question. The inquiries of the classical Indian philosophers
into the possibilities of human reason are considered afresh: new philosophical
paradigms are unravelled, new applications for the concept of reason are
discovered, and a common philosophical vocabulary is thereby enriched.
Philosophy in Classical India rescues a story suppressed in Orientalist discourses
of the East – the story of reason in a land too often defined as reason’s Other.
Jonardon Ganeri read mathematics at Cambridge before pursuing graduate
studies in philosophy at London and Oxford. He is the author of Semantic
Powers: Meaning and the Mesans of Knowing in Classical Indian Philosophy
(Clarendon Press, 1999). He is currently Spalding Fellow in Comparative
Religions, Clare Hall, Cambridge.
Philosophy in Classical India
The proper work of reason
Jonardon Ganeri
London and New York
First published 2001 by Routledge
11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE
Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada
by Routledge
29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group
This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2006.
“Disclaimer: For copyright reasons, some images in the original version
of this book are not available for inclusion in the eBook.”
“To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’s
collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.”
© 2001 Jonardon Ganeri
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced
or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means,
now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording,
or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in
writing from the publishers.
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
A catalog record for this book has been requested
ISBN 0-203-15827-X Master e-book ISBN
ISBN 0-203-18011-9 (Adobe eReader Format)
ISBN 0-415-24034-4 (hbk)
ISBN 0-415-24035-2 (pbk)
Contents
1
Introduction
1
The motive and method of rational inquiry
7
1.1
1.2
1.3
1.4
1.5
1.6
1.7
1.8
1.9
2
Rationality, emptiness and the objective view
2.1
2.2
2.3
2.4
2.5
2.6
2.7
3
Early recognition of a ‘practice of reason’ 7
Rationality in the Nya-ya-sutra 10
Rationality and the ends of life 15
Perception 17
Mind, attention and the soul 22
Rationality and extrapolation 25
Rationality and debate 28
Reason, scripture and testimony 35
Reason’s checks and balances 37
Further reading 40
Thought and reality 42
Emptiness and the objective view 43
Rationality in Madhyamaka 47
On causation 51
The impossibility of proof 58
A new paradox of motion 63
Self-refutation 66
Further reading 68
The rational basis of metaphysics
3.1
3.2
3.3
3.4
3.5
3.6
42
Order in nature 71
The categorial hierarchy 72
The structure of the world 77
The taxonomy of natural kinds 79
Absence as a type of entity 82
Higher-order absence 85
71
vi
Philosophy in classical India
3.7
3.8
4
How to practise poverty in metaphysics 97
A skeletal ontology 98
Marking and similarity 100
The role of language in conceptual construction
The exclusion theory of meaning 106
Sentence meaning 111
Conditions on rational extrapolation 114
Reasoning from specifics 118
Are reason–target relations law-like? 121
The problem of grounding 123
Further reading 126
Rationality, harmony and perspective
5.1
5.2
5.3
5.4
5.5
5.6
5.7
5.8
6
89
Reduction, exclusion and rational reconstruction
4.1
4.2
4.3
4.4
4.5
4.6
4.7
4.8
4.9
4.10
5
Navya-Nya-ya logic
Number 91
Further reading 95
104
128
A rationality of reconciliation 128
The many-sided nature of things 128
Disagreement defused 130
The epistemology of perspective 134
The logic of assertion 137
Assertion and the unassertible 141
The mark of a good reason 144
Integration and complete knowledge 147
Further reading 149
Reason in equilibrium
6.1
6.2
6.3
6.4
6.5
6.6
97
151
Reason and the management of doubt 151
The burden of proof 153
Criteria for rational rejection 155
Supposition and pretence 158
A new doxastic ascent 159
Epistemic equilibrium 162
Further reading 167
Notes
Texts
Bibliography
Index
169
184
192
203
Introduction
This is a book about philosophical theory in classical India. It is an attempt to
understand the nature of the classical Indian philosophical endeavour, and in
so doing to reveal a richness of projects and a diversity of methods. Reason is
the instrument of all philosophers, but conceptions of the nature and function
of reason vary along with varying ideas about the work for which reason is
properly employed. Manu, the lawmaker, said that those whose only guide is
reason should be banished from the company of the virtuous. That is the view
too of the great narrators of the Indian epics. Reason unchecked was seen as
a threat to the stability of Brahminical social order, as the tool of heretics and
troublemakers. But the epic horror of pure reason was a disdain not for reason
itself, but only for its capricious use, to undermine belief rather than to support
it, to criticise and not to defend. Philosophy in India, or so I argue in Chapter
1, flourished in the space this distinction affords.
The mortal finger in Michelangelo’s Creation stretches out, but cannot
touch the divine hand. Is this an appropriate metaphor for reason itself? Does
the subjectivity that goes along with being situated in the world preclude our
attaining through reason an objective conception of it? Is the idea that human
reason can find nature intelligible in some fundamental way misguided? This
ancient problem is but one of the leitmotivs of philosophical inquiry in classical
India, where radical critiques of reason are as plentiful as more moderate
applications. Brahman, the still divinity, the Upanisadic symbol for objectivity
itself, is that from which ‘before they reach it, words turn back, together with
the mind’.1 But if there are limits to language and reason, can we by reason
come to know what they are and where they lie? Or are the limits of reason
themselves beyond reason’s limit? Can it be rational to strive to transcend the
boundaries of reason, to attempt what one knows to be impossible? If reason
is by its very nature limited, then perhaps the subversion of reason itself
becomes a rational end. That appears to be the conclusion of Nagarjuna, the
founder of Madhyamaka Buddhism, whose philosophical method I examine
in Chapter 2. He reasons that the constructs of reason are as empty as the
magician’s hat, and he welcomes the predictable retort that his own reasoning
is empty too.
2
Philosophy in classical India
Other paradigms abound in India of the nature of philosophical inquiry
and the proper work of reason. Some are familiar, for instance the
instrumentalist conception of reason as promoted by Kautilya, a royal minister,
strategist and educator. Others, less so. In Chapter 3, I show how the Vaisesika
metaphysicians find in reason a tool for the construction of a formal ontology.
A hierarchical theory of categories and natural taxonomies, alleged to be the
metaphysics encoded in the Sanskrit language itself, is interpreted graphically,
giving metaphysics a formal basis. The Yogacara Buddhist, Dinnaga is, by
contrast, an ontological reductionist and a nominalist. He is uncompromising
in his search for unity and simplicity in philosophical explanation, and he
uses the method of rational reconstruction to rebuild our old conceptual
superstructures on new, leaner, foundations. His system is my concern in
Chapter 4. Chapter 5 concerns the Jaina philosophers, who look to reason as
an instrument of harmonisation. The ancient philosophical controversies – so
resistant to solution, so intractable to the up-front reasoning of debate, argument
and evidence – call, it seems, for a new rationality, one whose function is to
subvert the way ordinary language works, making explicit the hidden
parameters in assertion, and so enabling the reasoner to harmonise apparently
conflicting beliefs. The task of reason is again different in the new epistemology
of the later classical writers. The problem now is whether the norms of reason
can themselves be rationally justified, and the idea to be defended is that
reason sustains a wide reflective equilibrium of beliefs, actions, principles
and theories. It is in this way, I argue in Chapter 6, that an attempt is made to
diffuse a critique of reason advanced by the formidable Advaita sceptic,
Sriharsa – that reason seeks to justify itself only at the peril of a viciously
infinite regress.
These are just some of the shifts and turns of the classical Indian concept of
reason, some paradigms for a problematic notion. Many others do not get a
mention here. In particular one may refer to the Mimamsakas, who see in
reason a hermeneutical instrument for the analysis of the Vedas, and to the
Veda-ntins, who wrestle with the relations between reason, authority and
faith. My justification for omitting these approaches is only that a great deal
has already been written about the place of reason in Indian philosophy of
religion, and I want to focus on philosophical agendas overlapping, but not
coextensive with the soteriological. Nor do I feel any need to follow the ‘six
systems’ approach to the study of Indian philosophy, popularised by Max
Müller and later by Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan,2 but too simplistic to do justice
to a complex web of interconnections, themes, personalities and
transformations. The authors I do discuss form a moderately compact network
of mutual reference and criticism, influence and response. In their work one
finds a broad vein of critical rationality, in which reason is used both
constructively and also to put itself in question.
What do we mean when we speak of a culture’s notion of the rational?
Not, of course, that the concept itself is culturally specific, but only that it is
embedded, articulated and manifested in culturally specific ways. J. N.
Introduction
3
Mohanty, a formidable interpreter of India’s past, has observed that the role a
concept of rationality has within a culture is a highly stratified one, its criteria
and principles operating ‘first of all in the life-world of the community
concerned, then in the higher-order decisions of the scientists, law-givers and
artists, finally in the theoretical discourse of the philosophers’.3 There is much
truth in this remark. New paradigms of what it is to act and believe rationally
come into being as old concepts are criticised, revised and rejected. A
particularly fine example of this approach to the analysis of Indian theory is
Bimal Matilal’s study of the concept of reason embedded in changing treatments
of moral dilemmas in the epic literature and dharmasastras.4 His idea is that
a diachronic study of conceptions about what constitutes an adequate resolution
to a moral dilemma illuminates both shifts in the notion of reason itself, and
also the mechanics of internal criticism, theory revision and paradigm rejection.
Forms of rationality are, I maintain, interculturally available even if they
are not always interculturally instantiated. In an influential and thoughtprovoking essay, A. K. Ramanujan5 has advanced a thesis contrary to mine.
His claim is that there is a type-difference between Indian and western modes
of reason. Drawing his conclusion from a range of linguistic and
anthropological evidence, Ramanujan suggests that norms of reason are
conceived as ‘context-sensitive’ in India, whereas in the West they are ‘contextfree.’ The distinction is one he derives from linguistics, in which context-free
rules, such as that every sentence has a verb, are contrasted with rules that
are sensitive to grammatical context, such as the rule governing pluralisation
of nouns in English. I have no objection as such to distinctions of this sort, but
only to their application. It can at best be only a contingent truth, a historical
fact about the exemplification of paradigms, that such a separation should
exist, and if so it is of limited philosophical significance. In fact, my
investigations here have convinced me that East–West type-difference
hypotheses of such generality are definitely false.6 Some paradigms for the
rational can be found in both cultures, for example, instrumentalism and the
epistemic conception of reason. Others, for instance the Jaina notion of a
rationality of reconciliation, or the modelling of reason by game-theory, are
found in one, but not the other. The point is to discover new forms of rationality
and applications of the concept of reason, and so to enrich a common
philosophical vocabulary. We become in this way aware of possibilities for
reason we had forgotten or had not yet seen.
Might I not be accused of a reconfigured Orientalism in looking for
expressions of rationality in Indian philosophy, on the grounds that the West
is again setting the standard? As one critic has said, ‘[w]hy is a need felt to
describe the “rationality” of the Indian philosophies, to assert that Indian
philosophers were “as rational” as their western counterparts? Such a general
project would not be conceived of with regard to western philosophy, because
the West sets the paradigm. We look in our traditions for what is to be found
in the West, like the sense-reference distinction. But why should we even look
for such a distinction?’7 I suggest that the criticism here depends on a failure
4
Philosophy in classical India
to distinguish sufficiently carefully between philosophical problems and
philosophical explanations. The point is not to comb the Indian literature for
the sense-reference distinction, but for their solutions to the problem that
distinction was invented to solve, a problem that is as real for Fregeans as for
those who reject his distinction, as real for Indian philosophers of language as
for their western colleagues.8 If the objection is simply that ‘rationality’ is a
western concept imperiously misapplied, my response would be that it is no
more western than perception, thought, language or morality. The mistake
here is in thinking of such philosophical concepts as internal to a theory,
when in fact they are concepts about which there can be many theories (a
distinction particularly well articulated in Canguilhem’s philosophy of science9).
Indeed, so far from being Orientalist, the project envisaged here is that of
rescuing a story suppressed by Orientalism – the story of reason in a land too
often defined as reason’s Other.
In analysing the philosophical literature of classical India, then, I adopt an
approach neither comparative nor historical. Philosophy is not history, even
if both disciplines are relevant to the study of classical India. History studies
ideas in their context – it situates an author in an intellectual milieu. Philosophy,
on the other hand, tries to free an idea from its context – it separates the idea
from what is parochial and contingent in its formulation. The historian of
Indian philosophy must be sensitive to the character of a philosophical thesis,
but ought not indulge in wanton borrowing from other philosophical literatures.
David Seyfort Ruegg offered some timely methodological advice when he
said that the historian of Indian thought should ‘beware of anachronistically
transposing and unsystematically imposing the concepts of modern semantics
and philosophy, which have originated in the course of particular historical
developments, on modes of thought that evolved in quite different historical
circumstances, and which have therefore to be interpreted in the first place in
the context of their own concerns and the ideas they themselves developed’.10
The historian’s worst crime is anachronism, displacing a concept and resituating
it in some new and inappropriate context.
A philosopher has also to be guarded, but for different reasons. The
philosopher must take care not to mistake contingent properties in the contextual
formulation of an argument or idea for essential properties of the argument or
idea itself. If the historian’s worst crime is anachronism, that of the philosopher
is parochialism, failing to separate the idea from its context. The philosopher’s
goal is to decontextualise. It is not to recontextualise, to situate old ideas
within the context of current philosophical concerns, except in so far as those
concerns are themselves context-neutral. The philosopher examining the Indian
theories is for this reason justified in using the modern philosophical idiom as
a generally shared and convenient vehicle in which to frame his discussion.
The concerns of the classical Indians are clearly recognisable as philosophical,
and in using a contemporary idiom, one’s aim is to bring out the philosophical
structure of those concerns, whether or not they coincide with anything in
contemporary philosophical theory. My goal then is not the mere comparison
Introduction
5
of one idea with another, but the unravelling of new philosophical paradigms.
It would be rather to miss the point to criticise that venture on the grounds of
a difference in the preoccupations, religious beliefs and motivations of the
classical philosophers. For discoveries made by the classical Indian
investigators into the possibilities of human reason can be of interest and
relevance even in different times and other cultures. There are indeed, as
David Hume once said, more species of metaphor in this world than any one
person can have dreamed.11 My approach, distinct both from comparative
philosophy and from the history of ideas, is instead a critical and analytical
evaluation of conceptual paradigms in Indian theory.
To help those who are coming to the subject anew, I have added to each
chapter a list of texts as a guide to further reading. I also give, in the list of
philosophical texts discussed in this book, as comprehensive an indication as
I can of what translations are available at the present time. Many of the
important texts have been translated at one time or another, and even if some
of the older translations are not to a modern standard, they do at least help
open up the subject to non-Sanskritists. Unless otherwise specified, however,
the translations in this book are my own.
I would like to express my gratitude to the British Academy, whose award
under the Research Leave Scheme in 1999 freed me from departmental duties,
and so gave me the time to prepare a typescript. Heartfelt thanks too to
Gillian Evison, Simon Lawson, Helen Topsfield, Elizabeth Krishna and
Kalpana Pant, librarians of the Indian Institute in Oxford, an invaluable
research archive wherein I found all the materials I needed for this book. It is
a pleasure to thank Roger Thorp and Hywel Evans at Routledge, who have
been meticulous in overseeing the production of the book at every stage, and
also to thank the referees for many helpful comments. Thanks too to Piotr
Balcerowicz, Arindam Chakrabarti, Brendan Gillon, Stephen Phillips and
Richard Sorabji for their sustained encouragement. The experience of trying
for a number of years to teach courses on Indian Philosophy at King’s College
London and the University of Nottingham has been an important stimulus for
the ideas developed in this book, and I have benefited from the keen critical
faculties of my students in both institutions. Above all, however, it has been
the teachings and writings of my late supervisor, Bimal Krishna Matilal,
which have inspired and sustained me, as indeed they have many others, and
it is with pleasure and gratitude that I dedicate this book to him.
Jonardon Ganeri
1 The motive and method of
rational inquiry
1.1 EARLY RECOGNITION OF A ‘PRsACTICE OF REASON’
Reason can be used or abused. A cautionary episode in the Mahabharata
illustrates the point. Bhisma tells Yudhisthira that there is nothing more worth
having than wisdom. Wisdom, he declares, is the greatest good, the refuge of
all living things, the ultimate acquisition, and is considered by the virtuous to
be heaven itself (12.173.2). But then, in case his point should be
misunderstood, he recounts the story of Indra appearing in the form of a
jackal (12.173.45–8):
I used to be scholarly [says Indra], a reasoner, a scorner of the Veda. I was
pointlessly fond of critical inquiry and the science of argument. I used to
make declarations on the basis of logic; in assemblies, speaking with
reasons, I harangued the brahmins and was rude during the Vedic
recitations. I was an unbeliever, sceptical about everything, and though
stupid, I thought myself wise. The status of a jackal that I have obtained
is the result, Kasyapa, of my misdeeds.
The terms in which Indra deprecates himself are important ones, for they
gradually came to be associated with the practice of philosophy itself in
India. Indra was a ‘reasoner’ (haituka), he was addicted to the study of
critical inquiry (anviksiki) and to the science of argument (tarka-vidya). That
free thinking of this sort was seen as embodying a danger to the stability of
orthodox brahminical learning is only too clear. In another epic narrative,
the Ramayana, Rama advises his brother Bharata to steer well clear of such
people (2.94.32–33):
You must not associate with those ‘worldly’ (lokayata) brahmins, dear
brother. Their only skill is in bringing misfortune; they are fools who
think themselves wise. In spite of the pre-eminent treatises on right conduct
(dharma), these ignorant people derive their ideas from critical inquiry,
and make declarations without any point.
8
Philosophy in classical India
These ‘reasoners’ represent a challenge and a threat to the existing tradition.
They will assent to the deliverances of reason whether or not it agrees with
the scriptures and the authorities on what is considered to be proper conduct.
The lawmaker Manu therefore advises that a brahmin who has adopted the
science of reasoning, treating with contempt the twin authorities on proper
conduct (the scriptures and the texts on right conduct or dharma), should as
an ‘unbeliever’ and a ‘scorner of the Vedas’ be driven from the company of
the virtuous.1
It is not that in the great epics reason as such is condemned, but only its
capricious use. The ‘reasoners’ are condemned for lacking any goal other
than the use of reason itself; they believe in nothing and are sceptical of
everything. They use reason to criticise the scriptures, but have no doctrines
of their own. Reason, the message seems to be, is misapplied when it is used
in a purely negative, destructive way. In other words, the proper use of reason
should be to support, and not to undermine, one’s beliefs, goals and values.
The objection to the reasoners, as they are represented in the epics, is that for
them the use of reason has become an end in itself. It is goalless, capricious,
ungrounded.
The idea that the use of reason must be purposeful or goal-directed is
taken up in the Treatise on Gains (Arthasastra), a famous book on
government, politics and economics which dates from around 300 BC. Its
author is Kautilya, supposed to have been the chief minister in the court of
Candragupta, a Mauryan ruler who came to power at about the time of
Alexander’s death. The period following Alexander’s campaign in India
was in fact a time of intimate and extended contact between India and
Greece. The ancient Greek chronicler Megasthenes frequently visited the
court of Candragupta and in his Indica he presented to the Greeks a vivid
account of the Indian society of those times. Fragments of this lost work
quoted by later writers reveal Megasthenes to have been greatly impressed
by similarities between Greek and Indian ideas, especially about space,
time and the soul.2 He is also said to have carried messages between
Candragupta’s son Bindusara, the father of Asoka, and Antiochus I. Bindusara
indeed asked Antiochus to send him Greek wine, raisins, and a Sophist to
teach him how to argue. Antiochus replied by sending the wine and raisins,
but regretted that it was not considered good form among the Greeks to
trade in Sophists!
Kautilya’s purpose in writing the Treatise on Gains was to educate future
kings in the necessary skills required for a successful and prosperous rule. He
states that there are four branches of learning in which a young prince should
be trained: the religious canon composed of the three Vedas; the sciences of
material gain, primarily trade and agro-economics; the science of political
administration and government; and finally anviksiki, the discipline of critical
inquiry, of which samkhya, yoga and lokayata are listed as the principal
divisions. Significantly, he rejects explicitly the claim of Manu and others
that the study of critical reasoning is tied exclusively to a religious study of
The motive and method of rational inquiry
9
the self and its liberation (atmavidya). Critical inquiry is an autonomous
discipline (1.2.11):
Investigating by means of reasons, good and evil in the Vedic religion,
profit and loss in the field of trade and agriculture, and prudent and
imprudent policy in political administration, as well as their
relativestrengths and weaknesses, the study of critical inquiry (anviksiki)
confers benefit on people, keeps their minds steady in adversity and in
prosperity, and produces adeptness of understanding, speech and action.
He reiterates an old couplet (1.2.12):
The study of critical inquiry is always thought of as a lamp for all branches
of knowledge, a means in all activities, and a support for all religious
and social duty.
Shortly after the rediscovery and publication of the Treatise on Gains in
1909, Hermann Jacobi wrote an article arguing that Kautilya had to all
extents distinguished and defined ‘philosophy’ in India.3 Kautilya’s separation
of a study of ‘critical inquiry’ (anviksiki) from theological studies was enough,
he conjectured, to justify the identification of ‘critical inquiry’ with philosophy.
This rather important conjecture has been strongly disputed, on the grounds
that critical inquiry as described by Kautilya consists simply in the art of
investigating by reasons, and this is something that is practised in all branches
of learning. Paul Hacker4 makes the point that this ‘critical inquiry’ is not
necessarily an independent system of thought, but is sometimes rather a method.
In the same vein, it has very plausibly been conjectured5 that the early
references to samkhya, yoga and lokayata are not to well-defined schools of
philosophical speculation, but reflect instead a methodological division. Thus
samkhya labels the methods of inquiry that rest on the intellectual enumeration
of basic principles, yoga the methods of spiritual practice, and lokayata the
methods of worldly or empirical investigation.
We can agree with these conjectures without having to identify philosophy
as a discipline with the having or inventing of a system of thought. Philosophy
is circumscribed by adherence to a certain methodology and body of problems.
Broadly, it is the a priori analysis of the interconnections and distinctions
between groups of concepts to do with the nature of value, thought, existence
and meaning. It is indeed possible to hear in Kautilya’s remark about
‘investigating . . . good and evil in the Vedic religion, profit and loss in the
field of trade and agriculture, and prudent and imprudent policy in political
administration’ a suggestion that a reasoned investigation is an inquiry into
the nature of the distinction between good and evil, the proper goals of political
institutions, and so on. But the intended domain of application for critical
inquiry seems to be much wider than that. It encompasses any situation in
which one sets about achieving one’s aims in a reasoned way. There is a
10
Philosophy in classical India
reasoned way to go about making a profit, a reasoned way to rule a country.
The study of what such reasoning consists in is one thing, the philosophical
investigation of the nature of profit or rule quite another. So anviksiki in
Kautilya’s sense is a study of the generic concept of rationality, as that concept
features in questions about how rationally to think, how rationally to act, and
how rationally to speak.
Kautilya’s conception of rationality is goal-oriented and instrumental. The
interest is in the reasoned way to achieve some goal, whatever that goal may
be. The use of reason does not tell us for which goals one should strive, but
only how rationally to strive for them. The Arthasastra is, after all, a manual
of instruction for princes. The discipline Kautilya calls that of critical inquiry
is the one which trains the prince in the way for him to fulfil his projects,
having once decided what those projects are to be. The other sciences, of
trade and agriculture, of policy-making and government, train him in the
skills of choosing one objective rather than another. A person is rational when
he uses rational methods to reach his aims. (Kautilya wanted kings to become
philosophers, not as Plato that philosophers be made kings.) It is not enough
to be rational that the aim be in some sense a ‘worthy’ one, for even worthy
goals can be striven for by irrational means.
Bertrand Russell6 said that ‘reason’ ‘signifies the choice of the right means
to an end that you wish to achieve. It has nothing to do with the choice of
ends.’ The epic horror of the reasoner concerned the aimless use of reason,
using reason capriciously or solely to subvert the goals of others. Kautilya’s
defence makes rationality instrumental and therefore goal-directed. It follows,
however, that a tyrant can be just as rational as a ruler who is beneficent, an
atheist as rational as a believer. If rationality is instrumental, then to act
rationally is not the same as to act well. Followers of reason alone still face
the charge of immorality, hereticism and untruth.
1.2 RATIONALITY IN THE NYAYASUTRA
Gautama Aksapada’s Nyayasutra, the redaction of which took place in the
first or second century AD, deals with such themes as the procedures for
properly conducting debates, the nature of good argument, and the analysis
of perception, inference and testimony in so far as they are sources of
knowledge. There is a detailed account of the causal structure of the mind
and the nature of its operation. Certain metaphysical questions are addressed,
notably the reality of wholes, atoms and universals. At the beginning of his
commentary on this remarkable work, Vatsyayana Paksilasvamin (c. AD
400) wonders what it is that makes the Nyaya system distinctive. He answers
as follows:
Nyaya is the examination of things with the help of methods of knowing
(pramana). It is an inference supported by observation and authority.
This is called a ‘critical proof’ (anviksa). A ‘critical proof’ is the proof of
The motive and method of rational inquiry
11
things desired, supported by observation and authority. The discipline of
critical inquiry is the one which pertains to it, and is also called the
science of nyaya or the writings on nyaya. But an inference that contradicts
observation and authority is only a bogus-nyaya.7
Vatsyayana agrees with Kautilya that the study of critical inquiry is one of
the four branches of study, but he insists that it has its own procedures or
methodology. He claims that if critical inquiry did not have its own procedures
then it would ‘merely be a study of the soul’s progress, like an Upanisad’.
This is a rather important remark. Reasoned inquiry and scriptural studies
are now claimed to have the same eventual goal or purpose; where they differ
is in method. That marks a departure from Kautilya’s purely instrumental
conception of rationality, in which the use of reason could equally well serve
any end. For Vatsyayana wants to claim that there can be rational goals, as
well as rational means, and so to distance the Nyaya system from the freethinkers in the epics.
Let us first see that Vatsyayana shares the epic horror of aimless reason.
Reason, he says, can be used in one of three ways. One may employ it in a
good and proper way (vada), as one does when one’s goal is to ascertain the
truth of the matter. One may employ it in a bad or improper way (jalpa), as
when one’s goal is to defend one’s position at all costs, using any intellectual
tricks one can think of. Finally, one might employ reason in a negative and
destructive way (vitanda). Here one has no goal other than to undermine
one’s opponent. People who use reason in this way are very like the sceptics
and unbelievers of the epics, and Vatsyayana disapproves. He claims indeed
that to use reason in this way is virtually self-defeating:
A vaitandika is one who employs destructive criticism. If when questioned
about the purpose [of so doing], he says ‘this is my thesis’ or ‘this is my
conclusion,’ he surrenders his status as a vaitandika. If he says that he
has a purpose, to make known the defects of the opponent, this too is the
same. For if he says that there is one who makes things known or one
who knows, or that there is a thing by which things are made known or a
thing made known, then he surrenders his status as a vaitandika.8
Vitanda is the sceptic’s use of reason. Vatsyayana’s point is that someone who
presents an argument against a thesis has at least that refutation as their goal,
and so commits himself to the machinery of critical examination. But a
vaitandika who accepts this gives up his claim to use reason aimlessly, without
commitment. So the aimless use of reason is not just pernicious, it is selfdefeating!
The salient point here is that reason must have a purpose, and the question
is what that purpose should be. Vatsyayana’s answer is clever. He argues that
a goal is a rational one if it is the rational means to some further goal. And he
claims that whatever one’s eventual goal is, the rational way to achieve it is
12
Philosophy in classical India
through the acquisition of knowledge – knowledge about one’s goal and how
it might be achieved. So the acquisition of knowledge is always a rational
goal. Indeed it is the rational goal par excellence, for knowledge is instrumental
in the rational pursuit of any other goal:9
Since there is success in one’s activities when the awareness of one’s object
is produced by an accredited method of knowing (pramana), the method
of knowing is connected with the object. Without a method of knowing,
there is no awareness of the object. Without an awareness of the object,
there is no success in one’s activities. But the knower, having grasped the
object in thought by some suitable method, either desires it or wants to
avoid it. His ‘activity’ is the effort prompted by his desire for or aversion
of it. ‘Success’ is the coming together of that activity with its reward.
Desiring the object, or wanting to avoid it, one either makes an effort to
obtain it or else to avoid it. One’s ‘object’ is the contentment [one feels]
and the cause of that contentment, or the disdain and the cause of that
disdain.
Let me take a simple example. Suppose my goal is to acquire a piece of silver.
To succeed, I need to know where silver might be found, and how to recognise
it; I need to be in a position to know, of some object, that it is made of silver.
I need to know other things as well, such as that I have some way of acquiring
the silver once identified. So the reasoned way for me to go about acquiring a
piece of silver is to seek to acquire knowledge of the identifying traits,
whereabouts and means of acquiring of silver objects. The acquisition of such
knowledge becomes itself a goal, subsidiary to my principal aim of acquiring
silver.
In the translation, I have tried to retain an ambiguity in the Sanskrit word
artha, in rendering it as ‘object’. It can mean both one’s goal, such as acquiring
silver, and also the thing which that goal concerns, the silver itself. It is the
target of one’s endeavour, both as the piece of silver, and equally well as the
acquiring of that silver. Vatsyayana suggests that it can also denote the
satisfaction one feels on achieving one’s goal, or the irritation of not doing so.
Later on,10 he stresses that, in virtue of the connection that exists between
knowledge of the object and success or failure in one’s goals concerning it,
one should employ some suitable method of knowing if one wants to succeed.
The theory of rationality in this way depends on a theory of the proper means
of acquiring true beliefs.
Kautilya said that the study of critical inquiry is the study of the notion of
‘investigating with reasons’. Vatsyayana tells us what a ‘reason’ (hetu) is. It is
a method of acquiring knowledge, a pramana. For a ‘reasoned’ inquiry is one
which is based on the acquisition of knowledge. The early Nyaya writers
look closely at the characteristic method that constitutes a rational inquiry.
The opening verse in the Nyayasutra is a list of sixteen items which, according
to its author, comprise the subject matter of the Nyaya system. The first two
The motive and method of rational inquiry
13
items are the various methods of knowing and the domain of knowables.
They constitute the Nyaya epistemology and metaphysics. The next seven
are the theoretical components in the process of critical inquiry: doubt, purpose,
observational data, doctrinal bases, extrapolative demonstration, suppositional
reasoning, and a final decision. The final seven are terms of art in the theory
of debate. Nyayasutra 1.1.1:
The highest goal in life is reached through knowledge about the nature of:
(a) knowables, methods of knowing,
(b) doubt, purpose, observational data, doctrinal bases, the parts of a
demonstration, suppositional reasoning, final decision,
(c) truth-directed debate, victory-directed debate,
destructive debate, sophistical rejoinders, tricks, false reasons, defeat
situations.
A properly conducted inquiry, adds Vatsyayana, is that process by which we
move from an initial uncertainty about the nature of the thing or concept
under investigation, to an ascertainment of its properties. The inquiry is
permitted to draw upon such data as are incontrovertible or accepted by both
parties in the dispute, and it proceeds by adducing evidence or reasons in
support of one side or the other. The first element here is the existence of a
doubt (samsaya) which initiates the investigation. A doubt is said to be a
mental state whose content is of the form ‘Does this object have a certain
specified property or not?’ Typical doubts discussed in the Nyayasutra (is the
soul eternal or non-eternal?, is a whole object identical with the sum of its
parts?) tend to be philosophical conjectures or hypotheses, but the method
applies just as well to the resolution of empirical questions.
An inquiry must have a purpose. The assumption is that any form of rational
behaviour must have some motivating purpose, the point for which one wishes
to resolve the doubt. The inquiry can appeal to shared background doctrinal
principles and empirical data. Here, by ‘empirical data,’ what is meant are
the observational facts to which all parties can appeal. The background
principles are called ‘doctrinal bases’ or ‘proved doctrines’, and might also
include a category of a priori truths or principles. Gautama actually mentions
several kinds of doctrinal base. In particular, there are those which everyone
must accept, for example that objects of knowledge are established via means
of knowing. Other doctrinal principles are in the form of conditionals, where
both parties agree on the truth of the conditional, but dispute the truth of the
antecedent. Also mentioned are assumptions which are made merely for the
sake of argument. One or both sides might grant some principle, simply to
facilitate the inquiry. In any case, having initiated an inquiry for some purpose,
and taken into consideration both empirical evidence and such doctrinal or a
priori considerations, the investigation concludes with the decision, which is
a resolution of the initiating doubt.
14
Philosophy in classical India
Similar characterisations of the general structure of problem-solving are
offered in the contemporary literature on formal heuristics.11 There a problem
is defined as one in which the following features are specified and delimited:
a goal – a criterion of judging outcomes; an initial state, consisting of a
situation and the resources available for the solution; a set of admissible
operations for transforming states; constraints on states and operations; and
an outcome. It would seem that the Nyaya account fits rather nicely this
characterisation of the structure of a problem-solving set-up. The doubt is an
initial state of uncertainty, the purpose is the goal, the admissible operations
are the sanctioned methods of reasoning by extrapolative demonstration
(Chapter 1.6) and supposition (tarka, for which see Chapter 6), the constraints
are the observational data and doctrinal bases to which all parties agree, and
the outcome is the final decision. A critical inquiry, then, is a formal heuristic
for problem-solving.
Nyayasutra 1.1.1 makes a further demand on the type of proof procedure
admissible in a critical inquiry. It insists that the inquirer be able explicitly to
set out for others the piece of knowledge so acquired as the conclusion of a
precisely formulated demonstration (avayava). In its general schematic form,
a demonstration scheme has five steps:
(i) Preliminary statement of the thesis to be proved.
(ii) Citation of a reason.
(iii) Invoking an example.
(iv) Application to the present case.
(v) Assertion with confidence of the conclusion.
For example: (i) There is a fire on the mountain. (ii) Because there is smoke
there. (iii) As in the kitchen. (iv) The mountain is the same. (v) Therefore,
there is fire there. I will look in detail at the structure of such argument
schemes in a later section (Chapter 1.7). I am interested here in what the
demand for demonstration tells us about the nature of critical inquiry, an
investigation ‘with reasons’. The early Nyaya writers want to explicate the
notion of a reason. Since the rational way to achieve one’s goals is by
acquiring knowledge about its constituents, it might seem that a reason is any
method of acquiring knowledge (pramana). However, the insistence now is
that the rational inquirer be able to set out his reasoning in an explicit and
canonical way. And a ‘reason’ is the premise or evidence (hetu) in such a
suitably formulated argument. Vatsyayana explains that the various means
of acquiring knowledge have a subsidiary role here. They enter the account
as the means by which each step in the explicitly formulated demonstration is
proven:12
The means of acquiring knowledge reside in those [demonstration steps].
The preliminary statement of the thesis is an item of testimony (agama).
The reason (hetu) is an item of inference. The example is an item of
The motive and method of rational inquiry
15
perception. The application is an item of ‘analogical comparison’. The
final conclusion exhibits the possibility of all these coming together in a
single thesis. Such is a nyaya par excellence. With the help of this alone
can truth-directed, victory-directed and destructive debate techniques be
employed, never otherwise. Fixing the truth depends on this. The steps in
the demonstration are sentences, and as such are included among the
objects of knowledge; but they are mentioned separately for the above
reasons.
Vatsyayana’s systematising idea is that the three strands out of which the
Nyaya system is formed – theory of knowledge, study of critical inquiry and
art of debate – can be brought together into a single discipline. In doing so, he
introduces a new condition on a rational inquiry: that it be capable of being
made public through verbal demonstration. A rational inquiry is, to be sure,
a procedure for reaching one’s goal which exploits knowledge about that goal
and the most effective way to achieve it. But it must also be knowledge of the
sort that can be displayed. It must be knowledge that is backed up by reasons
of the sort that are potentially capable of convincing others, something that
can stand up to the scrutiny of a debate.
There is a conflict here between two accounts of the source of rational
norms. On the one hand, to proceed rationally is to proceed by acquiring
knowledge of an appropriate sort. But on the other hand, to proceed rationally
is publicly to adduce reasons and arguments for the knowledge one purports
to have. The first is an epistemic conception of norms, while the second grounds
norms in the public conventions of the debating hall. The early Naiyayikas,
drawing on their roots in the systematisation of debating theory, insist that
rationality must be a public affair, an explicit demonstration in the five-step
format, but they try to merge this idea with another, that the norms of reason
are the norms of warranted belief. The tension between these two concepts of
reason will manifest itself again as we examine in later sections other
paradigms of rationality in the Nyayasutra.
1.3 RATIONALITY AND THE ENDS OF LIFE
The early Naiyayikas have linked the pursuit of rational inquiry with the
final ends of life. Nyayasutra 1.1.1 states that it is by understanding the
nature of reasoned inquiry, epistemology and debating theory that one attains
the ‘highest goal’ (nihsreyasa). Nyayasutra 1.1.2 amplifies the point, adducing
an exact sequence of causal relations between knowledge and liberation
(apavarga).
The final aim of life is the permanent elimination of duhkha. Duhkha is a
difficult term in Indian soteriology. Its meaning is: suffering, pain, discontent,
frustration, displeasure. What then is the source of all this discontent? One
source has already been mentioned by Vatsyayana in the passage quoted
before – the frustration of one’s plans. Obtaining one’s goals is an end in
16
Philosophy in classical India
itself, but so too is the pleasure or contentment that success instils. It is not just
that in obtaining the piece of silver, I gain as well the pleasures that go with
possessing a valuable thing. It is also that fulfilling one’s projects is a form of
satisfaction in its own right. Vatsyayana stresses, however, that the final aim
of life must involve a separation from pleasures as well as pains. For pleasure
is invariably attended by pain, as if it were honey mixed with poison! So the
ultimate aim in life consists in the elimination of any attachment to the
success or failure of one’s projects, or the rewards or discomforts such projects
bring.
Can a life of reason help one achieve this? Kautilya perhaps thought so, for
he said that pursuing one’s goals by means of rational inquiry helps to keep
the mind steady in both adversity and prosperity. The Naiyayika thinks so
too (NS 1.1.2):
Liberation results from the removal of the next member when the
immediately preceding member is removed in the sequence of: wrong
belief, bad qualities, actions, birth, suffering.
This is the pan-Indian karma theory, a causal theory of moral retribution.
There is a direct causal link between the moral quality of one’s present actions
and one’s future contentment or frustration in this birth or another (a
commentator13 points out that by ‘actions’ here what is meant is righteous
and unrighteous conduct, since it is such conduct that is the cause of birth and
rebirth). We observed earlier that with a purely instrumental conception of
rationality, it is no more rational to do good than to do evil. To be rational is
simply to set about one’s aims in a reasoned way. In the context of a causal
theory of moral retribution, however, it is rational to strive to do good. For
given that one’s final aim in life is to avoid frustration (presumably including
the frustration of one’s future plans), one has a reason to behave well now and
do good. At least, one has a reason as long as one knows that there is a direct
causal link of the sort described. After all, acquiring knowledge about the
sources of frustration and suffering is the rational way to accomplish one’s
aim of eliminating them!
The rational life is a life best suited to eliminate at least one source of
suffering, namely the frustration of having one’s plans fail. So if one’s ultimate
end in life is to avoid suffering, and the main source of suffering is due to the
frustration of one’s plans, one has a reason to live a rational life. Moreover
since, when one examines the general causes of suffering and frustration,
what one finds is that future frustration is caused by past immoral deeds, one
has a reason to have only moral deeds as one’s goal. Someone who believes
in the karma theory of moral retribution has a reason to strive to do good and
not to do evil. One final link is needed to complete the picture. It is that bad
or immoral deeds are the result of false beliefs. Once one knows this, one has
a reason to strive for only true beliefs. For if one has only true beliefs, then
one cannot do wrong, cannot incur the moral cost of future frustration, and so
The motive and method of rational inquiry
17
will succeed in life’s ultimate goal of eliminating such frustrations. One has,
therefore, a reason to strive to minimise false beliefs, and so to study the
sources of true belief and knowledge. And, in so far as a study of the Nyaya
system is the best method of achieving one’s highest goals, one should study it
through repeated reflection, discussion with others and by engaging in friendly
debates (NS 4.2.47–9).
This then is the reason why the study of epistemology and critical inquiry,
in short of the Nyaya philosophy, is instrumental in achieving one’s final
aims. There is an elegant explanatory closure here. One might not be inclined
to agree with every step in the explanatory chain. While it is plausible that
there is a dependency between the degree of success or failure of one’s plans
and the extent of falsity in one’s beliefs, it is less easy to see that the dependency
is mediated by the moral value of one’s actions. Even if one were tempted to
omit that link, or regard the tie between rationality and moral behaviour
differently, the explanatory scheme affords a marvellous account of the
relationship between the study of philosophy and the quest for life’s final
ends.
1.4 PERCEPTION
The Buddhist asserts that perception of objects is itself a rational activity.
One does not, properly speaking, perceive the object at all, but only patterns
of colour, sound, touch, smell and taste. From their sequence in time and
arrangement in space, one infers the presence of an object of one kind or
another. Reason here is a mental faculty of construction, synthesis and superimposition. It brings order to the array of sensory data. The early Naiyayika,
however, has tied reason to explicit demonstration and proof. He has no
place for the idea of reason as an inner mental faculty of sensory integration.
Since there is no logical connection between the capacity to see an object and
the capacity to describe it, one is led instead to the idea that objects enter
directly into the content of perceptual experience. The Naiyayika rightly
worries that if reason has a role in the construction or synthesis of the objects
of perception, then realism about those objects is threatened. However, he
allows reason to have a role in the organisation of the totality of one’s
perceptions. Kalidas Bhattacharya accurately, if enigmatically, assessed the
idea when he said that ‘thought as judgement, according to Nyaya, is either
the perception of a passive unity of different data in substantive-adjective
relation, or, going beyond perception, conscious management of data through
actual use of language.’14
I begin with the Nyayasutra definition. Vatsyayana would later classify
the sutras into three kinds: ‘naming’ sutras, which introduce a topic or concept
for analysis; ‘defining’ sutras, which offer a definition of the concept in question;
and ‘critical’ sutras, which examine and evaluate the adequacy of the proposed
definition. A definition is a property co-extensive with the concept to be defined.
A definition is faulty if it is either too wide or too narrow – showing that it has
18
Philosophy in classical India
neither of these faults is the purpose of the ‘critical’ sutras. The Nyaya method
here is not very different from the technique of finding necessary and sufficient
conditions. Notice however that it does not tell us what the essence of the
thing defined is, but rather gives us a syndrome, a criterion for distinguishing
between it and all other kinds of thing.
Nyayasutra 1.1.4 is a ‘defining’ sutra. It is the definition of perception:
Perception is an awareness which, produced from the connection between
sense-organ and object, is non-verbal, non-errant, and determinate in
nature.
A perception is an awareness that stands in a certain special relation to its
object. The attempt is to define that relation in purely non-cognitive terms. If
the attempt is successful, then perception is a physical anchor between the
subject and the external world. It is not itself cognitive, but rather supplies the
raw material for cognition and so for reason.
What constraints are there on the physical relation that obtains between a
perceiver’s perceptions and the object perceived? A first constraint is just that
the relation be physical, so that it is not explicated in terms of semantic
relations such as that of denotation. This is what is meant by the assertion
that perception is ‘non-verbal’. Second, the relation has to have the right
extension: it needs to hold between perceptions and the sorts of object one is
normally regarded as capable of perceiving. Uddyotakara (c. AD 500) has a
clear discussion of this point.15 He notes that the relation must be capable of
obtaining between the perceiver’s perceptions and objects which are both
nearby and far away; it must be a relation capable of obstruction by solid,
opaque objects; it must connect the perceiver not only with the objects
themselves, but also with their perceptible properties such as colour and shape,
as well as with the perceptible properties of those properties; it must connect
the perceiver not only with the front surface of a whole object, but with the
object as a whole (for one sees the table and not just its surface); and finally,
he asserts that it connects the perceiver with the absences of things, for
apparently one can say that one sees the absence, and not merely that one
fails to see.
It is hardly surprising that the Naiyayikas find themselves unable to describe
a single physical relation which obtains in all (and only) these circumstances,
but perhaps they do not need to. For if it is part of the concept of perception
only that it is grounded in a physical relation with a certain extension, then
an adequate physicalist theory of perception needs only to specify what the
extension of the underlying physical relation is. The discovery of the way that
relation is realised in actual human perception might be a task assigned to the
psychologist of perception, not to the philosopher.
The real interest in the Nyayasutra attempt to give a physical description
of perception lies in the remaining two conditions. The point is that, no matter
how well one succeeds in describing the underlying physical connection, there
The motive and method of rational inquiry
19
will be cases where that connection obtains, but the resulting awareness is not
genuinely perceptual. Vatsyayana points to cases of perceptual illusion and
perceptual confusion:
During the summer the flickering rays of the sun intermingled with the
heat radiating from the surface of the earth come in contact with the eyes
of a person at a distance. Due to this sense-object contact, there arises an
awareness as of water. Such an awareness might be (mis-)taken as
perceptual; hence the clause ‘non-errant’. An errant one is of that wherein
it is not. A non-errant one is of that wherein it is – this is a perception.
Perceiving with the eyes an object at a distance, a person cannot decide
whether it is smoke or dust. Such an indecisive awareness resulting from
sense–object contact might be (mis-)taken as perceptual; hence the clause
‘determinate in nature.’
These ambiguous passages led to a ‘vortex of controversy’ (Matilal 1995:
310) and eventually to a sophisticated theory of content. It is alleged that a
person witnessing a mirage does not see the refracted sun’s rays, even if in the
right sort of physical connection with them. Neither does he see water, for
there is none to be seen. Someone witnessing a mirage does not see anything,
but only seems to see water. And a person who witnesses a ball of dust in the
distance does not see the dust if he is uncertain whether it is dust or smoke. An
object is not seen if it is not seen distinctly.
In both cases there is a natural temptation to say that the person does see
something, but does not understand or know what it is that they see, or that
they misconstrue what it is that they see, or that their perceptual appearance
is non-veridical. One sees the refracted rays of light, but mistakes them to be
water; one sees the ball of dust, but fails to determinate it as such. To say this
would be to concede that the existence of an appropriate physical connection
is sufficient for object perception. The difficulty with such a move is that,
although it does indeed extrude rationality from the perceptual, it does it so
completely that the perceptual cannot be a basis for rational thought. The
‘objects’ of perception are merely things in which one stands in a certain
special physical relation, on a par with other objects one comes into physical
contact with (e.g. by standing on or picking up). However, if perception is to
be a foundation for rationality, there must be a way in which it is understood
as making objects available in thought, as placing them within the ken of the
observer.
Might we analyse the two additional clauses in terms of belief? If a person
witnessing a mirage does not see the refracted rays of the sun, perhaps it is
because he falsely believes them to be water. Similarly, one can perhaps say
that the person looking at the ball of dust does not see it because he does not
believe that it is dust (does not know whether it is dust or not). We might then
think of taking the additional clauses as defining the perception of an object
in terms of a physical connection, together with the absence of a belief that it
20
Philosophy in classical India
is something it is not, and the absence of doubt or disbelief that it is something
that it is. That is:
S’s perception is of object x iff:
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
S’s perception stands in a relation R with x.
R is physical (non-verbal).
for all F, if S believes that Fx then Fx.
for all F, if Fx then S does not disbelieve that Fx.
There are two objections to such a proposal. First, clauses (3) and (4) are
much too strong. It is clearly possible to perceive an object and at the same
time have false beliefs about it. I might, for example, perceive the table and
yet believe that it is made of space-filling infinitely divisible stuff. Second,
since belief implies rationality, the definition of perception in terms of belief
is contrary to the attempt to extrude reason from perception.
The proper implication of the Nyayasutra definition is that the perception
of objects is modulo a property. When I see an object (my desk, for instance)
I do not simply see it, but I see it as a table. Here, the clause ‘as a table’ is to
be read as an adverbial modifier of the seeing relation R. I stand in a ‘tableseeing’ relation to the object. The relativisation of the seeing relation by a
property allows a reconstruction of Vatsyayana’s cases. The person who
witnesses a mirage stands in a ‘water-seeing’ relation to the refracted rays.
The errancy lies in the fact that they are seeing the refracted rays as water,
when in fact the rays are not. And the person who witnesses a ball of dust, but
fails to distinguish it as dust or smoke stands neither in a dust-seeing relation
to the dust-ball, nor in a smoke-seeing relation, but equivocates. The correct
way to read the definition then is:
S’s perception is of object x iff:
(4)
for some F, S sees x as an F, where
S sees x as an F iff:
(1)
(2)
(3)
S’s perception stands in a relation R with x.
R is physical (non-verbal).
Fx.
Clause (4) excludes the case of the ball of dust, for since there is no definite
way by which the person sees the dust, the person does not see any object. It
is necessary for object perception that the object is seen in some definite way.
Clause (3) excludes the case of the mirage, for the person attempts to see the
rays modulo water but the rays are not water. Notice here that ‘non-errancy’
signifies simply an absence of warping, a lack of discord between the perception
The motive and method of rational inquiry
21
and its object, and is not explicated in terms of a correspondence between the
object and a perceptual content. We should think of this absence of warping
as a property of the perceptual relation, much as transparency is a property of
clear glass. Both are characterised in terms of the lack of a distortion or
corruption of what is seen, and not in terms of representational correspondence.
The passivity of perception is preserved; perception remains free from
interpretation and construction.
It follows from the definition that if one perceives an object, and one does
so by seeing it modulo its having a certain property, then it does indeed have
that property. This is so even though one does not see that the object has the
property. Perceiving x as F does not imply believing that x is F, but it does
imply that one would be justified were one to believe that x is F. Perception is
an evidential support for reason, without itself being reasoned (an idea echoed
in Roderick Chisholm’s critical cognitivism16). Later Nyaya writers draw a
distinction between perception that is ‘with imagination’ and perception that
is ‘without imagination’. Bimal Matilal explains the philosophical use here
of the term ‘imagination’ or vikalpa as standing ‘for anything that, let us say,
the mind adds to, or recognises in, the “given”.’17 In the Nyaya theory the
object perceived (x) and also the mode under which it is perceived (F) constitute
the perceptual given. It is the work of the ‘imagination’ to bring them together
into a propositional judgment (x is F).
Buddhist objections to the Nyaya definition focus on instances where
perception does seem to imply belief and inference. There is the case of
Uddyotakara’s rather remarkable claim that we perceive absences. I am looking
for a pot. I look in the kitchen and see no pot. Uddyotakara says: I see the
kitchen as qualified by absence-of-pot and thereby see the absence. The Buddhist
Dharmakirti objects that this is really a piece of reasoning, an inference from
non-observation. The inference runs thus. None of the objects which I perceive
in the kitchen is a pot. If there were a pot in the kitchen, I would see it, for my
perceptual faculties are working normally and all other ceteris paribus
conditions for perception are met. Therefore, there is no pot in the kitchen
(see Chapter 4.9). Dharmakirti’s point is well taken, but it does not constitute
a refutation of the theory. We may simply give up the strange claim that
absences can be perceived.
Nyayasutra 2.1.31 rehearses an argument, apparently again due to
Buddhists, which if sound would constitute a refutation. The argument is that
our ordinary perceptual claims are disguised inferences. I cannot see the whole
table from any one place. When I say that I see the table, what I mean is that
I infer that there is a whole table on the basis that I have seen a part (its front
surface). We never see wholes, but infer their existence from our more
immediate perceptions. If the argument is that all perception is inferential,
then Gautama’s counter in Nyayasutra 2.1.32, that we see at least front
surfaces, is conclusive. If the argument is that all perception of wholes is
inferential, the Nyaya reply is that the whole is present in each of its parts. So
we can perceive a whole just as we can perceive a property. One says that one
22
Philosophy in classical India
sees the colour or shape of the flower in virtue of seeing the flower; so too one
sees the whole in virtue of seeing a part.
What is at stake is the amount of work done in perception by reason. The
Buddhist presses the Naiyayika on the point that there is, in perception, an
extrapolation and interpretation of what is immediately given. Allowing
properties to enter the (non-conceptual) content of perceptual experience as
adverbial modifiers offers a way of avoiding the unpalatable consequence
that the perception of a whole is an inference. Attention is drawn to two
kinds of properties of wholes: those that are properties of the whole without
being a property of any its parts, and those that are properties of the whole
only because they are properties of every part (see Chapter 3.6). The second
sort ‘saturate’ the object, in rather the same way that sesame oil saturates
the sesame seed. The property being-a-table or being-a-cow, on the other
hand, applies to the whole, but not to any of its parts. It follows that seeing
modulo such a property is seeing the whole and not its parts. This Nyaya
rejoinder to the Buddhist criticism depends on one’s being able to regard the
property being-a-cow as an entirely objective feature of the perceived situation,
not as itself a mere concept or mental construct. It is for this reason that, in
the war for hegemony between the Buddhist and Nyaya philosophical views,
some of the severest battles were those over the reality of universals and
wholes.18
1.5 MIND, ATTENTION AND THE SOUL
Is the mind rational? Is it conscious? That depends on what we mean by
‘mind’. The Naiyayika, as generally for thinkers in classical India, sees in the
mind (manas) something distinct from the soul (atman). It is the soul alone
which is the seat of reason, qua thinker, perceiver, enjoyer of pleasures and
sufferer of pains. The mind is a mere instrument of the soul. It is that by which
the soul controls the senses. The mind is given a second function: it is also
that by which the soul perceives its own mental states. So the mind is both an
inner sense and the controller of the outer senses, but all the while entirely
directed by the soul. The mind is mechanical.
An enduring metaphor for the senses, due at least to Prasastapada, is as
windows onto the world. In a room with a window on every wall, each one
represents a possibility of sensory contact with some aspect of the world. But
only a possibility: in order to see out, one has to direct one’s attention to one
window rather than another. In the case of the senses, this role is assigned to
the mind. It is a faculty of attention, that by which the soul directs its gaze
through one sense rather than another. Another metaphor is helpful here.
Think of the senses as converging railway tracks, meeting at a point and
becoming a single track. The mind is the set of points at the junction. It is that
by which the controller (the soul, the signalman) channels its attention in one
direction rather than another.
The motive and method of rational inquiry
23
A perception arises in the soul when there is a causal chain: from object to
sense, from sense to mind and from mind to soul.19 Uddyotakara observes that
if this role of the mind in perception seems to have been forgotten in the
Nyayasutra definition of perception, it is because a mind–soul link is not
something special to perception, while a mind–sense link is implied by the
mention of the sense–object connection.20
The existence of the mind as an inter-sensory switching device follows
from an alleged deficiency in the powers of the conscious soul. This is that the
soul can attend to at most one thing at a time. There is a strict sequence in the
temporal order of thought. If the senses are functioning simultaneously, but
one can entertain no more than one thought at a time, then one must have
within oneself a capacity to choose between the deliverances of the senses (NS
1.1.16, NS 3.2.56). In reply to the obvious objection that we do seem to be
able to attend to more than one thing at once, Vatsyayana claims that this is
an error produced by our inability to discriminate events which happen in
very quick succession. He cites (NS 3.2.58) the illusion of a circling firebrand,
appearing as if it were a continuous hoop, and more interestingly, the way
one hears a sentence as a whole even though the letters and words are uttered
in sequence.
This account of the mind is smooth. But a worry now presents itself. If the
conscious soul fails to notice the distinctness in a sequence of perceptions, it
seems to follow that the mind after all has a certain autonomy in operation.
For if the soul is not quick enough to follow the mind’s switchings from one
perception to the next, how can it be controlling them?21 And yet there is no
question of assigning consciousness (caitanya) to the mind. Nyayasutra 3.2.38
is explicit:
It [consciousness] is not a property of the mind, for reasons already given,
and because of its being ruled by another, and because [there would then
follow an] acquiring of the benefits of actions not performed.
The ‘reason already given’ is simply the definition itself of the soul, as the
exclusive abode of thought, will, pleasure and pain (NS 1.1.10). The idea of
‘benefits of actions not performed’ is a reference to the karma theory of moral
retribution. If the soul and the mind were distinct consciousnesses, then the
future contentments or frustrations of the soul would depend on the present
deeds of another, the mind. This contradicts the fundamental principle of the
karma theory, that the benefits and costs of one’s present actions accrue to
oneself and not to someone else. Vatsyayana uses the same line of reasoning
against the Buddhist reduction of a person to a ‘sum and series’ of
consciousness-moments (NS 3.2.39). If a person is a series of distinct
consciousnesses, then the deeds of one reach their fruition in the contentments
and frustrations of another, an injustice incompatible with the hypothesis of
karma.
24
Philosophy in classical India
The more important assertion is that the mind is ‘ruled by another’. It does
not act independently, but only as directed by the conscious soul. It therefore
cannot itself choose which sense to connect with. How then can the soul be
unaware of its operation? A solution to the puzzle begins to emerge when we
remember that the mind has another function, along with that of intersensory
switch. It is also an inner sense, the means by which the soul perceives its own
mental states. Vatsyayana:22
Memory, inference, testimony, doubt, intuition, dreams, suppositional
argument, and perception of pleasure and pain are the proof of mind.
One conclusion we can draw from this is that the soul is not immediately
aware of its own thoughts, for it requires an inner sense to perceive them.
Thoughts, just like external events, can appear and disappear unperceived.
So the mere fact that a thought occurs does not imply that it is taken notice of
in consciousness. Once the point has been made that the mere occurrence of a
thought is not sufficient for its being noticed, we see that the switching function
of the mind need not determine which thoughts are noticed, but need only
ensure that thoughts occur in succession. We can think of the mind as scanning
the senses, constantly switching from one to the next. Its movement so conceived
will be very swift, but entirely automatic and mechanical. Perceptions from
all the senses occur rapidly, but sequentially in the soul.
To attend to something then, is not to direct the mind qua intersensory
switch towards one rather than another sense faculty, but rather to direct it
qua inner sense to some occurrent perception. The rapid movement of the
mind need not be something of which the soul is aware. There is still a
problem. If a perception comes before consciousness only if one chooses to
direct the mind towards it, how can it be that one’s attention is sometimes
drawn by the perception itself? Standing on a thorn or a chip of stone will
draw the attention even of a person whose mind is fastened on some other
thing (NBh. under NS 3.2.32). The worry is that I will not notice the pain in
my foot unless I direct my mind to attend to the deliverances of my tactile
sense, but that there need be no motivation for me to do this in advance of
noticing the pain. Unless it occurs to me to check whether my foot has been
injured, I will not notice the pain! Even this, however, can be squared with a
mechanistic conception of the mind. Let us say simply that some perceptions
are so intense as to force the mind in their direction, not because it chooses to
direct itself towards them, but simply because it is driven to do so by the
intensity of the perception. A conception of the mind as entirely mechanical
in operation has room to allow that this could happen. The ‘movement’ of the
mind is an automated scanning of the senses, potentially diverted by the
occurrence of intense perceptions and by the controlling influence of the soul.
The mind is not itself a rational agent, and it is only in a relatively weak
sense that the Indian soul–mind division is what one would now call a
‘divided mind’ hypothesis.23
The motive and method of rational inquiry
25
What now is the place of reason in perception? The function of the soul is
to integrate the content of distinct perceptions across times and between sensory
modalities (NB 3.1.1). It has the power to identify the object of some past
perception and an object currently being perceived. The identity ‘this is the
same as that’ is not given in perception, but discovered or ‘imagined’ by the
soul. The same is true across sensory modalities at a given time. Physical
objects are perceived only by sight and touch, but the identification of an
object held in one’s hand with an object currently being seen with one’s eyes
is the work of reason and not of perception. Such identifications require one
to be able to assume a point of view which spans times and crosses sensory
modalities. Rationality then has a reconstitutive role in aligning our perceptions
with each other, so that they come to represent a world of temporally extended
and modality-independent objects.24
The possibility of trans-temporal and trans-modal identification of objects
is said by the Nyaya to be the best argument for the existence of the soul as
distinct from the mind or the senses, and as the final refutation of the Buddhist
analysis of the person as a mere continuum of discrete consciousnesses. For
how is a re-identification of an object possible by one who exists only for a
moment? Only a single consciousness spanning time can ‘simultaneously’
witness the same object at two different times, and recognise it as the same.
Only a single consciousness spanning sense modalities can ‘simultaneously’
witness a single object through two modalities, and recognise it as the same.
The Buddhist asserts that a momentary consciousness can compare a current
perception with a current memory (produced by the past perception of an
earlier momentary consciousness), and so there is no need for there to be a
single subject of the current and past perceptions. The Naiyayika reply is that
there is a logical difference between, on the one hand, judging that an object
seen now is the same as an object seen some time ago, and, on the other,
keeping track of an object over a period of time. It is perhaps like the difference
between discovering that two different names refer to the same thing, and
using a single name twice.25
The ability to turn fleeting modality-specific perceptions into thoughts about
enduring physical objects is a concealed art of the soul. It is rational because
it admits of a standard of correctness. Inter-perceptual identifications can be
right or wrong – the degree to which one can make them accurately, and the
extent which one can do so for perceptions more distant from one another in
time or appearance, is the index of a rational capacity.
1.6 RATIONALITY AND EXTRAPOLATION
The discovery of identities among the contents of one’s perceptions is a core
function of reason. There is another. This is the capacity to extrapolate from
what one has perceived to what one has not. That extrapolation is a key
concept in the early history of Indian logic is clear from some of the examples
26
Philosophy in classical India
Vatsyayana gives under NS 1.1.5.26 Seeing a rising cloud, one infers that it
will rain. An interesting variant is: seeing the ants carrying their eggs, one
infers that it will rain. Seeing a full and swiftly flowing river, one infers that
it has been raining. Seeing a cloud of smoke, one infers the existence of an
unseen fire. Hearing a cry, one infers that a peacock is nearby. Seeing the
moon at one place at one time and at another place at another time, one
infers that it is moving (even though one cannot see it move). The medical
theorist Caraka27 has some other examples: inferring impregnation from
pregnancy; inferring the future appearance of fruit from the presence of seeds.
In the ancient Buddhist logical text, The Essence of Method,28 we also find:
inferring from a child’s special mark that this person is that child, now grown
up; inferring from the salty taste of one drop of sea water that the whole sea
is salty. The Ts ‘ing-mu29 (a commentary on Nagarjuna’s Middle Stanzas, for
which see Chapter 2) has a similar example: inferring that all the rice is
cooked on tasting one grain. And the Vaisesikasutra mentions another sort of
extrapolation – the inference of an entire cow from the perception only of its
horns.30
Extrapolation from the seen to the unseen can take place in any of the three
dimensions of time – past, present and future. Our interest is in the Indian
theory of rationality, and for this we want to look at answers given to the
question: on what basis, if any, ought the extrapolation be made? For while
dice-throwing, guesswork and divination are ways of extrapolating, they are
not rational ones. Extrapolation, like critical investigation, must be done ‘on
the basis of reasons’, and a theory of such ‘reasons’ is a theory of that in
virtue of which an extrapolation is warranted. So we can discover Indian
theories of rationality in their explanations of why the extrapolations in the
examples mentioned above are warranted. Rationality now is the search for
extrapolative licence.
While Vatsyayana says only that there should be a connection between
what is seen and what is inferred,31 many of the early writers have a definite
interest in prediction and scientific explanation, and assume that extrapolation
is warranted when underwritten by a causal relation. On the other hand, it is
clearly recognised too that not all warranted extrapolation is causal. The
Vaisesikasutra lists, in addition, the relations of contact, inherence, coinherence
in a third, and being contrary (VS 3.1.8, 9.18), while the early Samkhya
sastitantra has an overlapping list of seven.32 Take the inference from a drop
of salty sea water to the conclusion that the whole sea is salty. This is not an
inference based on any causal relation between the drop of sea water and the
sea as a whole; rather, the relation between them is mereological. One would
say that it is an inference from sampling a ‘typical’ member of a group. This
is a very common and useful form of reasoning (witness the example of
checking that all the rice is cooked by tasting a single grain). It is not formally
valid, but it is a pervasive and powerful species of informal reasoning. We
will see in the next section that it acquires particular significance in the context
of a debate.
The motive and method of rational inquiry
27
There is also an intriguing example from Vatsyayana I have not yet
mentioned. This is the inference of the ‘residual’ by elimination.33 Wondering
whether sound is a substance, a quality, or an event, and finding reasons to
deny that it is a substance or an event, one draws the conclusion that it is a
quality. What is interesting is that the early writers are well aware that not all
warranted inference can be reduced to the causal model. An adequate theory
of inference has to find a description of the extrapolation-warranting relation
at a level more general than that of the causal.
The difficulty in finding adequately general bases for extrapolative inference
encouraged a scepticism about their existence. In one form, scepticism about
the possibility of rational extrapolation is just the claim that there is no adequate
extrapolative basis. It is the view allegedly of the Lokayata ‘materialist,’ and
most notably of the sceptic Jayarasi (c. AD 600). An early version of the
sceptic’s argument is recorded in the Nyayasutra (NS 2.1.37):
[Objection:] Inference is not a means of knowing, because there may be
errancy arising from embankment, damage and similarity.
Gautama is referring to the examples of the swollen river, the ants and the
peacock. His point is that the observed facts admit of different explanations:
the swollen river might have been caused by a dam or embankment further
downstream, the ants might be carrying their eggs because their nest has been
damaged, and the peacock’s cry might have been made by a human or animal
impersonator. There are alternative causal explanations for each perceived
event. This is a standard sceptical move. The sceptic introduces an alternative
possible explanation (that our experiences are all dreams or produced by an
evil genius, that the world was created five minutes ago with all its fossil
records) and then claims that the existence of such an alternative explanation
shows that one is not entitled to assume that the common-sense expanation is
the correct one. Gautama’s reply is interesting (NS 2.1.38):
No. Because it is a different thing from a [mere] partial case, fear, and
[mere] similarity.
The compact response is that there is an observable difference between a river
which is swollen because of upstream rain and one which is swollen because
of a downstream blockage, a difference between the orderly procession of
ants when it is about to rain and their fearful scurrying when the nest is
disturbed, and a difference between a genuine peacock’s cry and that of an
impersonator.
The implication of Gautama’s reply for the rationality of extrapolation
seems to be this. An extrapolation from the seen thing to the unseen thing is
rational when there is a relation of some appropriate (as yet unspecified) sort
between the two. The relation does not obtain between the unseen thing and
something which merely resembles the seen thing. The rational extrapolator,
28
Philosophy in classical India
therefore, must have the capacity to discriminate between the thing in question
and other things which merely resemble it, but do not stand in the appropriate
relation to the unseen thing. Only someone who can tell the difference between
a flood river and a dammed river is entitled to infer from swelling to rain;
only someone who can tell the difference between marching ants and frightened
ants is entitled to infer from marching to rain; and only someone who can tell
the difference between a peacock’s cry and a human impersonator is entitled
to draw the inference from cry to peacock.
The sceptic will reply, of course, that he can always find an alternative
explanation for the occurrence of a perceived event, no matter how finely
attuned the perceiver’s discriminating powers. Even the best expert can be
fooled by a good enough forgery. But the question is whether it is rational to
concern oneself with such extreme sceptical possibilities. The Naiyayika
proposes a common-sense maxim for extrapolative reasoning: do not
extrapolate beyond the level of your competence. The sceptic has a different
maxim: do not extrapolate if there is any possibility of error. Since human
beings have finite discriminatory capacities, there is always the possibility of
error, and so the sceptic’s maxim implies that it is never rational to extrapolate.
(Jayarasi34 claims even that there is no rational extrapolation from the rising
to the setting of the sun!) To reach the sceptical conclusion, however, the
sceptic has further to prove that his maxim of extrapolation is the rational
one to adopt, while the common-sense Nyaya maxim is not. And that is
precisely what Gautama is here denying.
1.7 RATIONALITY AND DEBATE
H. N. Randle observed a long time ago that ‘the Naiyayika was from first
to last a tarkika, a disputant.’35 More recently, B. K. Matilal has called
debate the ‘preferred form of rationality’ in classical India.36 There is a
good deal of truth in these observations. A sophisticated theory of rationality
evolved in the arenas of debate. Kautilya observed that rationality is about
the best means to an end, and the end of the debater is to win. But what
counts as winning a debate? If the debate is the victory-at-any-cost sort, and
a debater wins when his opponent is lost for words or confused or hesitant,
then the best and so most rational way to proceed would be to employ such
tricks as play on the opponent’s weaknesses: speaking very quickly or using
convoluted examples or referring to doctrines of which one suspects one’s
opponent is ignorant. In the other sort of debate, the truth-directed sort,
‘winning’ is a matter of persuading one’s opponent, and also an impartial
audience, that one’s thesis is true, and the rational debater must find some
other methods. Nothing is more persuasive than an argument backed up by
well-chosen examples and illustrations. And so, when the Naiyayikas came
to codify the form of rational debating demonstration, the citation of examples
was given at least as much prominence as the citation of reasons. When the
Nyaya theory of inference was ‘rediscovered’ by Henry Colebrooke (he
The motive and method of rational inquiry
29
broke the news at a meeting of the Royal Asiatic Society in London in
1824), the Indologists of the day in their excitement failed to pay due attention
to this fact, and were led to some rather extraordinary speculations about
the origins of syllogistic theory. The Sanskritist Görres apparently arrived
at the view that Alexander, having been in conversation with the logicians
of India during his campaigns, sent some of their treatises back home to his
tutor who worked them up into a system! Equally remarkable was Niebuhr’s
claim that the Indians must have derived their theory from the Indianised
Greeks of Bactria (it is a view Vidhyabhusana was to repeat much later on).
If there is a lesson here, it is that a little comparative philosophy is a
dangerous thing.
The debating room is a theatre for the art of persuasion. It is a metaphor
for any situation in which one wants to persuade others of the correctness of
one’s point of view. It will include by extension both the mundane situation of
persuading one’s companion that something is about to happen, and
persuading a scientific or academic community of the truth of one’s thesis.
The model of rationality which comes out of the theory of debate is public,
explicit, demonstrational. The norms of public reason are those of mutual
agreement.
The proper way to formulate one’s position is in accordance with a ‘fivelimbed’ schema: tentative statement of the thesis to be proved; citation of a
reason; mention of an example; application of reason and example to the
case in hand; final assertion of the thesis (NS 1.1.32). Suppose I want to
persuade my walking companion that it is about to rain. I might reason as
follows: ‘Look, it is going to rain. For see that large black cloud. Last time
you saw a large black cloud like that one, what happened? Well, it’s the same
now. It is definitely going to rain.’ In order to be able to generalise the structure
of such patterns of reasoning, the Naiyayikas make an important simplifying
assumption. They assume that the underlying pattern is one of propertysubstitution. The claim is that all such patterns exemplify the same canonical
form: Ta because Ra. An object (the paksa or ‘site’ of the inference) is inferred
to have a property (the sadhya or ‘target’) on the grounds that it has some
other property (the hetu or reason). The first simplification, then, is to think of
reasoning as taking us from an object’s having one property to that same
object’s having another.
The simplification scarcely seems justified. A cursory inspection of the
cases mentioned at the beginning of the last section shows that only about
half fit such a pattern. The cases of the swollen river, the ants, the peacock’s
cry, the fruit and the salty sea do not seem to fit at all. Neither can we fit
reasoning to the remainder by elimination. The canonical schema seems to fit
the case of the moon, the pregnancy and the child’s special mark, but it is
only at a stretch that one can force the case of smoke and fire into the pattern
(an irony as this is a hackneyed example which all the logical texts quote).
Bearing in mind the ways in which Indian logic was later to develop, one can
be forgiven for feeling that this adoption of a property-substitution model at
30
Philosophy in classical India
an early stage, while perhaps a helpful and necessary simplification for the
sake of initial progress, also restricted the study of other patterns of inferential
reasoning. Only the Jaina logicians explicitly tried to develop a theory of
extrapolation free from this restriction (see Chapter 5.7).
What licenses the inference from Ra to Ta? The Nyayasutra answer is
given in five brief and controversial aphorisms (NS 1.1.34–38):
A reason is that which proves what is to be proved by being like an
example.
Again, by being unalike.
An example is an observed instance which, being like what is to be proved,
possesses its property.
Or else, being opposite, is opposite.
The application is an assimilation to what is to be proved ‘this is thus’ or
‘this is not thus’ depending on the example.
Likeness and unlikeness are relative to properties. Something is ‘like’ another
thing if both possess a given property. They are unalike with respect to that
property if they do not both share it. Now arguably the natural way to interpret
these sutras is as follows. Either the locus of the inference is like the example
(in that both possess the reason property, R) and, since the example has the tobe-proved property, so does the locus. Or else the locus of the inference is
unlike the example (it possesses the reason property, but the example does
not), and since the example does not have the to-be-proved property, the locus
does have it. If we let ‘b’ stand for the example, then we seem to have:
α is likeR b
Tb
∴ Ta
α is unlikeR b
~ Tb
∴ Ta
This formulation actually makes the inference a generalisation of the inference
from sampling. The example is a typical member of the class of things having
the reason property. And it has this other property, the to-be-inferred target
property. But the site of the inference is also a member of the class of things
having the reason property. So it too has the target property (the negative
formulation is similar). This is a powerful form of reasoning, one which we
engage in all the time. It is not formally valid, but it is a pervasive type of
informal reasoning. We employ it whenever we infer that an object has a
property on the grounds that it belongs to a type, the typical members of
which have that property. Compare: this grain of rice is typical of the whole
pan of rice, and it is cooked. So any other grain will be cooked as well. This
drop of water is typical of the entire sea, and it is salty. So this other drop
must be salty as well.
The motive and method of rational inquiry
31
We said that in the debating model, rationality is subject to public norms
of correctness. In arguments of the kind being considered, public norms do
indeed have a role to play, for they determine whether the object adduced by
the debater as an ‘example’ is adequate. For something to be capable of
playing the role of example, it must be generally and uncontroversially accepted
as a member of R and as a T. The debater must, when he chooses an example,
be careful to select one that will fit public criteria of acceptability. Warranted
extrapolation, clearly, is context dependent and occurs, in particular, only
when there is a background of shared knowledge. For one grain of rice is an
adequate exemplar of all only if it is commonly known that all the rice has
been cooked in the same pan, at the same temperature, and with the same
amount of water. It is for this reason that the pattern of reasoning here is
neither formally valid nor reducible to an Aristotelian syllogism.37
There is a strong pressure, nevertheless, to fit such arguments into a
deductive-nomological model. These arguments, the thought goes, rest on an
underlying lawlike universal generalisation – that all the members of kind R
are Ts. The argument is then enthymematic for a deductively valid one: Ra,
all R are T ∴ Ta. The role of the example, it is alleged, would be to provide
empirical support for the universal rule, either by being something which is
both R and T, or by being something which is neither R nor T. The pioneer
indologist, Stanislaw Schayer, had a different idea.38 He read the step labelled
‘example’ in the five-step proof as an application of a logical rule, the one we
would now call ‘universal instantiation’. This is the rule that permits one to
infer from ‘(! x)(Rx ´ Tx)’ to ‘(Ra ´ Ta)’. And he read the step called
‘application’ as the application of another logical rule, modus ponens. But he
still sees the overall inference as a formally valid one whose validity is a
consequence of the fact that there is a hidden premise ‘(!x)(Rx ´ Tx)’.
More light can be thrown on this point if we examine the early Nyaya
account of a pair of debating moves called the ‘likeness-based’ rejoinder and
‘unlikeness-based’ rejoinder. A sophistical rejoinder (jati) is a debating tactic
in which the opponent tries unsuccessfully to produce a counter-argument, an
argument designed to prove the opposite thesis. It is sophistical because the
counter-argument is based on a false or superficial resemblance. Nyayasutra
5.1.2–3 state:
When there is assimilation through likeness or unlikeness, the likenessbased and unlikeness-based rejoinders lead to the opposite property.
[The reply is:] the proof [of the thesis] is just like the proof of a cow from
cowhood.
One debater, debating properly, tries to prove that a certain object has a
certain property by pointing out that it is like another object which does have
that property. (The black cloud overhead now is like the cloud we saw
yesterday – both are black. But that cloud caused it to rain, so this one will
32
Philosophy in classical India
too.) The opponent now tries to counter by pointing out that the object is also
like an object which does not have the property. (The black cloud overhead is
like the white cloud we saw the day before yesterday – both are clouds. But
that cloud did not cause rain, so this one won’t either.)
a is likeR1 b
Tb
∴ Ta
a is likeR2 c
~ Tc
∴~ Ta
As an argument, the rejoinder seems to follow the very same pattern as the
original one, so why is it false? The existence of such rejoinders shows that
mere likeness is not sufficient for good argument. The likeness has to be of the
right type. When is the likeness of the right type? The Nyayasutra’s very
cryptic comment is that the ‘right type’ is the type displayed by the relationship
between a cow and its genus cowhood. Vatsyayana, the commentator, is unclear
and confused on this point. He does, however, make one important
observation:39
If one proceeds to establish the required inferable property on the basis
simply of likeness or unlikeness then there will be lack of regularity
(vyavastha). Irregularity does not arise with respect to some special
property. For something is a cow because of its likeness with another
cow, which likeness is actually cowhood, not the cow’s having dewlap,
etc. It is because of cowhood that a cow is unlike a horse, etc., not because
of a difference of particular qualities. This has been explained in the
section on the limbs of a demonstration. In a demonstration, each limb
serves a single purpose because they are connected with the means of
knowing. The irregularity rests only on a bogus reason.
If the likeness must be of the right type, then the reason property, as determiner
of the likeness relation, must also be of the right type. The object under
investigation must be like objects which belong to a group, the typical members
of which have the target property. Vatsyayana implies that if the property in
question is a property shared by typical members of the class of cows, then
the reason property must be the class-essence cowhood.
In the last section, we saw that rational inference is linked with warranted
extrapolation, and we wondered what it was that made an extrapolation
warranted. The problem we have here is similar. We are now asking for the
conditions under which it is admissible to extrapolate a property from one
object to another. It appears to be admissible to extrapolate the property
‘rainmaker’ from one black cloud to another black cloud, but not from a
black cloud to a white cloud. It appears to be admissible to extrapolate the
property ‘has a dewlap’ from one cow to another cow, but not from one fourlegged animal (a cow) to another (a horse). There seems to be an order in the
world of objects, a structure which licenses the extrapolation of properties in
The motive and method of rational inquiry
33
some directions, but not others. Objects are grouped together on the basis of
their likenesses and unlikenesses to one another. The possibility of likenessbased and unlikeness-based rejoinders shows, however, there are many different
ways of making these groupings, many different metrics of likeness. So the
problem is this – given some arbitrary property we wish to extrapolate from
one object to another, how do we decide which such metric determines a
standard for proper and warranted extrapolation? For an extrapolation may
be warranted under one likeness relation, but not another. So not every inference
of the standard pattern is permissible:
a is likeR b
Tb
∴ Ta
The response given in the tradition to this problem is to impose further
constraints on the relation of likeness. Relevant or extrapolation-warranting
likeness consists in the sharing of a property at least as narrow in extension as
the property to be extrapolated. The idea is clearly expressed and ably defended
by Dinnaga (Chapter 4.7), and for that reason he is rightly thought of as one
of India’s finest logicians. I also think that the pre-Dinnaga Naiyayikas would
not have developed the theory of inference in the way they did unless they had
some such idea in their minds. But I do not believe we should be led by this to
try to reinterpret what they said as an unequivocal expression of the idea.
Matilal puts the matter well when he says that ‘the conception of a universal
connection is being hinted at on the analogy of a universal property.’40 The
hint was there, but it was for Dinnaga to lend that hint articulation (and
perhaps it is only at moments when a theory is being revised that a precise
definition is needed). The important point is this need not be read as the
introduction of a new premise into the inference pattern, but rather as a
condition on when an inference is admissible. The constraint is of the form: it
is valid to infer Ta from Tb if a is likeR b when b, the example, is relevantly
like a (i.e. when the property it shares with a is narrower in extension than the
property being extrapolated). An inference rule is not another premise in the
inference, but rather that in virtue of which the inference is valid or invalid.
And the treatment of the early Nyaya theory as a theory of inference from
sampling shows how the rule that there be a ‘universal connection’ (vyapti) of
this kind between the properties is not an enthymematic premise, but a genuine
inference rule of an informal logic.
Five sorts of bogus reason (hetvabhasa) are mentioned in Nyayasutra 1.2.4:
the wandering, the contradictory, the unproven, the counter-balanced and the
untimely.41 Of special importance here is the one called the ‘wandering’ (for
the ‘unproven’ and the ‘counter-balanced’, see Chapter 1.9). This was
interpreted by later Naiyayikas as meaning that the reason property deviates
from the target, and so as a case in which the criterion enunciated in the
above paragraph is violated. If a faulty reason is one which is present somewhere
34
Philosophy in classical India
the target property is not, then by contraposition, a proper reason is one
which is not present somewhere the target property is not, and so is at least as
narrow in extension. The Nyayasutra definition is, however, less than explicit,
and Vatsyayana’s explication of this most important sutra is all over the
place:
The wandering is that which does not remain at only one end. (NS 1.2.5)
An example is: sound is eternal because it is intangible. A pot is tangible
and is seen to be non-eternal. Sound is not tangible in the same way.
What then? It is intangible. One might say, therefore, that because it is
intangible, sound is eternal. However, in this example, tangibility and
non-eternality are not grasped as standing in a prover–proven
relationship. For example, an atom is tangible and it is eternal. And
when something like the soul is the example, then the reason, which is
taken to be ‘because of being intangible’ in accordance with the sutra ‘a
reason is that which proves what is to be proved by being like an
example (1.1.34),’ deviates from eternality. For a thought is intangible
as well as non-eternal. So, as there is deviation in both sorts of case,
there is no prover–proven relationship as the mark of a (proper) reason is
absent. One end is eternality, one end non-eternality. So we understand
‘being at one end’. Opposite to that which is at one end is that which
does not remain at only one end, because it is a pervader (vyapaka) of
both ends.
Four inferences are compared. (1) A pot is non-eternal. Sound is unlike a pot
– one is tangible, the other intangible. So sound is eternal. However, we also
have this. (2) An atom is eternal. Sound is unlike an atom – one is tangible,
the other intangible. So sound is non-eternal. Again, we have: (3) The soul is
eternal. Sound is like the soul – both are intangible. So sound is eternal. But
also: (4) A thought is non-eternal. Sound is like a thought – both are intangible.
So sound is non-eternal. The implication is that what undermines the inference
is the existence of examples which do not fit, i.e. counter-examples. Another
maxim of extrapolation is in play: do not extrapolate if you know of any
counter-examples (there is no implication that the extrapolator is obliged to
look for counter-examples, however). A prover–proven relationship is one for
which no counter-examples exist. What Vatsyayana lacks, however, is a clear
grasp of what makes something a counter-example. He does not see that only
a thing which is intangible and non-eternal ought to be thought of as a counterexample to the inference from intangibility to eternality. Something which is
tangible and eternal (an atom) is not a counter-example. For the existence of
tangible eternal things is not inconsistent with the rule underpinning the
inference, that whatever is intangible is eternal. It is the gaining of a clearer
grasp of the notion of a counter-example that leads one to an understanding of
the proper form of the prover–proven relationship. Again, Dinnaga is extremely
The motive and method of rational inquiry
35
precise on the nature of counter-examples (Chapter 4.7), and can take a lot of
the credit, even if the essential point had been appreciated before him.
My point has been that there are many ways to arrive rationally at
belief, other than that of formal deduction. Informal argument schemes,
such as the inference from sampling, are just as much ways of reaching
beliefs that it is rational for someone to hold, and it is with this wider
concept of rational belief that we make better sense of the early Nyaya
philosophical enterprise.
1.8 REASON, SCRIPTURE AND TESTIMONY
Is it rational to believe the testimony of others or the statements of the
scriptures? Does the assumption that it is rational to believe what we hear or
read require us to think of rationality in a new way? We have so far encountered
two epistemic models of rationality: the perceptual model, according to which
rationality provides norms for the temporal and cross-modal integration of
perceptual experiences; and the extrapolative model, according to which
rationality provides norms for the extrapolation from the perceived to the
unperceived. The Naiyayika thinks that belief in the testimony of others is
indeed rational, but that neither the perceptual nor the extrapolative model of
rationality can account for why this is so. Testimony is a sui generis source of
rational belief (i.e. a pramana).
The Nyaya theory of testimony is simple. Nyayasutra 1.1.7 states that
testimony is the utterance of a ‘credible person’ (apta). On this sutra,
Vatsyayana adds the following important comment:
A credible person is a speaker who has knowledge of the object and is
motivated by the desire to tell of the object as known. This definition of a
credible person is equally applicable to the seer (rsi), the noble (arya),
and the outsider (mleccha).42
The comment is important because it implies that the scriptures do not have
any special claim to our assent, but are to be believed for precisely the same
reasons as any other piece of testimony, namely because the transmitter is
credible. A credible person is one who is knowledgeable about the subject
matter, and who has a sincere desire to communicate that knowledge, and
can come from any walk of life or branch of society.43 Vatsyayana elaborates
the point while discussing the Nyayasutra argument (NS 2.1.68) that the
authority of the Veda is just like that of a medical treatise, in that it rests on
the credibility of the communicator. He comments:
To what is this authoritativeness due? It is due to the direct knowledge of
what is prescribed, compassion for fellow beings, and the desire to
communicate rightly. Credible communicators, having direct knowledge
of what they prescribe, show compassion for fellow beings, (advising)
36
Philosophy in classical India
‘this is to be avoided,’ ‘this is a cause of pain,’ or ‘this is to be attained’
and ‘this is the means to its attainment.’ For creatures who cannot
themselves understand, there is no other way of knowing all this . . . Thus
a credible communicator is a source of knowledge.44
When a person speaks who is knowledgeable, well motivated and caring, it is
rational to believe what they say. The scriptures, as it happens, are transmitted
to us by such persons, and so we are entitled to believe them and regard what
they say as a valuable source of knowledge, especially about moral and
soteriological matters we would not otherwise be informed of. It is rational to
believe the scriptures in just the same way and to just the same extent as it is
rational to believe a medical text about medical matters, or any other experts
about their respective field of competence.
A dilemma threatens this account of testimonial rationality. Must we know
that the speaker has the qualities of competence, sincerity and compassion in
order to be entitled to believe her, or not? It can hardly be right to say that we
are entitled to believe any utterance we hear, and just hope that its author is
competent and sincere. That would be an epistemic charter for the gullible.45
But if we have first to establish that the speaker is competent and sincere, then
it seems that our grounds for believing are inferential, and the rationality
implicated in testimony is nothing but a variety of extrapolative rationality.
We reason, in effect, that the present utterance is relevantly similar to past
utterances of the same speaker, which have been seen to be true. Someone
who accepts this (David Hume is a notable case) is led to conclude that it is
indeed rational to believe the utterances of a sincere and competent speaker,
but that no new model of rationality is involved.
What saves the Nyaya theory is the idea that one can ‘monitor’ the
competence and sincerity of the speaker without forming any beliefs about
her competence or sincerity. One might simply have an internal ‘lie-detector’
subconsciously monitoring for signs of blushing, fidgeting, and so on. The
existence of such a mechanism makes the following counterfactual conditional
true: if the speaker were lying, one would come to believe it. In the presence
of a sub-doxastic faculty of this sort, one need not attempt to acquire knowledge
about the speaker’s credentials. For one’s readiness to assent to what is being
said will be overridden if she were to lie. Assent is made rational in a negative
way, by the absence of evidence that the speaker is deceitful, rather than by
positive evidence that she is sincere. It is rational in the same way that it is
rational for one to believe that one has not just trodden on a nail. One need
have no positive reason for so believing (a visual inspection of the foot, for
example) for one knows that, if one had just trodden on a nail, one would
have come to know about it. The ‘reasoning’ is ab ignorantiam and not
inductive.46
While the worry about the reduction of testimony to inference is raised in
the Nyayasutra (NS 2.1.49–51), this defence is not to be found there. It emerges
The motive and method of rational inquiry
37
in the later idea that a precondition for testimony is the ‘absence of knowledge
of unfitness’ and not the ‘knowledge of fitness’, Vatsyayana says only that
testimony depends on the speaker’s credibility and that ‘inference is not like
this’.47
1.9 REASON’S CHECKS AND BALANCES
I began this examination of rationality in the early Nyaya with a description
of the disreputable ‘reasoners’ mentioned and criticised in the epics. The illrepute was on the grounds that their use of reason was unmotivated,
groundless, unconstrained. The Naiyayika is very careful to avoid this
charge. The very term nyaya, which Vatsyayana identified with reasoned
inquiry itself, is contrasted with another, nyayabhasa – a pseudo-inquiry. A
pseudo-inquiry is one which, although otherwise in accord with the rules
governing proper reasoning (setting out the demonstration in a five-limbed
format and with a proper reason property), contradicts observation and
authority (see Chapter 1.2). The same point is made time and again. A
properly conducted debate, one which is friendly and truth-directed, is one
which proceeds with the help of the methods of knowledge-acquisition,
employs the five-limbed format, and is not in contradiction with any
doctrinal base (NS 1.2.1). A reason property which proves a thesis
contradictory to a doctrinal base is a mere bogus reason (NS 1.2.6). Reason
in Nyaya has had its wings clipped. It can override neither observation nor
authoritative doctrine!
Descartes observed that our perceptions can sometimes contradict one
another, and that when they do it is the role of reason to adjudicate. A tower
might look round from a distance, but square closer up. A star and a distant
lamp both look like specks of light, but one is vastly larger than the other. It
is reason (belief and inference) that tells us that the star is larger than the
lamp, even though they both look the same size. It is reason that allows us to
decide whether the tower is really square or round. How, then, can one deny
that reason sometimes overrides perception? However, there are cases where
perception overrides reason. Vatsyayana tries to find a case where a reasoned
argument meets all the criteria as laid down in the theory of inference, but
whose conclusion has to be rejected because it goes against perception. His
example is: fire is not hot, because it is a creation, like a pot. Fires and pots
are alike in that they are both products of human effort (let us restrict the
extension of ‘fire’ to those produced by humans). A pot, however, is a thing
made of clay and so is not hot (material things are composed out of the four
material elements, earth, water, fire and air, and only those containing
elemental fire are hot). So fire too is not hot! The inference goes through even
if we insist on a universal connection between reason and target. For it is
indeed true that, among everything seen, created things are not hot. The point
is that the inference extrapolates from the seen to the unseen, and fire’s heat
therefore belongs here with the unseen. The thermal properties of fire, as the
38
Philosophy in classical India
matter under investigation, are, as it were, sub judice. Every created thing
ever encountered (excluding fire) has been found to be cold. So, extrapolating,
fire too as a created thing must be cold. Uddyotakara says that the inference
is baffled by a perception of fire.
The conflict here is between a prediction based on an inductive generalisation
and an actual observation. In general, one faces a choice whenever one has
both an inference to the truth of some conclusion and strong evidence that the
conclusion is false. One can either reject the evidence for the falsity of the
conclusion, or else reject one of the premises in the inference. The examples
of Descartes are cases where the first option is the correct one to choose. The
evidence of the senses is defeated in one case by its own internal inconsistency
and in the other by a generalisation with enormous empirical support (that
things look smaller when they are further away). But the example of Vatsyayana
is a case where the second option is the correct one. In the face of incontrovertible
observation, one must reject the similarity metric on the basis of which the
extrapolation was made.
When is it rational to reject the premise, when the conclusion? Is this not
a question for reason itself to decide, and when it decides in favour of the
conclusion (i.e. of perception) does it not therefore decide to override itself?
It is to avoid the apparent absurdity of such a result that the Nyaya insist on
there being two different models or faculties of reason: reason as the rational
extrapolator, and reason as the rational integrator of mental contents
(perceptual and inferential). Integrative reason strikes a balance between
perception and extrapolation, preferring one or the other according to its
own standards. What is true of the relation between perception and inference
is true too of the relation between testimony and inference, and true also of
the relation between perception and testimony. What is the norm on
integration? What principle does it follow in deciding who to override?
Maximising consistency is the obvious answer, but there is scope for
weighting. The Nyaya, it would seem, wants to weight testimony (and
especially scriptural testimony) more heavily than anything else, and to
weight observation more heavily than extrapolation. The pure reasoner of
the epics would maximise the weight given to inference – no doctrine is
unrevisable, no scripture sacred – or else, like the materialist, to observation.
Such an anti-dogmatism may have led him to be banished from the company
of the virtuous, but for us a question still remains. If there is a choice of
weightings, which one is the rational choice? On what principle does one
choose? The search for reasons goes on. Only at the end of this book will we
see how the later Naiyayikas brought this search for reasons to a close
(Chapter 6).
Can reason really override itself? As we have seen (Chapter 1.7), five sorts
of bogus reason are mentioned in Nyayasutra 1.2.4. In two of them, the
unproven and the counter-balanced, reason acts as its own regulator. These
are important, for they are favourite weapons of the sceptic. The situation
called ‘counter-balanced’ is one in which, in order to resolve the point at
The motive and method of rational inquiry
39
issue, the debater adduces a reason which might equally well prove the point
either way. The reason meets all the criteria for warranted extrapolation, and
would have been entirely adequate in settling the matter, were it not for the
possibility of an equally acceptable and adequate extrapolation to the opposite
conclusion. Vatsyayana’s example is: sound is non-eternal because we do not
apprehend in sound the properties of eternal things, just like the pot, etc. The
objection to this otherwise admissible extrapolation is that it is reversible. For
we can equally well argue as follows: sound is eternal because we do not
apprehend in sound the properties of non-eternal things, just like the sky, etc.
This too, on its own, would have been an admissible extrapolation. (A simpler,
if not entirely suitable, example would be: sound is eternal because it is eternal;
and: sound is non-eternal because it is non-eternal.) In the absence of any
ground for preferring one of these over the other, the most reasonable thing to
do is to accept neither. Behind this bogus reason is another maxim of
extrapolation: when faced with equal, but opposite bases for extrapolation
between which you cannot choose, do not extrapolate. When reasons are
balanced against each other, one is driven instead towards the sceptic’s ataraxia
(see Chapter 2.5).
The other bogus reason of interest to us here is the one called ‘unproven’,
or, more literally, ‘same as the thesis’ (sadhyasama). The reason is one which
has not itself been established, and in that sense is in the same state as the
thesis to be proved. Vatsyayana’s intriguing example is: a shadow is a substance
because it moves. We have again an otherwise admissible extrapolation, but
one that would be a false move in a debate. The problem is that the movement
of shadows is not itself an established fact: it is neither a shared doctrine nor
an indisputable observation. For one needs to know whether shadows are
seen to move like men, or whether what takes place is a succession of
perceptions of dimly lit things produced by the obstruction of the light by a
moving cover. Extrapolation proceeds from the seen to the unseen, or more
generally, from the proven to the unproven. The underlying maxim on
extrapolation is therefore: only extrapolate from what you have already
established. The fault of being ‘the same as the thesis’ is a violation of this
maxim.
The Madhyamika sceptic Nagarjuna uses this fault to devastating effect.
He argues that any reason adduced to refute the sceptical thesis will suffer
the fault of being the same as the thesis. For if the sceptical thesis is that
nothing can be known, then to refute it is to prove that something can be
known. But if it is not yet established that anything can be known, one can
adduce no known or established fact to prove it. So any putative reason one
adduces to prove that something can be known will be the ‘same as the
thesis’ in being as yet unproven. The two propositions, ‘A proves B only if A
is proven in advance of B’ and ‘B = something is proven’ in combination
entail that A has to be something which is proven in advance of anything
being proven, and this entails that there is no such A. The sceptic’s thesis is
indefeasible!
40
Philosophy in classical India
Such is the account of reason as it was conceived in early India. The
concept is a shifting, not to say shifty, one, an interplay of different themes.
The collection of ideas presented here was supposed to describe the way people
actually do reason and explain why they are justified in doing so. It is a
common-sense theory of common sense. In the subsequent chapters, I will
look at attacks on this account from several directions. The Madhyamika
sceptic’s claim that reason is self-defeating has already been mentioned. It is
self-defeating because, if true, it is provable that nothing is provable (Chapter
2). The Jainas are diametrically opposed: reason, they say, is over-complete:
everything is provable (Chapter 5). And Dinnaga, a founder-member of
Yogacara-Vijñanavada Buddhism, is neither a sceptic nor a syncretist, but a
unificationist about reason. What he rejects is the idea that there is a plurality
in the concept of rationality (rationality qua integrator, qua extrapolator, and
qua recipient of testimony). Such a unification of reason, it turns out, necessitates
a radical departure from naiveté (Chapter 4). At the end of the book, we will
return to Nyaya, and see how in the later period, responding to the many and
varied assaults on the concept of rationality embedded in common sense, it
revitalised its defence of the common-sense account.
FURTHER READING
Texts
Gautama c. AD 150, Nyayasutra (NS).
Vatsyayana c. AD 450, Nyayabhasya (NBh).
Rationality, philosophical method (1.1–3)
1
Arindam Chakrabarti, ‘Rationality in Indian Philosophy,’ in Eliot
Deutsch and Ron Bontekoe eds., A Companion to World Philosophies (Oxford:
Blackwell Publishers, 1997), pp. 259–278.
2
Wilhelm Halbfass, ‘Darsana, Anviksiki, Philosophy,’ in his India
and Europe: an Essay in Understanding (Albany: State University of New
York Press, 1988), pp. 263–286.
3
Bimal Krishna Matilal, ‘On the Concept of Philosophy in India,’ in
Philosophy, Culture and Religion: Collected Essays (Delhi: Oxford University
Press, 2001).
4
Bimal Krishna Matilal, Perception: An Essay on Classical Indian
Theories of Knowledge (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), Chapter 3.
5
C. Ram–Prasad, Knowledge and the Highest Good: Liberation and
Philosophical Inquiry in Classical Indian Thought (Basingstoke: Macmillan,
2000).
The motive and method of rational inquiry
41
Perception, mind (1.4–5)
1
Bimal Krishna Matilal, Perception: An Essay on Classical Indian
Theories of Knowledge (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1986), Chapters 6, 8.
2
Bimal Krishna Matilal, ‘A Realist View of Perception,’ in P. K. Sen
and R. R. Verma eds., The Philosophy of P. F. Strawson (New Delhi: Indian
Council of Philosophical Research, 1995), pp. 305–326; reprinted in his
Philosophy, Religion, Culture: Collected Essays (Delhi: Oxford University
Press, 2001).
3
Arindam Chakrabarti, ‘I Touch What I Saw,’ Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research 52 (1992), pp. 103–117.
4
Kishor Chakrabarti, Indian Philosophy of Mind: The Nyaya Dualist
Tradition (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1999).
Extrapolation, informal logic, debate (1.6–7)
1
Esther Solomon, Indian Dialectics (Ahmedabad: B. J. Institute of
Learning and Research, 1976), 2 volumes.
2
Mrinalkanti Gangopadhyay, Indian Logic In Its Sources (Delhi:
Munshiram Manoharlal, 1984).
3
Claudius Nenninger, ‘Analogical Reasoning in Early NyayaVaisesika,’ Asiatische Studien 48 (1994), pp. 819–832.
4
Claus Oetke, ‘Ancient Indian Logic as a Theory of Non-Monotonic
Reasoning,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 24 (1996), pp. 447–539.
5
Bimal Krishna Matilal, The Character of Logic in India (Albany:
State University of New York Press, 1998).
Testimony, tradition (1.8–9)
1 Bimal Krishna Matilal and Arindam Chakrabarti eds., Knowing from
Words (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1994).
2 J. N. Mohanty, Reason and Tradition in Indian Thought (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1992), Chapters 8, 9.
3 Jonardon Ganeri, ‘Testimony,’ in Semantic Powers: Meaning and the
Means of Knowing in Classical Indian Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1999), pp. 72–81.
2 Rationality, emptiness and the
objective view
2.1 THOUGHT AND REALITY
Is reality accessible to thought? Could it not be that there are limits on our
cognitive capacities, and the way the world is, whatever that might be, is
something beyond our powers of understanding? What there is in the world
might extend beyond what we, in virtue of our natural cognitive endowment,
have the capacity to form a conception of.
The thesis is a radical form of scepticism. It is a scepticism about what we
can conceive rather than about what we can know. Nagarjuna (c. AD 150),
founder of the Madhyamaka school of Indian Buddhism, is a radical sceptic
of this sort. Indeed, he is still more radical. His thesis is not merely that there
may be aspects of reality beyond the reach of conception, but that thought
entirely fails to reach reality. If there is a world, it is a world about which we
can form no adequate conception. Moreover, since language expresses thought,
it is a world about which we cannot speak.
Where the reach of thought turns back, language turns back. The nature
of things (dharmata) is, like nirvana, without origin and without decay.
(MK 18.7)
Not dependent on another, calm, not conceptualised by conception, not
mentally constructed, not diverse – this is the mark of reality (tattva).
(MK 18.9)
This indeed is for Nagarjuna the true meaning of the Buddha’s teachings, a
meaning so disruptive to common reason that the Buddha was reluctant to
spell it out.
For that reason – that the truth (dharma) is deep and difficult to understand
– the Buddha’s mind despaired of being able to teach it. (MK 24.12)
A century of scholarship on the Madhyamaka system has seen a plethora of
interpretations. David Seyfort Ruegg has remarked on a situation in which
Rationality, emptiness and the objective view
43
‘the doctrine of the Madhyamaka school, and in particular that of Nagarjuna,
has been variously described as nihilism, monism, irrationalism, misology,
agnosticism, scepticism, criticism, dialectic, mysticism, acosmism, absolutism,
relativism, nominalism, and linguistic analysis with therapeutic value.’1 More
recently, thematic relationships with antirealism2 and the Derridean technique
of deconstruction3 have received attention. Nagarjuna is certainly a complex
and at times ambiguous thinker. He writes in an aphoristic style, he may
have shifted his position in the course of his career, and no-one is entirely sure
whether many of the works usually attributed to him are his own compositions.
The exegetical problems remain fully to be resolved. What we can be sure of
is that Nagarjuna did indeed compose two fascinating philosophical
documents, the Middle Stanzas (Mulamadhyamakakarika: MK) and his Reply
to Critics (Vigrahavyavartani: V), whose great value lies in the undisputedly
radical nature of their ideas. What seems clear is that Nagarjuna thinks that
the conceptual scheme implicit in common sense presupposes the existence of
a world of stable, self-sustaining objects, and that his philosophical method
consists in demonstrating that existential presuppositions of this sort are never
true. To reach the sceptical thesis one needs a more general result, that the
common-sense scheme is the only possible conceptual scheme. For if nothing
of the sort that thought presupposes exists, then anything – if there is anything
– which does exist is inaccessible to thought.
2.2 EMPTINESS AND THE OBJECTIVE VIEW
The theory of emptiness (sunyata) is Nagarjuna’s most celebrated doctrine.
It is a theory about the nature of our understanding of our own experience,
and its relation to the world. It is a theory about our capacity for objective
thought. Experience represents itself as being about external objects, yet all
but the most unreflective know that their experience is sometimes misleading.
Among Nagarjuna’s favourite examples are witnessing the illusory objects
conjured up in a magical trick, apprehending an object in a dream, and
thinking that the objects of stories and fables, such as the city of celestial
musicians, are real (MK 7.34, 17.33, 23.8). We may add holograms,
hallucinations, objects seen in film projections. If one is to be able to
understand such experiences for what they are, the unreflective view must
be replaced with a more objective one, a view achieved by reflecting on the
origin of such experiences. One must attain a perspective on one’s own
experience which enables one to think of illusions, dreams and holograms
along with their etiology, and so to explain their occurrence without recourse
to the assumption that they have genuine content. The process of stepping
back from the contingencies of appearance produces a sequence of
progressively more objective conceptions. If the process can be completed,
it is completed in the attainment of an ‘objective view’4 or ‘absolute
conception’.5
Nagarjuna presses us towards an objective view. He observes that there
44
Philosophy in classical India
are types of experience for which, when we place them within our conception
of the world, we can find an adequate explanation without having to suppose
that there actually exist things of the sort represented in the experience. We
are not deceived by the magician’s illusion because we can explain the
appearance in terms of the magical trick. The new understanding we have
come to is a conception of such experiences as ones whose objects are, in
Nagarjuna’s term, ‘empty’. They are empty because they depend for their
apparent existence on other factors, such as the magician, the dream, the
holographic projector, or the fictional narrative.
Emptiness is proved on the grounds that things do not have self-standing
natures (svabhava). The dependent nature of things is what is called
‘emptiness,’ for a dependent nature is one which is not self-standing. (V
21–22)
We claim that dependent origination is emptiness. It is a derivative
designation, and it alone is the middle way. (MK 24.18)
One is in a position to think of an experience as empty if one can explain its
occurrence in terms of a set of causes none of which is an object of the type the
experience presents. The ability to think of one’s experiences in this way
depends on one’s having taken the first step towards an objective stance.
Someone who has taken this first step towards objectivity will contrast two
kinds of experience. Part of one’s experience is now understood as arising in
dependence of a deviant etiology. The remainder of one’s experience, however,
has to be understood in another way, as being about what causes it. The
conceptual scheme encoded in common sense offers just such an explanation.
What are the key elements in the common-sense scheme, the most deeply
ingrained categories in our thinking about the constituents of our surroundings
and our interactions with them? In the chapters of the Middle Stanzas,
Nagarjuna identifies the following concepts: origin, motion, sensory perception,
physical objects and their properties, desire, causation, past and future, suffering
(duhkha), combination, the idea that things have a self-standing nature or
essence, bondage and release, agency, the self, the flow of time, creation and
decay, and the possibility of error. Our common-sense understanding of the
world is as one containing stable, self-sustaining objects which move about
and causally influence one another, which we can see in virtue of their causal
influence upon us, which are caused to come into being and eventually to
decay, and which stand in spatio-temporal relations to one another and to us.
The karma hypothesis appears here too as a deeply entrenched ingredient in
the classical Indian common-sense understanding of moral consequence
(Chapter 1.3).
The common-sense understanding of ordinary (non-deviant) experience is
of experience as caused by the object it purports to represent. Such experience
is said to have a ‘support’ (alambana) in the world of objects (see Chapter
Rationality, emptiness and the objective view
45
4.10). When one thinks in this way of one’s experience as caused by the object
it represents, one has a certain conception of objects. They are conceived of
as things which can be perceived and can also continue to exist unperceived.
Nagarjuna claims that they are conceived of as things which have a ‘selfstanding nature’ or svabhava. This complex and ambiguous term conveys
notions of permanence, stability, endurance, independence, essence, identity.
It stands for the idea of an object which can exist independently of any
perception or experience, and which, by existing for a duration of time, can
be perceived more than once at different times. It is a conception of things
‘out there’ which make intelligible our having the experiences we do when no
other explanation of their origin can be found.
The common-sense understanding of our experiences and conceptions is a
step in the direction of objectivity, a step away from an uncritical acceptance
of the existential presuppositions of experience and conception. The crucial
move is the next one. Nagarjuna describes it as a move from ‘conventional’
truth (samvrtti-sat) to ‘ultimate’ truth (paramartha-sat). We may regard it as
the step from the common-sense scheme to an absolute conception. What
happens when we take another step away from appearance, when the conception
of these two kinds of experience itself becomes part of what we want to
understand? The possibility explored by Nagarjuna is that our conception of
experience, as produced by self-sustaining and independent objects, is itself a
fiction of the common-sense scheme. To put it another way, when we step
back from the common-sense scheme, what we come to understand is that we
have no independent conception of an independent reality, but conceive it
only as containing things which are not empty. The common-sense scheme
applies to such things because we have a category of experience for which we
can find no ‘deviant’ causal explanation. What we now discover is that it is a
mistake to take this inability to comprehend all of our experience in the way
we comprehend dreams and illusions as grounds for thinking that such
experience must be thought of as caused by an explanatorily independent
world of objects. Nagarjuna recommends calmness in place of striving for
such explanations:
Those with little understanding who see only the existence and nonexistence of things fail to see the calmness of what is experienceable.
(MK 5.8)
When one steps out of the common-sense conception and towards an objective
view, the view to which one is led is that all conception is empty. The idea
of experience explained by thinking of it as caused by explanatorily
independent objects is seen now for what it is – a fiction of the commonsense scheme. Such experience ought to be conceived of simply as experience
for which the experiencer cannot find the explanation. It is the proper function
of rationality to lead one to a critical assessment of one’s own conceptual
46
Philosophy in classical India
scheme, to an understanding of the operations and deceptions of common
sense, and so eventually to an objective view. Nagarjuna’s claim is that
when reason is so used, the objective understanding one attains is that the
‘naive’ view, the view that there is a role for objects in the causal explanation
of experience, is nothing but an appearance of explanation, created by the
naive view itself. An objective understanding is an understanding that all
conception and all experience is empty.
Just like a master, by his magical powers, fashions a magical figure,
and this magical figure in turn fashions another magical figure – in
that way, an agent is like the magical figure and his action like the
other figure fashioned by the first. Afflictions, actions, bodies, agents
and effects are like a city of celestial musicians or a mirage or a
dream. (MK 17.31–33)
The form of understanding encoded in common sense is more objective than
blind trust in one’s experience because with it one understands that some
experience is ‘genuine’ and other experience is mere ‘appearance’. The new
view, the view Nagarjuna thinks can be reached by a critical exercise of
reason, is that the explanation of ‘genuine’ experience offered by common
sense is itself a mere appearance of an explanation. Common sense deceives
us, just as common experience does. Common experience deceives us into
thinking that magical projections and other mere appearances exist. Common
sense deceives us into thinking that genuine experience is explained with
reference to a world of objects. When we achieve an objective understanding,
we realise that common sense is itself the projection of a magician, a magical
figure which fashions another magical figure in the form of the distinction
between genuine experience and mere appearance. Nagarjuna’s point, and
it is a theme running right through his work, is that common sense deceives
us when it appeals to the idea of an ‘independent’ object, which explains
why we have the experiences we do, but is not itself within the explanatory
web. But it is better to accept that some experiences are unexplained, than
to appeal to an idea which gives only an impression of being an explanation,
but in fact offers no real explanation. The same point is what leads him to
his attack on the ideas of an uncaused causer, an unproved prover, an
unmoving mover and an unperceived perceiver. The circle of explanation
(or causation, or proof, or motion, or perception) must be (but cannot be)
closed.
The Nyaya model of rational inquiry is itself a model embedded within
common sense. It is the intuitive, natural, naive account of the rational
processes of belief-formation, revision and rejection. For the commonsense appeal to the idea that beliefs are true when they are caused by what
they represent is itself a certification of certain methods of belief-formation
as rational. Nagarjuna has a quite different conception of the means and
ends of rationality.
Rationality, emptiness and the objective view
47
2.3 RATIONALITY IN MADHYAMAKA
Rationality is the means by which one ‘steps back’ to a more objective view.
Rationality is a mode of critical evaluation of one’s conceptual scheme. A
more objective understanding is one in which one understands that things are
not necessarily as they appear. It is a view from which one can see how and
where one’s earlier conceptions are misleading. One learns not to trust one’s
perceptions when a large object far away looks small, or a stick half submerged in water looks bent, and in learning this one exercises a mode of selfcritical reason. So too rational people learn not to trust their conceptions
when they presuppose the existence of independent, self-standing objects. From
the vantage point of an objective view, it is easy to see that one’s old conceptions
had false presuppositions. The real trick, however, is to be able to expose
those presuppositions while still ‘within’ the old conception, and so to lever
oneself up to a more objective view. This levering-up-from-within requires a
new way of reasoning: Nagarjuna’s celebrated prasanga-type rationality. It is
a self-critical rationality which exposes as false the existential presuppositions
on which one’s present conceptions are based.
One feature of those presuppositions is especially important. A conceptual
scheme does not presuppose a world of objects so much as a structure of division.
A conceptual scheme is a grid of divisions and relations imposed upon an
undifferentiated, amorphous reality. A system of concepts is a way of cutting,
grouping and relating. It represents a choice about where the boundaries of
objects should fall. Modern studies of the notion of an object encoded in common
sense suggest that common sense encodes principles of cohesion (‘surfaces lie on
one object if and only if they are connected’), principles of contact (‘surfaces
move together if and only if they are in contact’) and principles of continuity (‘an
object traces exactly one connected path over space and time’).6 Other notions of
an object, other carvings of reality, are possible, for example, the notion of an
object in Vaisesika ontology (for which, see Chapter 3), or those encoded in
modern physical theory. What a conceptual scheme presupposes, then, is that the
ways of cutting, grouping and relating which it encodes correspond to natural
structures of division and organisation in the world. It is on this presupposition
that the Madhyamika process of rational self-criticism bears.
A simple example will illustrate the kind of reasoning Nagarjuna thinks is
needed if one is to expose the presuppositions of one’s conceptual scheme
from within. A non-compound monadic concept ‘F’ has the following
application-condition: it applies only to things which are F. It is therefore a
concept whose application presupposes that there is a condition which divides
the domain into two. For our purposes, the condition can be thought of either
as ‘belonging to the class of Fs’ or ‘possessing the property being-F’. Now
take an arbitrary object, a, from some antecedently specified domain. There
are apparently two possibilities for a: either it falls under the concept, or else
it does not. That is, the two options are:
48
Philosophy in classical India
(I) F applies to a.
(II) F does not apply to a.
Suppose that one can disprove both of these options. How one would try to do
this will vary from case to case, depending on the individual concept under
scrutiny. But if one is able to disprove (I) and to disprove (II), then the concept in
question can have no application-condition. The presupposition for the
application of the concept, that there is a condition (class, property) effecting a
division within the domain, fails. A later Madhyamika master7 expresses the idea
exactly:
When neither existence nor non-existence presents itself before the mind,
then, being without objective support (niralambana) because there is no
other way, [the mind] is still.
Sentences are used to make statements, but if the statement so made is neither
true nor false, then, because there is no third truth-value, the statement must
be judged to lack content.8
Nagarjuna’s developed strategy involves a generalisation. A generalisation
is needed because many if not most of the concepts under scrutiny are relational
rather than monadic; centrally: causes, sees, moves, desires. When a concept
is relational, there are four rather than two ways for its application-condition
to be satisfied (Figure 2.1):
(I)
(II)
(III)
(IV)
R relates a only to itself.
R relates a only to things other than itself.
R relates a both to itself and to things other than itself.
R relates a to nothing.
As an illustration of the four options, take R to be the square-root relation √,
and the domain of objects to be the set of real numbers. Then the four
possibilities are exemplified by the numbers 0, 4, 1 and -1 respectively. For √0
= 0, √4 = 2 and also -2, √1 = 1 and also -1, while finally -1 does not have a
defined square root among the real numbers. The list of four options is what
is called in Madhyamaka a catuskoti.
Everything is thus, not thus, both thus and not thus, or neither thus nor
not thus. That is the Buddha’s [provisional] instruction. (MK 18.8)
Some say that suffering (duhkha) is self-produced, or produced
from another, or produced from both, or produced without a cause.
(MK 12.1)
Since every factor in existence (dharma) is empty, what is finite and what
is infinite? What is both finite and infinite? What is neither finite nor
infinite? (MK 25.22)
Rationality, emptiness and the objective view
49
Figure 2.1 The four options.
It is easy to see that the four options are mutually exclusive and jointly
exhaustive. For the class of objects to which R relates a is either (IV) the
empty set Ø or, if not, then either (I) it is identical to {a}, or (II) it excludes {a},
or (III) it includes {a}. Not every relation exhibits all four options. (I) is not
exhibited if R is anti-reflexive. (II) is not exhibited if R is reflexive and bijective.
(IV) is not exhibited if R is defined on every point in the domain. Note in
particular that if R is the identity relation, then neither (III) nor (IV) is exhibited,
not (III) because identity is transitive, and not (IV) because identity is reflexive.
Indeed, options (III) and (IV) are not exhibited whenever R is an equivalence
(transitive, symmetric and reflexive) relation.
The next step in the strategy is to construct subsidiary ‘disproofs’, one for
each of the four options. Although there is no pre-determined procedure for
constructing such disproofs, by far the most commonly used method is to
show that the option in question has some unacceptable consequence (prasanga).
A major dispute for later Madhyamikas was over what sort of reasoning is
permissible in the four subsidiary disproofs, the proofs that lead to the rejection
of each of the four options. It is a difficult question to answer, so difficult
indeed that it led, at around 500 AD, to a fission within the school of
Madhyamaka. The principal group (Prasangika, headed by Buddhapalita)
insisted that only prasanga-type, ‘presupposition-negating’ reasoning is
admissible. This faction is the more conservative and mainstream, in the
sense that their teaching seems to be in keeping with Nagarjuna’s own method
of reasoning. The important later Madhyamika masters Candrakirti and
Santideva defended this view. A splinter faction, however (Svatantrika, headed
by Bhavaviveka), allowed ‘independent’ inference or inductive demonstration
into the disproofs. Perhaps this was done so that the inductive methods
developed by Dinnaga (Chapter 4.7) could be deployed in establishing the
Madhyamika’s doctrinal position. Clearly, the fewer restrictions one places
50
Philosophy in classical India
on the type of reasoning one permits oneself to use, the greater are the prospects
of successfully finding arguments to negate each of the four options. On the
other hand, we have seen that the citation of paradigmatic examples is essential
to this type of reasoning (Chapter 1.6–7), and it is hard to see how one could
be entitled to cite examples in support of one’s argument, when the very
conception of those examples is in question.
The effect of the four subsidiary disproofs is to establish that none of the
four options obtains:9
Neither from itself nor from another, nor from both, nor without a cause,
does anything whatever anywhere arise. (MK 1.1)
One may not say that there is emptiness, nor that there is non-emptiness.
Nor that both, nor that neither exists; the purpose for so saying is only
one of provisional understanding. (MK 22.11)
The emptiness of the concept in question is now deduced as the final step in
the process. For it is a presupposition of one of the four options obtaining that
the concept does have an application-condition (a class of classes or relational
property). If all four are disproved, then the presupposition itself cannot be
true. When successful, the procedure proves that the concept in question is
empty, null, sunya. This is Nagarjuna’s celebrated and controversial ‘prasangatype’ rational inquiry, a sophisticated use of rationality to annul a conceptual
scheme.
A statement is truth-apt if it is capable of being evaluated as either true
or false. When Nagarjuna rejects each of the four options, he is rejecting the
claim that a statement of the form ‘aRb’ is truth-apt, since the four options
exhaust the possible ways in which it might be evaluated as true. But if the
statements belonging to a certain discourse are not truth-apt, then the
discourse cannot be part of an objective description of the world (a joke is
either funny or unfunny, but it cannot be evaluated as true or false). The
prasanga negates a presupposition for truth-aptness and so for objective
reference.
Nagarjuna applies the procedure in an attempt to annul each of the
concepts I listed above as the basic ingredients of the common-sense scheme.
In each case, his method is to identify a relation and prove that none of the
four options can obtain. On closer inspection, it turns out that his
argumentation falls into two basic patterns.10 One pattern is applied to
any concept involving the idea of an ordering or sequence, especially the
concept of a causal relation, of a temporal relation and of a proof relation.
The paradigm for this argument is Nagarjuna’s presentation of a paradox
of origin (MK Chapter 1), which serves as model for his analysis of
causation (MK Chapter 8), the finitude of the past and future (MK Chapter
11), and suffering (MK Chapter 12). The argument seeks to establish that
a cause can be neither identical to, nor different from, the effect. If nothing
Rationality, emptiness and the objective view
51
within the domain is uncaused, then the four options for the realisation of
a causal relation are foreclosed.
The other pattern of argumentation in Nagarjuna is essentially
grammatical. When a relational concept is expressed by a transitive verb,
the sentence has an Agent and a Patient (the relata of the relation): for
example, ‘He sees the tree,’ ‘He goes to the market,’ ‘He builds a house.’
The idea of the grammatical argument is that one can exploit features of the
deep case structure of such sentences in order to prove that the Patient can
be neither identical to the Agent, nor include it, nor exclude it, and that
there must he a Patient. Nagarjuna uses this pattern of argumentation in
constructing a paradox of motion (MK Chapter 2), and this chapter serves
as a model for his analysis of perception (MK Chapter 3), composition (MK
Chapter 7), fire (MK Chapter 10), and of bondage and release (MK Chapter
16). Indeed, the same pattern of argument seems to be applicable whenever
one has a concept which involves a notion of a single process extended in
time. In the next three sections, I will reconstruct respectively Nagarjuna’s
arguments against causation, proof and motion. What we say about these
prototypical cases will apply inter alia to all other concepts to which the
two basic strategies apply.
2.4 ON CAUSATION
How does the causal argument go? In a passage on the origins of suffering, a
theme so central to Buddhist soteriology and the Buddha’s teaching, Nagarjuna
rehearses the general pattern of argumentation:
Some say that suffering is self-produced, or produced from another, or
produced from both, or produced without a cause. (MK 12.1)
If suffering came from itself, then it would not arise dependently; surely
those sensory and bodily aggregates arise in dependence on these sensory
and bodily aggregates. (MK 12.2)
When being self-produced is not established, how could suffering be caused
by another? Whatever caused the suffering of another must have caused
its own suffering. (MK 12.7)
If suffering were caused by each, it could be caused by both. Not produced
by another nor self-produced. How could suffering be uncaused? (MK 12.9)
Not only are the four options impossible in respect to suffering, none of
the four options is possible even in respect to external things (bhava).
(MK 12.10)
The relational concept under scrutiny is ‘originator of’. The object in
question here is suffering, but Nagarjuna extends the argument to include
52
Philosophy in classical India
any object within the causal order. Let us then take some arbitrary object,
a. The four options are (I) that a originates in itself, (II) that it originates
in some other, (III) that it originates in itself and originates in some
other, and (IV) that it has no origin. And, if we read these passages along
with others in the Middle Stanzas, the four disproofs have something like
the following structure.
Disproof of (I). If a is self-originating then it exists and perpetuates itself
independently of anything else. For a is self-originating just in case a necessary
and sufficient cause of its existence at time t is its existence at time t - δ, and
so on backwards in time. It follows that there is no point in time at which a
comes into existence, for its existence at one instant is necessary for its existence
at the next. It also follows that there is no point in time at which it goes out of
existence, for its existence at one time is sufficient for its existence at the next.
So calling something ‘self-causing’ is just a rather misleading way of saying
that it is eternal. This is misleading because it is wrong to think of eternal
entities as ‘causal’ at all. They are outside the causal realm. This is the
prasanga, the unacceptable consequence of the initial hypothesis.
Disproof of (II). The claim is that only things other than a can be causes of
a. If a originates from some other thing, then one must ask wherefrom this
other thing originates. It cannot originate from itself. This is because, in the
previous argument, a was an object chosen arbitrarily. So that argument will
apply with equal force to the originator of a. But if the originator of a itself
originates from some other, we have the beginning of an infinite chain of
distinct causes (MK 7.19: ‘If another originates this, then origination is infinitely
regressive’). It cannot, however, be a matter of logical necessity that the world
of objects is infinite.
Disproof of (III). The remaining possibility is that at some point a causal
ancestry loops back on itself. An object in such a loop would be caused by all
the members of the loop, and so have both itself and other things among its
sufficient causes. However, the argument against (I) proved that a is not a
sufficient cause of itself, and the argument against (II) proved that no other
thing is a sufficient cause of a. So (III) is disproved by either of the previous
arguments.
Disproof of (IV). Can something exist and have no originating cause? One
may be inclined to think of numbers, universals and other abstract objects,
but Nagarjuna has specified that the argument is applicable only to bhavas,
and we may take a bhava in this context to be an object within the causal
order. Elsewhere, he insists that ‘there is nowhere an existing thing without a
cause’ (MK 4.2).
An interesting dialectical strategy underpins this sequence of arguments.
(I) in general asserts that R relates a to itself and that R does not relate a
to any other thing. The disproof consists in showing that R does not even
relate a to itself. Similarly (II) in general asserts that R relates a to other
things and that R does not relate a to itself. It is disproved by showing that
R does not even relate a to other things. The arguments against (I) and (II)
Rationality, emptiness and the objective view
53
are then individually sufficient to disprove (III), that R relates a to itself
and to other things.
Suppose we let ‘A’ stand for ‘R relates a to itself,’ and that we let ‘B’ stand
for ‘R relates a to other things.’ The dialectical structure is now:
So (III) is disproved both by the disproof of (I) and by that of (II). Nagarjuna
might have chosen a different dialectical strategy here. He might have chosen
to disprove (I) by disproving ‘A’, and to disprove (II) by disproving ‘¬A’. The
disproof of (III) would then follow from the disproof of (I), but not from that of
(II). He might also have chosen to disprove (I) by disproving ‘¬B’, and to
disprove (II) by disproving ‘B.’ The disproof of (III) would then follow from
the disproof of (II), but not from that of (I). To use either of these alternative
strategies, however, one would have to be happy with the idea that a proposition
and its negation can simultaneously be disproved. The important point is
that, whichever strategy one uses, the disproof of (III) is trivial once one has a
disproof of both (I) and (II).
The way that (IV) has been disproved is instructive too. In fact, it is not so
much disproved as ruled out by fiat. For we restrict the domain to objects
within the causal order, leaving no room for an object within the domain and
yet uncaused. This is a characteristic function of the fourth option. It is used
to delimit the domain is such a way that everything within the domain has the
property under scrutiny (in this case, the property having-an-origin).
Nagarjuna has sometimes been understood differently.11 It has been claimed
that Nagarjuna derives his argument against origin from a paradox about
change. Nagarjuna does indeed formulate the paradox of change in one place:
If a thing were by nature to exist, then it could not fail to exist, for a
change of nature is certainly not possible. (MK 15.8)
In the absence of a nature, what can undergo the process of change? On
the other hand, if a nature is present, what can undergo the process of
change? (MK 15.9)
The argument against (I) might then be that a thing that comes into being out
of itself cannot change from one moment to the next, and if it does not change
then nothing new has come into being. And an argument against (II) might be
that if one thing can change into something completely different from itself,
54
Philosophy in classical India
then there is nothing to regulate what produces what. If an oak tree can
originate from an acorn, then why not from a mustard seed? The general
strategy here is to argue that once we allow that R can relate a to things other
than itself, there can be no regulation as to which other things a is so related.
This is the prasanga, the unacceptable consequence, of assuming (II).
If this is Nagarjuna’s argument, it is a difficult one to defend. The idea that
the effect must resemble or pre-exist in its cause has always been enticing, but
it has little to recommend it. I think Nagarjuna has a much stronger argument
in mind. The idea that things have causes, if applied universally, forces us
into the unacceptable position of having to accept infinite causal chains or
else causal loops. The alternative, to allow there to be exceptions to the
proposition that things have causes and admit there to be uncaused causers, is
to make an unprincipled distinction. For there is no rational criterion with
which to divide things into the caused and the uncaused.
Let me try to clarify the structure of this argument. Graham Priest12 has shown
that there is a general structure common to many of the most familiar paradoxes.
A paradox arises whenever one has a function or operation which is bound to a
domain and yet which goes beyond that domain. A paradox is thus the result of
a pair of arguments. One proves closure – that the result of performing the
operation in question falls within a given domain. The other proves
transcendence – that the result of performing the operation in question falls
outside the domain. The pattern of arguing from the four options itself conforms
to this schema. For I observed that the effect of rejecting option (IV) is to delimit
the domain of entities to which the argument applies. So the rejection of (IV) is an
assertion of closure. And the rejection of the first three options jointly constitutes
the proof of transcendence, that the operation must nevertheless go beyond the
domain.
For the paradox of origin, take the domain to be the class C of things
which have causal originators, and the operation to be a function d from
objects to their originators. The idea behind the proof of transcendence is that
the repeated application of the ‘originator of’ function to an arbitrary object
a eventually takes us out of the domain C. The originator of the originator of
. . . of the originator of a is not in C:
∃n δna ∉ C
Transcendence
Closure, on the other hand, is the thesis that no matter how often the ‘originator
of’ function is iterated, it never maps out of C:
!n δna ∉ C
Closure
The proof of closure is, as I noted earlier, the role of the refutation of the
fourth option in the catuskoti. For this option states that objects arise uncaused,
while closure states that no object lacks a causal originator. I regard this as
having the force of a stipulation on what ‘object’ means in this context.
Rationality, emptiness and the objective view
55
The function of the first three options in the catuskoti is to prove
transcendence. Iteration on the ‘originator of’ function eventually maps out of
the domain C. The proof is by reductio. Let us assume that for any value of x,
the originator of x is in C. Then either (i) δx = x or (ii) δx ≠ x. Now (i) states
that x is its own originator – it is option (I) in the catuskoti. The argument
against this is that if an object is its own originator, then it must be eternal,
and if it is eternal then it is not within the causal domain, the domain of
things which have causes. That is, if δx = x then δx ∉ C. Calling something
‘self-originating’ is misleading. It gives the impression that such things do
have causal origins, but is really nothing more than a confused neologism for
saying that they are eternal and so acausal.
Let us suppose then that the originator of x is something different from x.
Consider the originator of the originator of x, i.e. δ2x. Again, either (i) δ2x = x
or (ii) δ2x ≠ x. The first possibility is that there are loops of causation, in
which x is caused by y, and y is caused by x. So the originators of x are x itself
and y (I am assuming that causal origination is a transitive relation). This is
option (III) in the catuskoti, the option that things originate both from
themselves and from others. The argument against this is that we again have
self-origination, and so again the object is eternal and so acausal. Another
objection would be that it contradicts the idea that a cause must precede its
effect, but this is not a principle on which Nagarjuna places any great weight.
The only remaining possibility is that δ2x ≠ x, the originator of the originator
of x is not identical to x. Since we have already shown that the originator of
the originator of x is not identical to the originator of x (because no object is
identical to its originator – the rejection of option (I) of the catuskoti), it
follows that x, δx and δ2x are distinct entities. Likewise, δ3x cannot be identical
to δ2x or δx, and if it were identical to x there would again be a causal loop,
this time with three rather than two members. One can clearly go on and
prove that the nth order originator of x is distinct from any lesser order
originator of x unless two lower order originators of x are identical or there is
a causal loop with n members. As long as there are no causal loops, it follows
by induction that the nth order originator of x is distinct from all lower order
originators of x. So there is an infinite sequence of distinct higher order
originators of x. This is the possibility excluded by the rejection of option (II)
in the catuskoti. One argument would be that the domain C is finite. Another
is that causal explanation would be vitiated – one never reaches the explanans.
This then is how Nagarjuna seeks to prove the transcendence part of the
paradox. It is interesting to see in Sextus Empiricus a parallel argumentative
strategy.13 The strategy of the Pyrrhonic sceptic is one of seeking to demonstrate
that the reasons for and against a thesis are equally strong. The Pyrrhonic
sceptic then recommends that the rational course is to suspend all judgment
and in doing so to reach a state of equipoise. From an Indian point of view,
this would be a route to scepticism via the fallacy of the ‘counter-balanced’
reason (Chapter 1.9). Sextus14 argues that it is very plausible that there are
causes, for
56
Philosophy in classical India
[I]f there were no causes, everything would come from everything else,
and by chance. For example, perhaps horses would come from mice, and
elephants from ants; and in Egyptian Thebes there would have been
rainstorms and snow and the south would have had no rain, if there had
not been a cause on account of which the south is stormy in winter and
the east is dry. Further, anyone who says there are no causes is refuted;
for if he claims to make this statement simply and without any cause he
will not be worthy of belief; while if he says that he makes it because of
some cause, he is positing a cause while wishing to deny it, in granting a
cause why causes do not exist.
On the other hand, Sextus argues that it is also very plausible that there are
no causes. One of his arguments is that it is impossible to conceive of a cause
before apprehending its effect as its effect, and this leads to a circularity.
Another argument is that
[A]s we are questioning the very existence of causes, it will be necessary
for him to supply a cause of the cause of there being a cause, and a cause
of that, and so on ad infinitum. But it is impossible to supply an infinite
number of causes; therefore, it is impossible to assert with firm assurance
that anything is the cause of anything.
Another of Sextus’ arguments against there being causes is this:
Whence some people say also the following: The cause must either exist
at the same time as its effect, or before it, or come into being after it. But
to say that the cause is brought into existence after the genesis of its effect
would be ridiculous. But neither can it exist before it, as it is said to be
conceived relatively to it, and the Dogmatists hold that relatives, qua
relative, coexist and are conceived together with one another. Nor can it
exist at the same time as the effect; for if it is productive of the effect, and
if what comes into being must come into being through the agency of
what exists, it is necessary that the cause first become a cause, and then,
this being done, produce the effect. Consequently, if the cause comes into
being neither before nor at the same time as the effect, and the effect does
not come into being before it, it does not, I suppose, have any existence at
all. It is also clear, I think, that by these considerations, too, the concept
of cause is once again destroyed.
The dialectical aims of Sextus and Nagarjuna are rather different, as I have
already observed. In brief the difference is that Nagarjuna thinks that there
can be no reasons for thinking either that there are causes or that there are
no causes, while Sextus thinks that there are plausible reasons for thinking
both that there are causes and that there are no causes. Yet there are certainly
echoes of Nagarjuna in the above passages. Nagarjuna, to be sure, is not as
Rationality, emptiness and the objective view
57
unclear as Sextus seems to be about the distinction between reasons and
causes (although that confusion undoubtedly arose in connection with the
Sanskrit term hetu, which can mean both ‘reason’ and ‘cause’). On the
other hand Nagarjuna’s argument against there being reasons, to which we
shall turn next, does indeed exploit the idea of an infinite regress, and the
pattern of arguing from ‘the three times’ (past, present and future), which
Sextus applies to the question of the existence of causes, is applied by
Nagarjuna to the putative existence of movement and other temporal
processes.
Nagarjuna’s paradox of causation is this: the concept of a cause is incoherent
because, given certain plausible assumptions, it is self-contradictory. The
concept is an empty one, failing to correspond to anything in the structure of
the real world: an apparently unacceptable conclusion derived from apparently
acceptable premises via an apparently acceptable argument. Something must
give! Some authors 15 have claimed to find fallacies in Nagarjuna’s
argumentation. I accept that Nagarjuna is not above using sophistical tricks,
such as equivocation and the like, but I hope that the reconstruction of his
argument I have given above is free from the sorts of fallacy of which he has
been accused. Another response would be to deny that Nagarjuna is employing
the common-sense concept of a cause. His argument depends for its plausibility
on the falsity of the following contentions: that to be self-caused is to be
causal; that there are causal loops; and that there are infinite causal chains.
Might one not argue that one or more of these contentions is consistent with
the common-sense notion of a cause? There is, perhaps, nothing so very counterintuitive about the idea of causal chains stretching back into the infinite past,
or of causation going round in loops.
I believe that no such defence of common sense is necessary. The idea
that the common-sense scheme is best-suited or even well-suited to provide
an adequate explanation of the world has lost its grip with the rise of
scientific theory. We are happy to be told that the ‘solid’ table is really
mostly empty space, that there is a finite maximum speed faster than which
nothing can travel, and so on. Nagarjuna’s error, I suggest, is to be located
in the extrapolation of his argument against the coherence of common
sense to the coherence of any system of concepts, or rather, in his implicit
assumption that the common-sense scheme is the only possible conceptual
scheme. I believe that we can accept that he has shown that the commonsense concept of a cause is incoherent, but reject the further claim that the
structure of reality lies beyond the powers of human conception. The reason
is this. Nagarjuna’s method is to expose the existential presuppositions of
a conceptual scheme, and demonstrate that they cannot obtain. The truth
of any assertion of the form ‘x is caused by y’ presupposes that there are
causal relations, and having shown that there is no value of ‘y’ for which
that assertion is true, the conclusion is drawn that the presupposition fails.
The problem for Nagarjuna is that scientific theories do not presuppose
the existence of entities, but posit them. Theoretical terms are introduced
58
Philosophy in classical India
by explicit stipulations. A scientific conception of the world does not rest
on a set of existential presuppositions, whose falsity would render the
conception empty. It rests on a set of explicit stipulations. So the existence
of entities denoted by the terms of such stipulations is not a presupposition
of the theory’s having content, but that in virtue of which the theory is true
or false.
Nagarjuna does not draw the crucial distinction. It is the distinction between
the ordinary terms in a language and the terms which are introduced by
explicit stipulation. Other Indian philosophers did appreciate the importance
of this distinction. The grammarian Bhartrhari, called terms of the first sort
ajanika ‘immanent’, and terms of the second sort adhunika ‘novel’. Great
weight was placed on this distinction by the scientific rationalists in India,
the Vaisesikas, and especially by Prasastapada (a contemporary of
Bhartrhari). The point is that the existence of a reference is presupposed
only by the use of immanent terms in the language, and not by the use of
stipulatively introduced ones, for which the existence of a reference is part
of what is explicitly stipulated. 16 This vital distinction shielded the
construction of scientific theory from Nagarjuna’s destructive arguments,
and allowed for a new conception of rationality (see Chapter 3). The great
advantage of Dinnaga’s formulation of the Buddhist position over
Nagarjuna’s is precisely that it bears upon the realism of scientific accounts
of conceptual structure (Chapter 4). Such structures, he claims, approach
reality asymptotically, but never reach it.
I have run ahead of myself. Let us go back to Nagarjuna, and examine his
demonstrations of the impossibility of proof and the paradox of motion.
2.5 THE IMPOSSIBILITY OF PROOF
Beliefs are justified with reference to the means by which they are acquired –
this is the central claim of the theory of knowledge known as the pramana
theory (see Chapter 1). Nagarjuna considers the theory to have a flaw so
fundamental as to render it paradoxical. His argument depends on what would
now be called a ‘doxastic ascent’. Ernest Sosa17 says:
It is sometimes held, for example, that perceptual or observational
beliefs are often justified through their origin in the exercise of one
or more of our five senses in standard conditions of perception. The
advocate of doxastic ascent would raise a vigorous protest, however,
for in his view the mere fact of such sensory prompting is impotent
to justify the belief prompted. Such prompting must be coupled with
the further belief that one’s senses work well in the circumstances, or
the like. For we are dealing here with knowledge, which requires not
blind faith but reasoned trust. But now surely the further belief about
the reliability of one’s senses cannot rest on blind faith but requires
its own backing of reasons, and we are off on the regress.
Rationality, emptiness and the objective view
59
Nagarjuna’s formulation of the criticism is similar:
If just such objects are established for you through the means of knowing,
tell me how you establish those means of knowing. If the means of knowing
are established through other means of knowing, then there is an infinite
regress (anavastha). Neither the beginning nor the middle nor the end
can then be established. (V 31–33)
Nagarjuna compares the means of knowing with measuring instruments. Just
as one cannot use a pair of scales to measure weight unless one knows that the
scales have been properly calibrated, so too one cannot use some method as a
means of knowing to ‘measure’ an object of knowledge unless one knows that
the method is an adequate means of knowing.
The literal meaning of anavastha is ‘lack of grounding’. If A is proved
through B, and B proves A only if it is itself proved, then a proof of A necessitates
a proof of B (the doxastic ascent). The argument iterates, and unless the
iteration can be made to come to rest somewhere, A will lack a proof. The
doxastic ascent switches the burden of proof from the thing to be proved to the
means by which it is to be proved. The idea that such a switching of the
burden of proof is legitimate is at one with the idea that it is a fallacy of
reason to establish one’s conclusion on the basis of unproved reasons. This
was the fallacy called the ‘unproven’ or sadhyasama, the reason’s being in
the ‘same predicament’ as what is to be proved. Admitting the legitimacy of
doxastic ascent is equivalent to accepting that this is indeed a fallacy.
Nagarjuna does regard this as a fallacy; indeed, the principal fallacy from
which his critics’ arguments suffer (MK 4.8–9).
The relations ‘is proved by’ and ‘originates in’ both generate infinite chains
by being indefinitely iterable. We can ask for the proof of the proof of A, just
as we can ask for the originator of the originator of x. As in the paradox of
origin, there are just two ways to block the infinite regress. One is by appeal
to the existence of termini of proof, propositions that are either self-proving or
else require no proof. The other is by appeal to the existence of loops of proof,
allowing proof relations to go round in a circle. These are options Nagarjuna
examines systematically in V 33–51. His objection to the idea that there are
two classes of proposition, those that must be proved through some means of
knowing and those that need not, is that this distinction lacks any basis in
reason:
If the means of knowing are established without any means of knowing,
then your position is abandoned. There is a discordance, and you should
state the distinguishing reason (visesa-hetu). (V 33)
This is an important methodological point. Distinctions should not be postulated
on an ad hoc basis. A good philosophical theory tries to give a unified explanation
of a diversity of facts. Dividing the facts into different types for which there are
60
Philosophy in classical India
different explanations leaves explanatory gaps in the account. One should
introduce a distinction only if it corresponds to some natural division in the
phenomena under examination, and not simply to solve a problem in one’s
theory. To block the threatened infinite regress by saying that there are unproved
provers is to postulate a category simply for theoretical expediency, and not
because there is any independent ground for doing so.
Even if there is no independently motivated distinction between the
unproved and the proved, perhaps there is a well-founded distinction
between what is self-proved and what is proved by another. Everything
must be proved, but might not the means of knowing be self-proving? This
seems to have been the view of Gautama, the author of the Nyayasutra
(cf. NS 2.1.19). The proposal is, it seems, analogical. The sources of proof
are like sources of light. A source of light illuminates other things and at
the same time illuminates itself. Likewise, a source of proof proves other
things and at the same time proves itself (V 33). Nagarjuna is apparently
responding to the Nyayasutra view here. His response is to dismiss as
defective the assertion that a source of light illuminates itself! To say that
something is illuminated is to say that it ceases to be in the dark. But a
source of light is not illuminated, for it is never in the dark, and if it is not
illuminated, then it certainly is not self-illuminated. Nagarjuna’s point
perhaps is that an object is visible just in case light is coming from it, and
since this description is true of both illuminators and things illuminated,
there is no need to say that an illuminator must be illuminated in order to
be visible. There is a hint in this reply of a ‘grammatical’ basis to
Nagarjuna’s argument (the influence of grammar on Nagarjuna’s way of
arguing is much more apparent, however, in the argument we will consider
in the next section). The implication is the Agent and the Patient cannot be
identical when the verb is ‘illuminates’. The statement ‘A illuminates A’ is
not well formed. It is not well formed because ‘A illuminates B’ means
something like ‘the addition of A in the circumstances results in B’s ceasing
to be in the dark,’ and that implies that A is something that can be added
to a circumstance in which B is already present.
Nagarjuna, I think, employs a sophistical debating trick in this curious
argument. The light analogy uses a causative form pra-vkas, whose
meanings include both ‘to make bright, illuminate, irradiate’, and by
extension ‘to make clear, evident, manifest’. The point of the analogy is
most plausibly that a source of light makes itself evident in the very act of
making some other object evident, for the object could not be made evident
unless by a source of light. It is only in ‘quibbling’ on the meaning of a
word that Nagarjuna is led in this context to discuss the capacity of light
to illuminate itself. What Nagarjuna ought to discuss, but does not, is
whether a means of knowing can prove itself in the very act of proving
something else.18
Nagarjuna, fortunately, has another argument against the idea that the
means of knowing prove themselves. It is that if they prove themselves
Rationality, emptiness and the objective view
61
independently of any reference to what it is that they prove, then they cannot
be proof of anything (V 40–41). His point is easiest to see if we remember the
analogy between means of knowing and measuring instruments. How might
one go about ‘measuring’ a pair of scales, that is to say, checking that it is
correctly calibrated? The only way, it seems, is to test its performance against
things of known weight. The same is true of a means of knowing such as
observation. In order to check that my visual sense is working properly, I test
it by reading an optician’s chart. If I want to check that I know a method for
solving quadratic equations, I solve a few textbook problems and then check
in the back of the book that I have the right answers.
Nagarjuna is swift to point out that the method of proof by testing against
known cases cannot block the threatened regress (V 42–43). The reason is
simple: the test cases must have been established first. An attempt to block the
regress along these lines would result in the technical fault of ‘proving the
proved’ (siddhasadhana). The methods of proof under investigation are being
proved by comparing them to known cases, but those cases are known only
because proven by those methods of proof. So one is attempting to prove
something which must already have been proved, that the methods of proof in
question are adequate and reliable. Couldn’t one counter by pointing out that
the method of proof used to establish the test case is not the same as the method
of proof under scrutiny? I solve the test problems, but someone else prepared
the answers in the back of the book. For otherwise one would have the situation
which Nagarjuna ridicules when he asks whether a son can be produced by a
father and the father by that very son (V 49–50). But it is clear that the alternative
is not much better. For if objects have to proved by a means of knowing, and
the means by objects, one ends up proving nothing (V 45–48).
Nagarjuna sums up the entire argument in a triumphant final verse:
The means of knowing are not established by themselves or by one
another or by other means of knowing. Nor are they established by
the objects known, nor accidentally. Perception is not established by
that very perception, inference is not established by that very inference,
comparison is not established by that very comparison, and testimony
is not established by that very testimony. Nor are they established
by one another, i.e. perception by inference, comparison and
testimony, inference by perception, comparison and testimony,
comparison by perception, inference and testimony, and testimony
by perception, inference and comparison. Nor are perception,
inference, comparison and testimony established, respectively, by
another perception, another inference, another comparison and
another testimony. Nor are the means of knowing established by the
objects known, taken collectively or severally, included in their own
field or in those of the other means of knowing as well. Nor are they
established accidentally. Nor are they established by a combination
of the causes mentioned before, whatever their number: twenty, thirty,
62
Philosophy in classical India
forty or twenty-six. In these circumstances, your statement ‘Because
the objects known are to be apprehended through the means of
knowing, those things are known to exist as well as those means of
knowing’ is not valid. (V 51)
This is a fine example of Nagarjuna’s general dialectical strategy. The
strategy is to find a rule such as ‘A proves B only if A is itself proven’ or ‘x
can cause y only if x is itself caused’, and to make every possible application
of the rule onto the domain. What happens when one takes the set of objects
(including provers and things proven), and tries to apply the rule at every
point, is that one discovers one cannot do it. Nagarjuna then concludes that
the rule cannot be applied, and so that the concept it governs is empty.
Formally, the argument follows very similar contours to the argument
against causation. The domain is the class of propositions with proofs,
and the operation is the function ‘proof of x’. Here closure is the thesis
that every proposition has a proof – there are no unproved provers.
Transcendence then follows from the plausible contentions that there are
no proof loops, for this would lead to a vicious circle, and that there are
no infinitely long proof chains, for this would lead to a lack of grounding.
However, while I was willing to accept that Nagarjuna had uncovered an
incoherence in the ordinary concept of a cause, I do not think that he has
succeeded in anything comparable here. For the rule on which his argument
plays, that A proves B only if A is itself proven, is not actually a rule
governing the notion of a proof. Some reasons, reasons based on
observation, are defeasible – observation in itself provides one with reasons
to believe, unless one comes to have reasons to suspect it. So the correct
rule on proof by observation is: A proves B unless A is disproven. In other
words, proof by observation is non-monotonic.19 Perception as of a table
proves the existence of the table; perception as of a table, together with
evidence that one is hallucinating, does not. The Naiyayikas beginning
with Uddyotakara were very clear about this.20
What happens now to the fallacy of the unproven, on which Nagarjuna said
that his refutation depended? One needs to be able to draw a distinction between
purely extrapolative reasoning, inference from the observed to the unobserved,
and demonstration-based reasoning, a public setting out of one’s thesis with
supporting reasons and examples. Extrapolation rests on observation, and
observation can prove without being proved. The second rule is the right one
here, and there is no fallacy of the unproven. Demonstration, however, rests on
convincing one’s audience by citing reasons, and reasons are convincing only if
they are themselves proven. So the proper domain of the fallacy of the unproven
is only that of reasoning by demonstration. The crucial distinction one needs is
the one Dinnaga was later to codify and make explicit with his terms ‘inference
for oneself’ and ‘inference for others’.21 Once again we see that Nagarjuna’s
arguments are ones which would have been highly persuasive at the time, and
which are refuted only by distinctions clearly recognised much later.
Rationality, emptiness and the objective view
63
2.6 A NEW PARADOX OF MOTION
Nagarjuna’s celebrated argument against motion is interesting in its own
right, but it also functions as a paradigm for a pattern of argumentation he
thinks is widely applicable. Kamaleswar Bhattacharya22 has described the
argument as having a grammatical basis, because it exploits the Sanskrit
grammatical theory of ‘deep case’ or ‘thematic role’ (karaka). This is a theory
of the underlying semantic structure of sentences rather than their surface
grammar, and Nagarjuna’s argument might therefore be better described as
‘semantic’. In any case, the fact is that the argument is a general one, applicable
whenever one has statements with certain semantic properties. It does not
depend on particular properties of the concept of motion.
The Sanskrit theory of deep case is an approach to the analysis of sentences
which takes the verb to be the core of a sentence, around which nouns stand in
a variety of relationships. A verb denotes an activity or event, and each noun
in the sentence denotes a thematic causal factor connected with that event. In
the sentence ‘Sita cooks rice,’ for example, the activity of cooking has for its
Agent Sita and for its Patient rice. Agency is a thematic deep case relation, a
relation explicated in terms of Sita having a certain causal role with respect
to the activity. One suggestion is to think of the Agent as an affector, and the
Patient as the thing affected. The Sanskrit grammarians do not quite say this,
however, but prefer to say that the Agent is ‘what is independent’, and the
Patient is ‘what is most desired’ by the Agent. Other thematic roles capable of
being occupied include Instrument (‘that by means of which the Agent performs
the activity’), Target, Donor and Place (the ‘location’ of the activity).23
When there is a moving, there is also an Agent of moving, the ‘mover’,
defined as that which is moving, as well as a Patient of moving, the ‘being
moved over’, here identified with the Place of the moving. The paradox
Nagarjuna exposes is one to do with the nature of such definitions. A thing
has the properties by which it is defined, and the mover is defined to be that
which is now moving. Nothing in the past or in the future can satisfy this
definition, for nothing in the past or the future has the property of being now.
But a movement cannot be entirely in the present moment, for movement
requires duration. Similarly, the being moved over is defined to be the place
now being moved over, and that cannot be a position already moved over,
nor a position yet to be moved over. But a movement cannot be located in the
point between the already moved over and the yet to be moved over, for
movement requires displacement.
How indeed can it be said that a mover moves, when without a movement
there is no mover. (MK 2.9)
From the perspective of one who thinks that a mover moves, there would
be the consequence of a mover without movement. But of a mover there
is movement. (MK 2.10)
64
Philosophy in classical India
If a mover were said to move, there must be two movements, one by which
he is called a mover, and one by which the mover moves. (MK 2.11)
If without motion one cannot posit a mover, how can one posit a mover
standing still? (MK 2.16)
One does not stand still where one is moving, nor where one has moved
nor where one has yet to move. Moving, starting to move and ceasing to
move are the same. (MK 2.17)
The motion by means of which the mover is so-called is not the motion
by means of which he moves. He does not exist before that motion, so
what and where is the thing that moves? (MK 2.22)
The motion by means of which the mover is so-called is not different
from the motion by means of which he moves. There cannot be two
motions in a single mover. (MK 2.23)
So there is no motion, no mover and no place to be moved over. (MK 2.25)
Nagarjuna draws a distinction between the event of movement (gamana), or
movement at an instant, and the process of movement (gati), or movement over
a duration. A process of movement cannot be identified with any one event of
movement, nor with a succession of such events. For if there are two movements,
then there are two movers, and then there is here no single mover in a process
of motion. The same argument applies to any process. The seer sees the seen.
The ‘seer’ is, by definition, one who now sees. This is a definition nothing past
or future can satisfy, and yet seeing necessarily requires duration, for it is a
causal process extending between the seer and the thing seen (MK Chapter 3).
An obvious solution is simply to allow that a single enduring substance
can be the ‘mover’ in a succession of movements. One who wishes to say this
has to be able to maintain that an object can be identically present at different
times. For only an object present now can be that which now moves, and only
an object present in the immediately succeeding instant can be that which
moves at that instant. If these two movers are one and the same, it follows
that the mover is identically present at different times. That invites the objection
that the mover will be the substratum of contradictory properties. The present
movement ceases, and is replaced by the next movement in the sequence; so
the mover will both have the present movement and also not have it. But this
is impossible.
If it cannot be said that there is a movement without a mover, then how
will there be a mover without that movement? (MK 2.7)
Just as a mover does not move, so too a non-mover does not move.
Apart from the mover and the non-mover what third thing can move?
(MK 2.7)
Rationality, emptiness and the objective view
65
Later Nyaya writers found a general solution to the problem of contrary
temporal properties. Their solution is to introduce adverbial modifiers
(delimitors) on the property possession relation. An object as delimited by one
time can possess a property, even if the object as delimited by another time
does not.24 This solution was not apparent in Nagarjuna’s time. Indeed, the
problem of temporary intrinsic properties is a live one even today, where one
finds both promoters and detractors of the adverbial solution.25
Nagarjuna’s argument has naturally been studied in comparison with those
of Zeno.26 Here are Zeno’s arguments as reported by Aristotle:27
[The Dichotomy] The first asserts the non-existence of motion on the
ground that that which is in locomotion must arrive at the half-way stage
before it arrives at the goal.
[Achilles] The second . . . amounts to this, that in a race the quickest runner
can never overtake the slowest, since the pursuer must first reach the point
whence the pursued started, so the slower must always hold a lead.
[Arrow] Zeno argues fallaciously; for if, he says, everything always rests
when it is against what is equal, and what is in locomotion is always in
the now, the arrow in locomotion is motionless. But this is false, for time
is not composed of indivisible ‘nows’, no more than is any other magnitude.
[Stadium] The fourth is the one about equal bodies which move in opposite
directions past equal bodies in a stadium at equal speed, the one row
from the end of the stadium and the other from the middle – in which he
thinks it follows that half the time is equal to double.
The only one of Zeno’s arguments bearing any resemblance to that of
Nagarjuna is the flying arrow, although there is no general agreement in the
interpretation of either paradox. Jonathan Lear28 has proposed an interpretation
of the arrow under which there is a substantial agreement with my
interpretation of Nagarjuna. The force of the argument, according to Lear, is
that the present tense ‘is moving’ cannot be applied to a period of time, as a
period cannot be present, and yet nothing at an instant is moving.
Nagarjuna’s paradox of motion is a paradox of definition. The phrase
‘the mover’ is defined as ‘that which now moves’. It is, therefore, defined
only for the present time, and not for any past or future time. One cannot
truly say that the mover will move or that the mover has moved. One can
indeed assert again, a moment later, ‘the mover is moving’, but this new
utterance of ‘the mover’ is again defined only for its time of utterance.
There is nothing in virtue of which one can say that the denotation of the
previous utterance is the same as the denotation of this one: whence
Nagarjuna’s claim that if there are two movements, there must be two
movers. Movement, however, requires a duration, and so one can never say
that a single thing, the mover, is moving.
66
Philosophy in classical India
Consider again the statement ‘the mover will move.’ Nagarjuna’s argument
depends on the claim that, because the phrase ‘the mover’ is not defined at
future times, this statement, uttered in the present, cannot be true. However,
‘the mover’ is defined in the present, and what is to stop us from asserting of
some present thing that it will be moving in the future? What stops us is the
existence of truth-value links between statements in different tenses uttered at
different times. The statement ‘a will be F’ is now true just in case the statement
‘a is F’ will be true. So the statement ‘the mover will move’ is now true just in
case the statement ‘the mover is moving’ will be true. But that future statement
can never be true, because the description ‘the mover’ is not defined at any
future time (and a future utterance of ‘the mover’ is an utterance of a different
description, defined only in the future).
The puzzle arises because we are dealing with descriptions of an unusual
type, ones whose matrix is an indexical property – the property of being the
Agent of a movement occurring now. Many definite descriptions are indeed
like this, for instance ‘the Prime Minister’, which is really an abbreviation for
‘the current Prime Minister’. Clearly, in truth-value links of the sort I have
just described, we have to take into account this indexicality in the description.
The statement ‘The current Prime Minister will resign’ is true just in case the
future statement ‘The past Prime Minister has resigned’ will be true. When
we make explicit the shifting value of the temporal index, the paradox
disappears. For the truth-value link we are after is this one: the statement
‘The present mover will move’ is true just in case the statement ‘The past
mover is moving’ will be true. Such truth-value links show how the sentence
‘the mover will move’ can after all be true.
2.7 SELF-REFUTATION
‘With relief, with humiliation, with terror, he understood that he too was a
mere appearance, dreamt by another.’ Thus ends a story by Jorge Luis Borges
entitled ‘The Circular Ruins’.29 It is a story about a magician who sets out to
dream into reality another man, and who completes his task only to discover
that he himself is nothing but a dream. According to Nagarjuna when one
achieves an objective view of one’s conceptions, what one finds is that all
conception is empty. Does that mean that the objective view is empty too,
that the concept of emptiness is as empty of content as the concepts it describes?
Does Nagarjuna’s thesis defeat itself?. The charge was one vigorously pressed
by Nagarjuna’s opponents, and in order to respond to it, he wrote a new
book, his Reply to Critics. This book begins with a formulation of the selfrefutation charge:
If a self-standing nature of things, whatever they may be, exists nowhere,
your statement must lack a self-standing nature. It is not, therefore, in a
position to deny the self-standing nature of things. (V 1)
Rationality, emptiness and the objective view
67
Let us recall what the emptiness thesis claims. It claims that no thesis or
theory formulated in terms of the categories and concepts of the commonsense
scheme has objective content, because a presupposition of that conceptual
scheme, that there are self-standing objects, is false. The emptiness thesis
itself, however, is not a thesis within the common-sense scheme, but a thesis
about it. It does not itself presuppose that there are self-standing objects.
There appears to be a straightforward non sequitur in the self-refutation charge,
as Nagarjuna himself points out:
This statement of mine, though lacking a self-standing nature because
dependently originated, is engaged in the task of establishing the nature
of things as lacking a self-standing nature. In these circumstances, your
statement is not proper. (V 22)
Similarly, when Nagarjuna famously claims to have no ‘doctrine’ (pratijña)
of his own (V 29), he might simply be using the term ‘doctrine’ to mean a
thesis resting on the same presuppositions as the common-sense scheme, and
it is quite evident that the emptiness thesis is not a ‘doctrine’ in that sense.30
Indeed, Nagarjuna sometimes speaks as if he has a viable alternative ontology
on offer, an ontology consistent with the teachings of the Buddha, in which
entities exist only in relations of dependent origination with one another and
lack any self-standing nature. The world, in this alternative ontology, is rather
like a net, where entities are merely the knots in interlocking ropes of
dependent origination, acquiring whatever capacities they have in virtue of
their relative position in the whole network and not in virtue of having intrinsic
properties (V 22).
This sits ill, however, with the concept scepticism Nagarjuna also avows.31
If common sense is the only possibility for an objectively well-grounded
conceptual scheme, and if even common sense fails, then no conception can
be well grounded. The emptiness thesis belongs to an ungrounded, dream-like
discourse, and within that dream-discourse other, embedded dreams are
described, the dreams that are common-sense theories. Nagarjuna exploits a
comparable literary device, the idea of a magic trick within a magic trick:
Suppose a magic man created by a magician should obstruct another
magic man created by his own magic and occupied by something . . .
[then] the magic man who is obstructed is void, and he who obstructs
is also void. In like manner, a negation of the intrinsic nature of all
things by my statement is possible, even though this statement is void.
(V 23)
Another sort of conceptual ascent has occurred here. It is like a novel the
narrator of which is a literary theorist who declares that all novels are
merely empty fictions. Within the novel, the narrator’s declaration has
the desired effect of making the other characters understand better the
68
Philosophy in classical India
nature of fictional discourse. This is so even though the narrator’s statement
itself is merely an empty fiction. Nagarjuna would like to explain the
therapeutic efficacy of his own teaching the same way. His denial that
things have self-standing nature can make one see that one’s experiences
are dream-like, empty, even though that denial is only dream-like too (V
23–28).
It might be argued that Nagarjuna’s position is self-refuting because it is
self-referential. For the statement ‘This statement is empty’ is, if true, then
empty and so not true, and, if empty, then true and so not empty. The only
remaining possibility is that the statement is false. If it is false, then it is not
empty, and Nagarjuna is wrong to say that the emptiness thesis is itself
empty. Nagarjuna’s point, however, is that one can agree that the emptiness
thesis is empty without agreeing that it is self-referential. Conception is like
a hierarchy of dreams within dreams within dreams, carried on indefinitely.
Whenever we take a step back to a more objective view, we ascend a level
in this hierarchy, and realise that our conceptions at the previous level were
themselves all empty. And this thought, that all those conceptions are empty,
is itself recognised as another empty thought when we take the next step
through the hierarchy of empty conceptions. So the emptiness thesis is
formulated at each level in the hierarchy, but recognised as itself empty in
the next level up. It never applies to itself.
Nagarjuna gives up on the idea that conception is ‘supported’ by the
world. Conception is always a dream within a dream. The real problem
with the Madhyamaka method is that it is piecemeal. All it can show is
that specific concepts, particularly the concepts of the common-sense
scheme, are dreamlike, ungrounded, empty. What it does not prove is
the emptiness of all concepts, and especially those concepts, such as
emptiness itself, which do not presuppose that there are self-standing
objects. Nagarjuna may have shown that the concepts of common sense
have false presuppositions; what he has not shown is that the same is
true of any possible system of concepts. Perhaps then there is still another
use of reason, a use neither to codify common sense (Chapter 1) nor to
leap-frog out of it (Chapter 2), but to construct ‘sophisticated’ or ‘scientific’
(non-common-sensical) theories of the world. After examining one such
theory, Vaisesika metaphysics (Chapter 3), we will be in a position to see
how the Buddhist challenge is reconfigured in the work of Dinnaga
(Chapter 4).
FURTHER READING
Texts
Nagarjuna c. AD 150, Mulamadhyamakakarika (MK, The Middle Stanzas).
Nagarjuna, Vigrahavyavartani (V, Reply to Critics).
Candrakirti c. AD 600, Prasannapada (P).
Rationality, emptiness and the objective view
69
Emptiness (2.1–2)
1
David Seyfort Ruegg, The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of
Philosophy in India (Wiesbaden: Otto Harrassowitz, 1981).
2
C.W. Huntington, The Emptiness of Emptiness: An Introduction
to Early Indian Madhyamaka (Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 1989).
3
David Burton, Emptiness Appraised: A Critical Study of Nagarjuna’s
Philosophy (London: Curzon Press, 1999).
The four options, the dialectical method (2.3)
1
Richard H. Robinson, ‘Some Logical Aspects of Nagarjuna’s System,’
Philosophy East and West 6 (1957), pp. 291–308.
2
David Seyfort Ruegg, ‘The Uses of the Four Positions of the Catuskoti
and the Problem of the Description of Reality in Mahayana Buddhism,’ Journal
of Indian Philosophy 5 (1977), pp. 1–71.
3
Brian Galloway, ‘Some Logical Issues in Madhyamaka Thought,’
Journal of Indian Philosophy 17 (1989), pp. 1–35.
4
Frank Hoffman, ‘Rationality in Early Buddhist Four-Fold Logic,’
Journal of Indian Philosophy 10 (1982), pp. 309–337.
5
Vijay Bharadwaja, ‘Rationality, Argumentation and Philosophical
Embarrassment: A Study of Four Logical Alternatives (catuskoti) in Buddhist
Logic,’ Philosophy East and West 34 (1984), pp. 303–319; reprinted in his
Form and Validity in Indian Logic (Shimla: Indian Institute for Advanced
Study, 1990), Chapter 4.
Causation, proof, motion (2.4–6)
1
Richard Hayes, ‘Nagarjuna’s Appeal,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy
22 (1994), pp. 299–378.
2
Bimal Krishna Matilal, Perception (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986),
Chapter 2.
3
Mark Siderits, ‘Nagarjuna as Anti-Realist,’ Journal of Indian
Philosophy 16 (1988), pp. 311–325.
4
Kamaleswar Bhattacharya, ‘Nagarjuna’s Arguments against Motion:
Their Grammatical Basis,’ in G. Bhattacharya et al. eds., A Corpus of Indian
Studies: Essays in Honour of Professor Gaurinath Sastri (Calcutta: Sanskrit
Pustak Bhandar, 1980), pp. 85–95.
5
Kamaleswar Bhattacharya, ‘The Grammatical Basis of Nagarjuna’s
Arguments: Some Further Considerations,’ Indologica Taurinensia, 8–9 (1980–
1), pp. 35–43.
6
George Cardona, ‘A Path Still Taken: Some Early Indian Arguments
Concerning Time,’ Journal of the American Oriental Society 111.3 (1991),
pp. 445–464.
70
Philosophy in classical India
Self-refutation (2.7)
1
Richard Robinson, ‘Did Nagarjuna Really Refute All Philosophical
Views?’ Philosophy East and West 22 (1972), pp. 325–331.
2
David Seyfort Ruegg, ‘Does the Madhyamika Have a Thesis and
Philosophical Position?’ in B. K. Matilal and R. D. G. Evans eds., Buddhist
Logic and Epistemology: Studies in the Buddhist Analysis of Inference and
Language (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1982), pp. 229–238.
3
Paul Sagal, ‘Nagarjuna’s Paradox,’ American Philosophical Quarterly
29.1 (1992), pp. 79–85.
3 The rational basis of
metaphysics
3.1 ORDER IN NATURE
Indian philosophical literature abounds with lists, enumerations, catalogues
and classifications. There are lists of the different means of knowing, of the
categories of knowable things, of the variety of psychological and physical
constituents of a person, and, generally, of the modes, realms and states of
existence. Our interest is in the rationale behind these classifications. What
function do the classifications serve? What are the criteria underpinning them?
Wilhelm Halbfass1 says that these lists answer ‘the question of being’ in India,
so that a list of the different kinds of being tells us what it is to ‘be’. Taxonomies
are cheap – there are many ways of dividing objects into groups – and the
choice of one particular way of dividing from the others is the selection of an
ontology. One approach to the Indian categories, indeed the traditional
approach, has therefore been to explore the reasons for choosing one way of
classifying rather than another. I think a fresh approach is needed. Remembering
that the classifications are given rather than chosen for all but the original
compilers of the sutra-texts (and perhaps not even for them), the real interest
is in the methods of rationalisation – how a predetermined list is made sense
of, and in the methods of revision – how the list is modified in accordance
with the principles by which it is rationalised.
My focus in this chapter is on the ontology of the Vaisesika school, a
school and a set of thinkers predisposed towards the study of the metaphysical
structure of the natural world. I will examine too the logical theory that is
integral to this ontology, as it was formulated and developed by the logicians
of Navya-Nyaya. I want to present a stark and beautiful theory, a theory
whose importance has not been fully appreciated by scholars who have charted
the contours of Indian philosophical thought. The theory I have in mind emerges
as a rationalisation of the early Vaisesika theory of the categories. My
contention is that three revisionary Vaisesika thinkers – Bhasarvajña (c. AD
950), Udayana (c. AD 1050) and Raghunatha (c. AD 1500) – saw that there is
a graph-theoretic basis to the Vaisesika notion of a category. If I am right,
then an old idea about Indian philosophy must be given up as a dogma – the
72
Philosophy in classical India
idea that mathematical concepts play no part in Indian philosophical thought
about order in the natural world.
3.2 THE CATEGORIAL HIERARCHY
A theory of ‘category’ is a theory about the notion of a type of thing. When
Gilbert Ryle2 accused Descartes of making a ‘category mistake’ in treating
the mind as if it were a thing of the same type as the body, he appealed to a
principle about categories – that organisations, structures and arrangements
are different in kind from the objects organised, structured or arranged. A
social organisation is not simply another thing of the same type of thing as
the people who belong to it; and, by the same token, neither is a class a thing
of the same kind as its members, or a property the same kind of thing as its
instantiations. Modern ontologies usually take the kinds of thing to be objects,
events and classes; some add states, properties and tropes.
Let us review the contours of the traditional Vaisesika account. Classical
Vaisesika lists six kinds of thing: substance, quality, motion, universal,
individuator, inherence. Later Vaisesika adds a seventh: absence. The basic
stuff of the cosmos in the Vaisesika world-view is atomic. Atoms are
uncreatable, indestructible, non-compound substances. Atoms can coalesce
into composite substances and can move. Indeed, the only changes in this
cosmos are changes in the arrangement, properties and positions of the
atoms. Creation is a matter of coalescing, destruction of breaking (and even
God does not create the cosmos ab nihilo, but only ‘shapes’ it, as a potter
shapes clay into a pot). A compound substance is a whole, composed out of,
and inhering simultaneously in each of, its parts. These substances are
individuated by the type and organisation of their parts. A ‘quality’ in
classical Vaisesika is a property-particular – for example, a particular shade
of blue colour or a distinct flavour (what one would now call a ‘thin’
property). Qualities inhere in substances and in nothing other than
substances. A ‘motion’ is another sort of particular; it too inheres in a
substance and in nothing but a substance. Universals inhere in substances,
qualities and motions. A universal inheres simultaneously in more than one,
but has nothing inhering in it. Lastly, the ‘individuator’ (visesa) is a
distinctive and eponymous component in classical Vaisesika ontology. An
individuator inheres in and is unique to a particular atom: it is that by which
the atomic, partless substances are individuated.3
Two principles lie at the heart of the Vaisesika system: a principle of identity
and a principle of change. The Vaisesika principle of change is this: a becomes
b iff the parts of a rearrange (perhaps with loss or gain) into the parts of b.
‘Motion’ is that in virtue of which the parts rearrange or stay together. There
are basic or partless parts, the atoms, which, precisely because they have no
parts, are incapable of becoming anything else. They move about, but are
eternal and indestructible. The Vaisesika principle of identity is this: a = b iff
the parts of a are numerically identical to and in the same arrangement as the
The rational basis of metaphysics
73
parts of b. ‘Quality’ is that in virtue of which the parts are numerically identical
or different. Atoms, precisely because they are partless, require a different
principle of identity: atoms are distinct iff they have distinct individuators.
Universals are limits on the degree of possible difference and change. One
thing cannot change into another thing of an entirely different sort (a mouse
into a mustard seed). One thing a can become another thing b iff the same
universal resides in both a and b, that is, if a and b are of the same sort (as
Udayana4 puts it, universals regulate causality).
This is the motivation for there being six ‘types’ of thing (substances,
qualities, motions, universals, individuators, inherence). The problem is to
find a proper philosophical basis for the notion of a ‘type’ of thing thus appealed
to. In his Laksanavali, Udayana reconstructs the categories in a new way, a
way which I shall claim explicates the notion of a type graphtheoretically.
What is a graph? It is a simple son of relational structure, consisting of a set
of nodes or vertices, and a set of edges (an edge being defined as a pair of
nodes). A graph is ‘directed’ if the edges have a direction. Graphs, like many
other mathematical structures, are realised in natural phenomena. A striking
example is molecular structure: it is because the structure of a molecule is a
graph that one can use a graph to depict one:
H–O–H
The implicit structure of the Vaisesika ontology is that of a directed graph.
The inherence relation connects things in the ontology in inheror–inheree
pairings. So the substances, qualities, motions, universals and individuators
are represented as the nodes of a graph whose set of edges represent the
inherence relation. A fragment of the graph might look like this:
This graph represents the following state of affairs: a universal U inheres in a
quality Q which inheres in a substance S. That substance is a dyad composed
of two atoms in which it inheres, and each of which has inhering in it an
individuator I. The structure of the world is a directed graph.
The nodes in a graph can be classified according to the number of edges
terminating in them, and the number of edges starting from them: so the
74
Philosophy in classical India
valency of a node in a directed graph is an ordered pair of integers (n, m).
What Udayana saw in the Laksanavali is that things of different types in the
Vaisesika ontology correspond to nodes of different valencies. His brilliant
idea is to use the idea of valency to define the categories of substance, quality,
motion, universal and individuator. He begins with a classification of the
categories into the four valency-groups (+, +), (+, 0), (0, +) and (0, 0):5
5
6
7
8
Non-eternal [= compound] substance, quality, motion, universal, and
individuator inhere.
Eternal [i.e. atomic] substance, inherence, and absence lack the property
of inhering.
Substance, quality, and motion are inhered in.
Universal, individuator, inherence, and absence have nothing inhering in
them.
In particular then, atoms have valency (+, 0), universals and individuators
have valency (0, +), while compound substances, qualities and motions have
valency (+, +).
Notice that Udayana says that the inherence relation itself has a valency,
(0, 0). We should not take this to mean that the inherence relation is to be
represented by a node disconnected from the rest of the graph, but rather that
it does not correspond to any node in the graph at all. The first and most
fundamental graph-theoretic type distinction is the distinction between a node
and an edge, and the inherence relation is represented in a graph by the set of
edges, not by any node. The set of edges represents the extension of the inherence
relation.
If the categories are to be distinguished from one another according to the
valency of the nodes in that graph which is isomorphic to the world of things,
then further specification is needed. The distinction between universals and
individuators is simple: an individuator has valency (0, 1) while a universal
has valency (0, m), with m > 1:
202
203
A universal has nothing inhering in it, inheres, and is co-located with
every difference.
Individuators lack the property of being inhered in, inhere, and lack
the property of inhering by being co-located with every difference.
Udayana’s phrase ‘co-located with every difference’ is a technical device for
expressing the idea that a universal inheres in more than one. For if an inheror
inheres in exactly one thing x, then all other things are loci of differencefromx, and the inheror is not co-located with difference-from-x. However, if the
inheror inheres in two things x andy, then difference-from-x is located in y
and difference-from-y is located in x, and the inheror is co-located with both
differences. So something co-located with every difference-from each of the
things in which it inheres is necessarily located in more than one thing. Notice
The rational basis of metaphysics
75
that in classical Vaisesika, individuators are said to have no universals inhering
in them precisely because they are fundamental units of individuation, having
nothing in common with one another.
Any node with valency (0, m) with m > 1 is now to be called a ‘universal’,
and any node with valency (0, 1) is to be called an ‘individuator’:
The valency of atoms is different from that of qualities or motions, but we
still need a general definition of substance, covering both atomic and compound
substances. For compound substances, like universals, but unlike atoms, inhere
in other things (their parts). Udayana in fact offers four definitions, of which
the first three repeat older definitions. The fourth definition, however, is
completely original:
9 A substance is not a substratum of absence of quality.
10 Or, it belongs to such a kind as inheres in what is incorporeal, inheres in
what is not incorporeal and does not inhere in what inheres in what is not
corporeal.
11 Or, it belongs to such a kind as inheres in space and in a locus, but not in
smell.
12 Or, it is that in which inheres that in which inheres that which inheres.
The first of these definitions is the classical one in Vaisesika6 – a substance is
that which possesses qualities. Udayana returns to this definition in his famous,
but conservative commentary, the Kiranavali. He thinks of replacing it in the
more experimental Laksanavali with a definition that makes no reference to
any other category and indeed is phrased entirely in terms of the notion of
inherence: a substance is ‘that in which inheres that in which inheres that
which inheres’. In other words, a substance is to be represented by a node
such as this:
76
Philosophy in classical India
The point of the definition is that a substance possesses qualities, and qualities
possess universals, and nothing else in the ontology possesses something which
possesses something. For universals and individuators possess nothing, while
qualities and motions possess universals and nothing else.
Let us define a ‘path’ between one node and another in the obvious way:
there is a path from node x to node w if there is a sequence of nodes <x, y, . .
., w> such that there is an edge from x to y, an edge from y to z, . . ., an edge
from v to w.7 Define the ‘length’ of a path as the number of edges between the
first and the last node. Udayana’s definition of a substance is now: a node is a
substance iff there is a path at least of length 2 leading to it. Substances inhere
in their parts; so the definition entails that every part of a substance is a
substance.
The classical conception of qualities and motions makes them almost
identical: they both inhere only in substances, and they both are inhered in
only by universals.8 Prasastapada’s remark9 that the qualities other than
contact, breaking, number and separateness ‘inhere in one thing at a time’
should not be construed as implying that they inhere in only one thing, but
only that this group of qualities are monadic (non-relational) properties. These
features are enough to distinguish qualities and motions from all else: from
universals and individuators (which do not have anything inhering in them),
and from substances (which are inhered in by things that are themselves inhered
in). It explains too why qualities cannot inhere in qualities – if they did then
they would be equivalent graph-theoretically to substances.
What is difficult is to find any principled way to distinguish between qualities
and motions. There was indeed a persistent revisionary pressure to assimilate
these two categories. Bhasarvajña10 heads the revisionary move, stating
unequivocally that motions should be treated as qualities because, like qualities,
they reside in substances and possess universals. From a graphtheoretic
perspective, this revision is well motivated: qualities and motions are
represented by nodes of the same valency, and so are things of the same type.
Udayana chooses the harder way, and tries to formulate definitions that will
accommodate the distinction. The classical Vaisesika idea11 that motions are
what cause substances to come into contact with one another is reflected in
his definitions:
The rational basis of metaphysics
77
126 A quality belongs to such a kind as inheres in both contact and noncontact, and does not inhere in the non-inherent cause of that sort of
contact which does not result from contact.
190 A motion belongs to such a kind as inheres in the non-inherent cause of
contact and does not inhere in contact.
These definitions introduce two new relations, contact and causation,
neither of which is explicable in terms of inherence nor belongs to the
graph-theoretic interpretation of the categories. The very success of that
interpretation gives a rationale to the revisionary pressure. Finding a pattern
into which all but a few items of some phenomenon fit grounds a presumption
that those items are in some way discrepant. This is a general principle of
scientific and rational inquiry (we will encounter it again in Chapter 6.6),
and we can see it has been used by Bhasarvajña to motivate revisions in
the classical Vaisesika theory. Rationality appears here in the form of
principled revision.12
3.3 THE STRUCTURE OF THE WORLD
The definitions of the categories generate constraints on permissible graphs.
What is the simplest solution to those constraints (the simplest possible
world)? Any path must have a beginning and an end. Only atoms can end
paths, and only universals and individuators can begin them. A graph
consisting of a single path, beginning with an individuator and ending in
an atom (I´S) is not well formed, however, because a substance must be
the end of a path of length at least 2. So the atom, besides its individuator,
must have inhering in it a quality, and in that quality a universal. However,
a universal must inhere in at least two things, so there must be a second
quality, a second atom and a second individuator. The simplest well-formed
graph is therefore:
In accordance with the definitions, we can identify this as a metaphysical
structure of the form:
Let us consider in this context the merits of another proposed revision
to the classical system. The two great revisionaries are Bhasarvajña
and Raghunatha. I have already mentioned one revision: the assimilation
of motions and qualities to a single category. Another candidate for
revision must surely be the category of individuator. Raghunatha13 indeed
argues that individuators should be eliminated, on the ground that since
the old school has to allow the self-individuation of the individuators,
78
Philosophy in classical India
one might just as well permit the self-individuation of atoms. In other
words, the charge is one of redundancy, the introduction of individuators
only postponing the necessity for self-individuation. And graphtheoretically it is clear that the individuators can be deleted from a
graph without altering its connectedness, for they are merely inert nodes
adorning each atom.
There is still more structure in the Vaisesika graph. Intuitively the ontology
‘descends’ from a top level of universals, down through the qualitiescummotions and compound substances, on through the simpler substances,
and ending at a bottom level of atoms. This intuition can be made more
precise. Notice first that there are no closed cycles in the Vaisesika graph. A
cycle is a directed self-terminating path <x, y, z, . . ., x>. The members of a
cycle must have valency (+, +). So no universal or individuator can be a
member of a cycle, because neither has anything inhering in it. No quality or
motion can be a member of a cycle, because only universals inhere in qualities
and motions, and there are no universals in a cycle. No atomic substance can
be a member of a cycle, because atoms inhere in nothing. That leaves only
cycles of compound substances. But there can be cycles of substances only if a
substance can have as a part something of which it is a part and so (if the
part-of relation is transitive) be a part of itself.
If there are no cycles then paths have determinate lengths. So let us now
define the ‘level’ of a node as the length of the longest path leading to it.
Universals and individuators all belong in level 0 – they are not inherees.
Nothing other than universals and individuators are in level 0 – substances,
qualities and motions are inherees. Level 1 is the level of all and only qualities
and motions – all are inhered in by universals and universals alone. Further,
it follows from the definition of Udayana that substances are in level 2 or
below. Indeed, the levels from 2 down are populated by substances and
substances alone. Every path comes to an end with some atomic substance.
The level of a node is the length of the longest path to it, but there will in
general be shorter paths too. Every substance has some universals inhering in
it, and every atomic substance has its own private individuator.
The rational basis of metaphysics
79
Musashi Tachikawa14 has aptly compared the structure of the world in
Vaisesika metaphysics with a mobile hanging from the ceiling. We must
remember, however, that the whole branching graph of substances is ‘suspended’
by threads running down from the top level of universals and individuators to
each and every substance in the lower levels. So another comparison would
be with a group of marionettes: the bodies of the puppets are the branching
structures of substances, and the strings will be the threads running up to the
level of universals and individuators.
3.4 THE TAXONOMY OF NATURAL KINDS
Udayana in the Kiranavali15 lists six specific constraints on the category
of universals. They are (1) that a universal not reside in fewer than two
things; (2) that no two universals reside in exactly the same things; (3) that
no two universals are ‘crosscutting,’ partially overlapping one another;
(4) that no universal lead to an infinite regress; (5) that no universal
undermine the very nature of the entity in which it resides; and (6) that no
universal be incapable of being related to the things in which it purports
to reside. These conditions can be interpreted graph-theoretically. The
function of constraints (4), (5) and (6) is to stop properties of the graph
becoming nodes in the graph. There can be no universal *inherencehood
(i.e. that which all the edges have in common), because the edges of a
graph are not nodes. So *inherencehood is ruled out by (6). There can be
no universal *individuatorhood (i.e. that which all the individuators have
in common), because an individuator by its very nature has nothing in
common with anything else. So *individuatorhood is ruled out by (5). No
universal can inhere in other universals, for, were this to occur, then that
universal could have further universals inhering in it, and so on ad infinitum.
So *universalhood and any other such merely ostensible property (upadhi)
of universals are ruled out by (4). Neither is one permitted to generate a
regress by introducing a node n1 connected to every other node, then a
second node n2 connected to every other node including n1, and so on ad
infinitum.
The first three constraints are conditions on the connectedness of the graph.
We have encountered the first already, that nodes representing universals
80
Philosophy in classical India
must have an ‘out-valency’ greater than one – that is the feature of their
valency which distinguishes them from individuators. Constraints (2) and (3),
however, are substantive and new. Constraint (2) is a uniqueness condition:
for any given set of nodes, there is at most one universal node connected to
each and every member. So graphs like this are ruled out:
This graph represents a situation in which two universals (the upper left and
lower right corners) reside in exactly the same pair of things (the upper right
and lower left corners). The general effect of (2) is to rule out reduplication
within the graph (and so within nature). It is an Occam’s razor on nodes
representing universals, a block on there being two nodes having exactly the
same edges with other nodes. We will see that the same principle of nonreduplication is extended to other types of node as well.
The third constraint rules out crosscutting among universals, that is, the
situation in which two universals reside jointly in some things and individually
in others. There is a considerable modern discussion of the thesis that crosscutting systems of categories cannot explain genuine natural kinds.16 This is
the typical sort of graph the condition rules out:
It is clear that the ‘no crosscutting’ condition induces a hierarchy in the
domain of universals. The nodes in level 0 are ordered within the level into
hierarchical groupings (each individuator being a hierarchy unto itself).
Vaisesika writers talk of the universals as being arranged in a ‘higher–lower’
relationship (VS 1.2.3). They posit the existence of a unique ‘highest’ universal
– called ‘being’ bhava or ‘existentness’ satta (VS 1.2.18) – a universal that
stands as higher in the higher–lower relationship with every universal other
than itself,17 and they add that other universals stand in the relationship as
higher to some universals and as lower to others (VS 1.2.5). The only exceptions
are the ‘ultimate species’ (antya visesa), said never to stand as higher, in the
higher–lower relationship, to any other universal (VS 1.2.6).
Ian Hacking18 defines a scientific taxonomy as a class of entities C and a
transitive asymmetric relation K, such that: (i) C has a head, a member of the
class that does not stand in relation K to any other member, but such that
every other member stands in this relation to it; and (ii) every member except
the head stands in the relation K to some other member. He adds that such
taxonomies sometimes terminate in a bedrock of categories that cannot be
The rational basis of metaphysics
81
further subdivided. It is clear that the Vaisesika theory satisfies this definition
of a scientific taxonomy. The class of universals is the domain, the higher–
lower relationship is a transitive and asymmetric relation, the universal
existentness is a head member, and the ultimate species constitute a bedrock.
This lends a degree of support to Bimal Matilal’s conjecture that the Vaisesika
universals are comparable to natural kinds.19
The thesis that natural taxonomies cannot be crosscutting, while certainly
the majority view, is not universally accepted. One author20 dissents on the
grounds that the different colours red and blue are to be found in the same
object, a vase painted both red and blue. The traditional Vaisesika reply, that
red and blue merge in the vase to form a single, new colour, is rather less
convincing than the Buddhist analysis of the vase into parts, some red and
some blue. Another21 argues that the ban on crosscutting would lead to a
catastrophic diminution in the number of universals, for the univeral relations
far and near crosscut all other universals. A different argument rests on the
standard, but curious, unwillingness to distinguish between artifact kinds and
natural kinds, from which it follows that vase and gold crosscut in a golden
vase. Rather more convincing is an example from the modern literature, the
kinds parasite and insect, and with it the suggestion that scientific taxonomies
are interest relative.22
There is one further rule on the connectivity of the graph (in fact, it is a
consequence of Udayana’s first condition). This is the rule that no universal
can be ‘unexampled’ (aprasiddha), inherent in nothing. The underlying principle
is that every node must be connected to at least one other node – there can be
no isolated nodes. And this, I think, is only an instance of a still more general
rule, that the graph forms one connected whole, and does not factorise into
separate and unconnected parts. The graph represents the world, and the
world is a single, connected unity.
Are there conjunctive and disjunctive universals? Suppose that the set of
nodes to which the nodes x and y have edges is equal to the set of nodes to
which another node z has edges. Then z = x ∨ y (z is the disjunction of x and
y; the identity follows from Udayana’s second condition). Conversely, if z is a
node with edges to just those nodes to which x and y both have edges, then z
= x ^ y (z is the conjunction of x and y). Daniel Ingalls23 says that NavyaNyaya do not have general terms for logical sum and logical product, and
the graph-theoretic explanation is that one cannot generate disjunctive and
conjunctive nodes at will. In particular, we can prove from the ‘uniqueness’,
‘exampled’ and ‘no crosscutting’ conditions that there are no conjunctive
universals in the Vaisesika graph. For, by ‘no crosscutting’, the conjunction of
two universals must be either empty (a possibility ruled out by the ‘exampled’
condition) or, if non-empty, then coextensive with and so (by ‘uniqueness’)
identical to one of the conjuncts. We might admit disjunctive universals,
however, when two disjuncts are disjoint. For then the disjunction would be a
universal higher than either. There are indeed Sanskrit technical terms (‘ubhaya’
and ‘anyatara’) with the logical force of this disjunction.
82
Philosophy in classical India
3.5 ABSENCE AS A TYPE OF ENTITY
‘Absence’ in Vaisesika is not the same as non-existence. Fictional characters,
dream-objects and hallucinations are non-existent: they do not exist as it
were by nature (cf. Chapter 2). It would be an absurdity to go in search of
Hamlet in order to find out whether he really exists or not – his non-existence
is not a merely contingent lack in the world of things. The absence of water
on the moon, on the other hand, is a contingent and concrete fact; so too is
the absence of colour in my cheeks. Notice the role of the phrases ‘of water’,
‘of colour’ here: an absence has an absentee – that which the absence is an
absence of. It also has a location (e.g. the moon, my cheeks), and a time. So
the proposal is to reparse the sentence ‘x does not occur in y at time t’ as ‘an
absence-of-x occurs in y at t ’. For it is often the case that the absence of
something somewhere is more salient than any fact about what is present
there (Figure 3.1).
There is one relatively straightforward way to interpret the idea of absence
graph-theoretically. If x does not inhere in y, then there is no edge (x, y) in the
graph. Now for every graph, there is a dual graph. The dual has the same
nodes as the original graph, but has an edge between two nodes just in case
the original does not. So the dual graph does have an edge (x, y). Following
this idea, one would be led to say that absences are things of a different type
from any presence because they are edges in the dual graph, rather than edges
or nodes in the original.
For various reasons, the Vaisesika do not consider this to be an adequate
explanation of the category. One problem is that it makes absences more like
relations than ‘things’, and this does not keep to the spirit of the Vaisesika
idea that absences are entities. In fact, absences do display much relation-like
behaviour – after all, absence is always the absence of x in y. Another objection,
however, is if absence is a new category, its introduction should result in an
extension of the original graph, and not in the introduction of a new graph,
let alone a graph completely disconnected from the original. For the connected
world of things ought not be represented by a pair of disconnected graphs. A
third problem arises if we admit something called ‘unpervaded occurrence’,
as we will see in the next section.
The Vaisesika idea is to represent absences as nodes, related in new ways
to the nodes of the original graph. Here is how to do it. For each unconnected
pair of nodes (x, y), create a new node x’ in the original graph. This new
node will have edges to x and to y, but they will be edges of two new types.
The edge (x’, x) is an edge belonging to the extension of the absentee–
absence (pratiyogita) relation, which I shall signify as ‘@ ’. This represents
the relation between an absence and what the absence is of. The edge (x’, y)
is an edge belonging to the extension of the ‘absential special relation’
(abhaviyasvarupa-sambandha), signified here by ‘ Î ’. This represents the
occurrence relation between an absence and its location. The relation between
an absence and its location is clearly not the same as the relation between a
The rational basis of metaphysics
83
media rights not available
Figure 3.1 René Magritte: ‘Man with a Newspaper’. (Copyright © 2000 Tate, all rights
reserved.)
84
Philosophy in classical India
presence and its location (inherence, contact), for it is clear that, when a
person is absent from a room, his absence is not in the room in the same sense
that the other things in the room are.
These new nodes belong in a domain outside the system of levels, for they
inhere in nothing and nothing inheres in them (inherence, and the whole
system of levels, is a structure on presences). The modified graph is instead a
concatenation of the original graph of nodes and edges with a new structure
of ‘absential nodes’ and ‘absential edges’.
Vaisesika theory of absence draws a type distinction between simple absence
(atyantabhava) and difference (anyonyabhava). Difference is the absence of a
relation of identity between two things. Here ‘x ≠ y’ is paraphrased as ‘a
difference-from y occurs in x’. Graph-theoretically, the distinction between
absence and difference is a distinction between a negation on edges and a
negation on nodes in the original graph. For, trivially, every node is such that
it is different from every other node. One way to represent this would be to
introduce a new kind of ‘non-identity’ edge into the graph, an edge which
connects every node with every other node. The Vaisesika, however, wants
the category of absence to correspond to a domain of things rather than
relations; so in the graph-theoretic representation, differences have to be
represented as nodes rather than edges. So let us say that for every node x in
the original graph, there is a new node x*. Call it an ‘antinode’. The antinode
x* is connected to every node in the graph. It is connected to x by an edge of
the absentee–absence type, and to every node other than x by an absential
location edge. There is a one–one correspondence between the new domain of
antinodes and the domain of original nodes.
The rational basis of metaphysics
85
The leading idea behind the graph-theoretic interpretation of the categories
is that a type of thing is a type of node, and node-types are determined by
patterns of possible valencies in the graph. It was for this reason that we did
not need earlier to label the nodes. With the introduction of the category of
absence, we have two higher-order type distinctions: the distinction between
positive and negative nodes, and the distinction among the negative nodes
between absential nodes and antinodes. Do these distinctions have a graphtheoretic explanation, or must we allow ineliminable node-labels to demarcate
presence nodes, absential nodes and antinodes? What we have now are three
different types of edge – corresponding to the relations of inherence, absence–
absentee and absential location. So we might hope to distinguish between
positive and negative nodes as those which are not and those which are at the
end of an absential edge. That is, we make it a requirement that no positive
node absentially qualify any other node. Clearly, the suggestion will work
only if the absence of an absence is not identical to a presence. We will see in
the next section that the graph-theoretically oriented Raghunatha indeed denies
that this is so. So as not to beg the question at this point, and for the sake of
pictorial clarity, I will continue to mark positive nodes ! and negative nodes
differently.24
3.6 HIGHER-ORDER ABSENCE
The above treatment of absence is in effect a procedure for introducing new
nodes into the original graph. One set of new nodes fills the ‘gaps’ in that
graph: whenever there is no edge between two nodes, an absential node is
introduced between, and linked to, them. Another set of new nodes exactly
mirrors the original graph: for each node in the original, there is one and only
one antinode, linked to everything the original node is not. But now, having
supplemented the original graph with two sets of new nodes, nothing is to
stop us from repeating the procedure again – generating new sets of secondorder absence nodes – and to do this again and again. It seems that we have
introduced a procedure for the indefinite recursive expansion of the graph.
Fortunately this does not in fact happen. As we will now see, no subsequent
recursion of the procedure after the first produces any new nodes.
Prima facie, it seems plausible to reason as follows (as we will shortly see,
this reasoning turns out to be subject to an important caveat). If x is in y, then
x′, the absence of x, is not in y, and so x″ the absence of x′, is in y. Conversely:
if x″ is in y, then x′ is not in y, so x is in y. Graph-theoretically, we represent
this as follows:
86
Philosophy in classical India
If this is right, then it follows that an entity and the absence of its absence
‘occur’ in exactly the same set of loci: for all y, there is an inherence edge (x,
y) just in case there is an absential location edge (x″, y). Can we appeal now
to an analogue of the uniqueness condition for universals – that two nodes are
identical iff they have exactly the same edges – and infer that the absence of
an absence of an entity is identical to presence of the entity? The point is
controversial, with the majority favouring identification. It is Raghunatha25
who argues that the identification is unsound, on the ground that nothing can
turn an absence into a presence. Here again Raghunatha’s intuition agrees
with the graph-theoretic reconstruction: the nodes x and x″ are connected to
other nodes by means of different types of edge. So they cannot both represent
entities of the same type. Moreover, as we shall see in more detail below, the
Naiyayikas do not accept that it is generally valid to infer from the occurrence
of x in y to the occurrence of x″ there, although they do allow the converse.
This is the caveat in the line of reasoning with which I began this paragraph.
The implication is that x and x″ need not, after all, share the same set of loci.
Let us repeat the procedure once more. If x", the absence of x, is in y, then
x″ is not in y, and so x#, the absence of x″, is in y. Conversely: if x# is in y,
then x″ is not in y, so x" is in y. Graph-theoretically:
It follows that a first-order absence and the absence of its absence reside in
exactly the same set of loci. But here we can appeal to the uniqueness condition,
because the edges are all of the same type. So x# is identical to x’, as
Raghunatha himself allows.26 Similarly, x# is identical to x″, and so on. There
are no absential nodes of order higher than two. The argument is summed up
by Annambhatta in the Tarkasamgraha:
The view of the early thinkers is that the absence of an absence is nothing
but a presence; it is not admitted as a new absence for there would then
be an infinite regress. According to the new school, however, the absence
of an absence is a distinct absence, and there is no regress as the third
absence is identical to the first. (TS 89)
Recall that we defined the absence x" as a node such that x" is absentially
located in y if there is no edge between x and y. That definition was adequate
for the introduction of first-order absences, because there is only one kind of
edge in the original graph, namely the inherence edge. The expanded graph
has another sort of edge, however: the absential edge. So the notion of a
second-order absence is underdetermined by our original definition. The new
definition we need is:
The rational basis of metaphysics
87
Rule for Absence:
An absence x" is absentially located in y if x does not inhere in y.
Rule for Higher Order Absence:
For i > 1, an absence xi is absentially located in y iff xi-1 is not absentially
located in y.
The second rule implies that absence is a classical negation for i > l, and so
in particular, that an absence of an absence of an absence is identical to an
absence. A double negation, however, is a mixture – a negation defined on
inherence edges followed by a negation defined on absential qualifier edges
and for that reason behaves non-classically. What I will show in the next
section is that Navya-Nyaya logic rejects the classical rule of Double
Negation Introduction – the rule that licenses one to infer from p to ~ ~ p.
What replaces it is a weakened rule – infer from ~ p to ~ ~ ~ p. This is
because negation is a procedure for filling ‘gaps’ in the graph: whenever
there is no edge between two nodes, the rule for negation licenses us to
insert an absential node between them. The classical rule for Double
Negation Elimination – the rule that licenses one to infer from ~ ~ p to p –
remains valid in Navya-Nyaya logic (i.e. if x" is not in y, then x is in y).27
The effect of this weakening in the rule for Double Negation Introduction is
that one is no longer entitled to infer that if x is in y, then x" is not in x". One
effect of this is to block the equivalence of a positive entity with the absence
of its absence. We can say that x" is the absence of x", but we cannot say
that x is the absence of x". Graph-theoretically, connections of the form ! x
Ö x’ are prohibited, since a positive entity cannot be the absence of
anything. Also prohibited are triangles of the form
because negation behaves classically within the domain of absences. What is
stranger, however, is the effect the weakened rule has of permitting a positive
entity to be co-located with its absence. For we are no longer in a position to
assert that the presence of an entity is inconsistent with its absence. Let us see
how the Nyaya philosophers arrive at the conclusion that one must allow for
such an unusual possibility.
Whenever something inheres in a compound substance, the question arises:
does it also inhere in the parts? An entity is said to be of ‘locus-pervading’
occurrence just in case it inheres in all the parts of its locus (as well as in the
locus itselt).28 It saturates its locus. A sapphire is red through-and-through,
and sesame oil pervades every part of the seed; but a painted vase is blue only
on the outside. Let us say then that x is locus-pervading with respect to y just
88
Philosophy in classical India
in case x inheres in y and if z is a part of y then x inheres in z.29 The only
things that have parts are substances, and substances inhere in their parts and
in nothing else. So x is locus-pervading with respect to y just in case x inheres
in y and if y inheres in z then x inheres in z. Certain types of quality pervade
their loci, according to the classical Vaisesika authors.30 Examples include
weight, viscosity and fluidity. A thing is heavy just in case every part of it is
heavy. Colours, tastes, smells can pervade their loci, but need not do so.31
And a compound substance is locus-pervading with respect to each of its
parts, if ‘part of’ is a transitive relation.
The notion of a locus-pervading entity has a distinctive graph-theoretic
correlate. An edge (n1, n2) is locus-pervading just in case there is an edge from
n1 to any node in any path from n2.
While locus-pervading nodes are straightforwardly definable in the system
as so far developed, the concept of ‘unpervaded occurrence’ (avyapyavrttitva)
marks a theoretical innovation. The classic Buddhist refutation of realism
about wholes is that wholes must be the bearers of contradictory properties.
For if some parts of a vase are red and other parts are not red, and if the vase
as a whole has a colour in virtue of its parts having colour, then one seems
forced to admit either that the whole is both red and not red, or that it has no
colour at all.32 The traditional Nyaya-Vaisesika solution is less than satisfactory
– it is to say that the whole has a new shade of colour called ‘variegated’!
Recognising the ad hoc nature of such a response, later Naiyayikas try instead
to make sense of the idea that a property can be co-located with its absence.33
The idea is to capture the sense in which one says that the vase is red, because
its surface is red, allowing at the same time that it is not red, because its
inside is some other colour. A favourite Nyaya example involves the relation
of contact: the tree enjoys both monkey-contact (there is a monkey on one of
its branches) and also the absence of monkey-contact (its roots and other
branches are in contact with no monkey). This defence of realism is what
motivates later writers to allow there to be such a thing as unpervaded
occurrence, defined to be an occurrence that is co-located with its absence.
That is, an unpervading node is a node x such that there is an edge (x, y) and
an edge (x", y). Triangles such as the following are now deemed to be
permissible in the graph:
The rational basis of metaphysics
89
The strangeness of such a possibility is ameliorated if one says, as some
Naiyayikas do, that x occurs in y as ‘delimited’ by one part, and its absence
occurs in y as ‘delimited’ by another part.34 Gangesa nevertheless goes to
considerable lengths to reformulate logic and the theory of inference in
Navya-Nyaya in a way that permits the co-location of an entity with its
absence. The phenomenon of unpervaded occurrence is regarded not as a
minor curiosity in Nyaya, but as the occasion for serious revision in their
analysis.35
3.7 NAVYA-NYAYA LOGIC
With the introduction of absence, the graph-theoretic ontologies become
also semantic models for a propositional language. A sentence ‘α’ is assigned,
let us stipulate, an ordered pair of nodes (x, y). The sentence is true if that
pair is an edge in the graph, false if it is not.36 The negation of that sentence,
‘~ α’, is true if (x", y) is an edge, false if it is not. Again, ‘~ is true if (x″, y)
is an edge, false if it is not. If triangles such as the one above are possible,
then the truth of ‘a’ does not imply the truth of ‘~ ~ α’, since (x, y) is an edge
but not (x″, y). So the propositional logic being modelled is, as we have
already observed, one in which Double Negation Introduction does not hold.
In this theory, we still have these correspondences between truth-value and
negation:
(R1) if ~Tα then T~ α from the Rule for Absence
(R2) T~~ α iff ~ T ~ α from the Rule for Higher Order Absence
where ‘T’ stands for ‘it is true that’.
What we no longer have is:
(R3) if T ~ $ then ~ Tα
The reason, as I said before, is that negation is an operation that fills ‘gaps’ in
the graph – it tells us nothing when there is already an edge between two
nodes. So the truth of a proposition is consistent, in Navya-Nyaya logic, with
the truth of its negation. This element of dialetheism37 in the theory does not,
however, mean that anything is provable or that anything follows from anything
else – the correspondences R1–R2 are enough to prevent the system collapsing.
Let us see why.
In the modern analysis of valid inference, an inference is valid just in
case it is impossible for the premises to be true without the conclusion also
being true. In the logic of classical India, validity is a matter of property
substitution, and the problem is to determine the conditions under which the
occurrence of the reason property at a location warrants the inference that
the target property occurs there too. The leading idea is that such property
90
Philosophy in classical India
substitutions are valid just in case the reason does not ‘wander’ or ‘deviate’
from the target (avyabhicara; see Chapter 1.6–7). In one of the most famous
passages in the Indian literature, Gangesa suggests five ways to make sense
of this idea:38
Now, in that knowledge of a pervasion which is the cause of an inference,
what is pervasion? It is not simply non-wandering. For that is not:
(1) non-occurrence in loci of the absence of the target, nor
(2) non-occurrence in loci of the absence of the target which are different
from loci of the target, nor
(3) non-colocation with difference from a locus of the target, nor
(4) being the absentee of an absence which resides in all loci of absence
of the target, nor
(5) non-occurrence in what is other than a locus of the target,
since it is none of these where the target is maximal.
A ‘maximal’ property is a property resident in everything (kevalanvayin).
Gangesa dismisses the five provisional analyses on the grounds that all
are formulated in terms of ‘absence of the target’, and that that phrase is
undefined when the target is maximal (the absence of a maximal property
– assumed here not to be of unpervaded occurrence – would occur in
nothing and so be ‘unexampled’, contradicting a basic condition of
connectedness). In his preferred definition, Gangesa exploits a trick to
overcome this problem.39 He says that any property whose absence is colocated with the reason is not identical to the target. This implies that the
target is not a property whose absence is co-located with the reason, but
the contraposed formulation avoids the use of the troublesome phrase
‘absence of the target’.
Consider now the difference between the first and second analyses in the
list of five. Graph-theoretically, what the first analysis states is that, if r is the
node representing the reason, and t is the node representing the target, then r
is present in no node where t is absent.
But what happens if the target has unpervaded occurrence? Then the first
analysis is too strong.40 For it is not a necessary condition on valid inference
that the reason not be present wherever the target is absent, if there are
nodes where the target is present as well as absent. What validity precludes
is the presence of the reason without the presence of the target. So the proper
The rational basis of metaphysics
91
definition is that the reason is not present wherever the target is not present
(and so also absent). This is exactly what the second analysis states. We can
make the point in terms of our earlier definitions of truth and negation. The
premise in an inference is the statement that the reason occurs in a certain
location, the conclusion the statement that the target occurs in that location.
What our first analysis asserts is that the premise is not true if the negation
of the conclusion is true (= absence of target in the location). The second
analysis states instead that the premise is not true if the conclusion is false
(= denial of presence of target in the location). Ironically, then, it is the very
element of dialetheism of the Navya-Nyaya system which forces Gangesa
to disambiguate the definition of validity, and to distinguish the correct
definition from the one that had been preferred before.
3.8 NUMBER
The classical Vaisesika theory of number is that numbers are qualities of
substances.41 A quality ‘two’ inheres in both members of a pair of substances,
another quality ‘two’ inheres in another such pair, and all the qualities ‘two’
have inhering in them a single universal ‘two-hood’.
Bhasarvajña and Raghunatha, as usual, lead the reforming move.
Bhasarvajña’s theory42 is that numbers are not qualities at all, but relations
of identity and difference. Thus the sentence ‘a and b are one’ means simply
that a = b, while ‘a and b are two’ means that a ≠ b.43 Bhasarvajña’s analysis
is echoed, very much later, in Gadadhara’s (c. AD 1650) comments on the
meaning of the word ‘one’.44 Gadadhara states that the meaning of ‘one F’
is: an F as qualified by being-alone, where ‘being-alone’ means ‘not being
the absentee of a difference resident in something of the same kind’. In other
words, ‘one F’ is to be analysed as saying of something which is F that no F
is different from it. If this is paraphrased in a first-order language as ‘Fx &
¬ (∃y)(Fy & y ≠ x)’ then it is formally equivalent to a Russellian uniqueness
92
Philosophy in classical India
clause ‘Fx & (! y)(Fy → y = x).’ The idea that ‘one’ expresses uniqueness is
in the spirit of Bhasarvajña’s idea that it denotes the identity of a thing. In
any case, it is clear that, for Gadadhara, ‘one’ has a logical role similar to
that of the definite article.
Raghunatha is more radical still.45 The central problem is that things in
any category in the Vaisesika ontology can be numbered, and Raghunatha
concludes that numbers must belong in a new category of their own:
Number is a separate category, not a kind of quality, for we do judge that
there is possession of that [number] in qualities and so on. And this
[judgment we make that qualities have number is] not an erroneous one,
for there is no [other] judgment which contradicts it.
Raghunatha puts his finger at exactly the right place. The ‘is-the-number-of’
relation is not reducible to the relation of inherence or any relation
constructed out of it, for it is a relation between numbers and any type of
thing. What is this new relation? Raghunatha points out that while inherence
is a distributive relation (avyasajya-vrtti), the number–thing relation has to
be collective (vyasajya-vrtti). The distinction occurs in the context of
sentences with plural subjects. An attributive relation is distributive if it
relates the attribute to every subject – if the trees are old, then each individual
tree is old. A relation is collective if it relates the attribute to the subjects
collectively, but not individually – ‘the trees form a forest’ does not imply
that each tree forms a forest. Number attributions are collective; if one says
that there are two pots here, one does not imply that each pot is two.
Inherence, however, is a distributive relation, and so cannot be the relation of
attribution for numbers. This new relation is called the ‘collecting’ (paryapti)
relation by Raghunatha:46
The collecting relation, whose existence is indicated by constructions
such as ‘This is one pot’ and ‘These are two’, is a special kind of selflinking relation.
His commentator Jagadisa explains:
It might be thought that the collecting relation is [in fact] nothing but
inherence . . . So Raghunatha states that collecting [is a special kind of
self-linking relation]. . . . In a sentence like ‘This is one pot’, collecting
relates the property pot-hood by delimiting it as a property which resides
in only one pot, but in a sentence like ‘These are two pots’, collecting
relates the property twoness by delimiting it as a property which resides
in both pots. Otherwise, it would follow that there is no difference between
saying ‘These are two’ and ‘Each one possesses twoness’.
Thus the number two is related by the collecting relation to the two pots
jointly, but not to either individually. Raghunatha’s idea is clear in the
The rational basis of metaphysics
93
graph-theoretic context. The introduction of numbers requires one final
expansion of the graph. We introduce another new domain of nodes (1, 2, 3,
. . .) and another new type of edge from these nodes. Like ordinary edges,
this new type of edge is an ordered pair whose first member is a node, but
now the second member is a set of nodes. The new edge connects the node 2
with every pair of nodes (x, y). Likewise, it connects the node 3 with every
triple of nodes (x, y, z), and so on. The node 2, then, is that node from which
all edges to pairs begin, the node 3 the node from which all edges to triples
begin, and so forth. This is enough to individuate number-nodes graphtheoretically:
The nodes to which the new edge can connect a number-node can be of any
type. In particular, they can themselves be number-nodes. Indeed, the new
edge connects 2 with pairs of nodes, one of whose members is 2 itself:
This solves the cross-categorial problem. Number-nodes are related by the
new kind of bifurcating edges to nodes of any and every type in the graph,
including number-nodes themselves.
The account of number affords an instructive insight into the mechanisms
of theory-change and internal criticism in Indian philosophical thinking.
94
Philosophy in classical India
The classical Vaisesika theory was modified under pressure from within,
through assimilation of the categories of quality and motion, elimination of
the category of individuators or perhaps of differences, and introduction of
a new category of number. What drove the revision was a perceived
explanatory failure in the older theory. The account of numbers as qualities
did not seem able to explain their cross-categorial behaviour, nor to give a
satisfactory explanation of the relation between numbers and the world of
objects. The old theory failed because it supplied no explanation of a range
of observed facts about the actual application of the concept of number, in
particular that the concept is applicable to objects in any ontological
category. The process of rejection and revision was driven, then, by a
perceived mismatch between the older theory of a concept and the actual
use of that concept in a range of cases. Such a process of theory-rejection
might be juxtaposed with another, according to which one looks for
inconsistency or incoherence in the basic concepts, and postulates which
form the foundation of the theory. This alternative method typically results
in or is driven by the discovery of paradox and absurdity. It has been a
familiar aspect of philosophical thinking in the West since the Greeks (Zeno,
Eubulides), and has had its promoters in India (Sañjaya, Nagarjuna, Sriharsa,
see Chapters 1, 2 and 6). However, the idea of rational acceptability as
foundational coherence is not the active principle behind the rejection or
revision of Vaisesika metaphysical theory. The underlying idea in their
philosophical theorising is that a theory is rationally acceptable if, or to the
extent that, it is in accordance with identified constraints on the construction
of ontologies. We have seen, in particular, that such constructions are
constrained by conditions of connectedness, redundancy and regress.
The graph-theoretic approach is, I think, full of potential. It offers a new
way to read and translate the discussions of the late Nyaya-Vaisesika texts.
One might proceed by looking for further situational constraints on what
constitutes a permissible graph and applying graph theory to analyse the
structure of those graphs. One might also try to establish the relationship
between such graphs and classical or non-classical logics. The treatment of
negation suggests a comparison with dialetheic logic, and the idea of selflinking nodes perhaps with non-well-founded set theory. My purpose here
has been to expose the graph-theoretic basis of Vaisesika theory, and to
draw a conclusion about the nature of rational thinking in India. The
conclusion is simply this. The idea that nature exemplifies mathematical
structure is not remote from the Indian understanding of natural philosophy,
contrary to what has generally been believed, but is in fact a fundamental
aspect of it.
The rational basis of metaphysics
95
FURTHER READING
Texts
Bhasarvajña c. AD 950, Nyayabhusana (NBhu).
Udayana c. AD 1050, Laksanavali (LA).
Ganges a c. AD 1320, Tattvacintamani (TC), Book II.
Raghunatha c. AD 1500, Padarthatattvanirupana (PTN).
The categories (3.1–3)
1
Wilhelm Halbfass, On Being and What There Is: Classical Vaisesika
and the History of Indian Ontology (Albany: State University of New York
Press, 1992), Chapters 1–5.
2
Karl Potter ed., Indian Metaphysics and Epistemology – The Tradition
of Nyaya-Vaisesika up to Gangesa, Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Vol.
2 (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1977), introduction.
3
S. Bhaduri, Studies in Nyaya-Vaisesika Metaphysics (Poona:
Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute, 1947).
Universals, cross-cutting (3.4)
1
Bimal Matilal, Perception (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), Chapters
11, 12.
2
Kishor Chakrabarti, ‘The Nyaya-Vaisesika Theory of Universals,’
Journal of Indian Philosophy 3 (1975), pp. 363–382.
3
Wilhelm Halbfass, On Being and What There Is: Classical Vaisesika
and the History of Indian Ontology (Albany: State University of New York
Press, 1992), Chapters 6, 7.
4
Sibajiban Bhattacharyya, ‘The Navya-Nyaya Theory of Universals,’
in his Gadadhara’s Theory of Objectivity, Part 1: General Introduction to
Navya-Nyaya Concepts (New Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research,
1990), Chapter 3.
Absence (3.5–6)
1
Daniel Ingalls, Materials for the Study of Navya-Nyaya Logic
(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1951), pp. 54–62, 69–72.
2
Bimal Matilal, The Navya-Nyaya Doctrine of Negation (Harvard:
Harvard University Press, 1968).
3
Bimal Matilal, ‘Double Negation in Navya-Nyaya,’ in M. Nagatomi
et al. eds., Sanskrit and Indian Studies: Essays in Honour of Daniel H. H.
Ingalls (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1980), pp. 1–10; reprinted in Logic, Language
and Reality (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1985), pp. 145–154.
4
Prabal Kumar Sen, ‘The Nyaya-Vaisesika Theory of Variegated
96
Philosophy in classical India
Colour (citrarupa): Some Vexed Problems,’ Studies in Humanities and Social
Sciences 3.2 (1996) – Epistemology, Logic And Ontology After Matilal (Shimla:
Indian Institute of Advanced Studies), pp. 151–172.
Navya-Nyaya logic (3.7)
1
Daniel Ingalls, Materials for the Study of Navya-Nyaya Logic
(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1951).
2
Bimal Krishna Matilal, ‘Gangesa on the Concept of Universal Property
(kevalanvayin),’ Philosophy East and West 18 (1968), pp. 151–161; reprinted
in Logic, Language and Reality (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1985), pp. 128–
139.
3
J. N. Mohanty, Gangesa’s Theory of Truth (Santiniketan, 1966).
4
Cornelius Goekoop, The Logic of Invariable Concomitance in the
Tattvacintamani (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Co., 1967).
5
Toshihiro Wada, Invariable Concomitance in Navya-Nyaya (Delhi:
Sri Satguru, 1990).
Number (3.8)
1
Jonardon Ganeri, ‘Numbers as Properties of Objects: Frege and the
Nyaya,’ Studies in Humanities and Social Sciences 3.2 (1996) – Epistemology,
Logic and Ontology After Matilal (Shimla: Indian Institute of Advanced
Studies), pp. 111–121.
2
Jonardon Ganeri, ‘Objectivity and Proof in an Indian Theory of
Number,’ Synthese (forthcoming).
3
J. L. Shaw, ‘Number: From the Nyaya to Frege-Russell,’ Studia Logica
41 (1982), pp. 283–291.
4
Roy W. Perrett, ‘A Note on the Navya-Nyaya Account of Number,’
Journal of Indian Philosophy 13 (1985), pp. 227–234.
4 Reduction, exclusion and
rational reconstruction
4.1 HOW TO PRACTISE POVERTY IN METAPHYSICS
The philosophical quest for unification is ancient and powerful. It is the
leitmotiv of the Upanisads, a dramatic enactment of the search for hidden
connections. There are indeed good reasons for seeking unity in a philosophical
theory. For any theory which introduces as primitive a distinction between
different domains of thing has left at least one thing unexplained – the reason
for the distinction. As a methodological principle, the philosopher should not
introduce a distinction simply to fix technical problems. We might recall
Nagarjuna’s maxim – the special reason for a proposed distinction must be
given. We might recall too the nominalist slogan of William of Occam – do
not postulate entities beyond necessity. Occam in fact rejected the Aristotelian
categories, and argued for simplicity as a constraint on rational theory
construction.
The Buddhist philosopher Dinnaga (c. AD 480–540) is uncompromising in
his search for unity and simplicity in philosophical explanation. He is an
ontological reductionist and a nominalist. It will be instructive to begin our
examination of his thought by comparing him with Nagarjuna. Both are
Buddhists, and in this context what that means is that they both reject the
ontological commitments of common sense. Common sense commits us to an
ontologically rich world, of individuals and properties, of parts and wholes,
and most importantly of a concrete connector of ‘inherence’, which binds
everything together in a categorial hierarchy. Nagarjuna’s philosophical
method is a debunking one – he wants to undermine common sense (and any
other conceptual scheme) by revealing as false the commitments it incurs. In
exposing the ontological ‘emptiness’ of our conceptual schemes, the end of
rationality is the elimination of conceptualisation (the end of reason is the end
of reason).
Dinnaga’s approach is different. His method is one of rational reconstruction.
He tries to show that the ontological commitments made by common sense
are reducible to a much smaller, more parsimonious set. The basic conceptual
scheme of common sense is preserved, but revealed in philosophical analysis
98
Philosophy in classical India
to be far less ontologically committed than it represents itself as being. The
end of rationality for Dinnaga is to rebuild our old conceptual superstructures
on new, leaner, foundations.
Let us distinguish four basic metaphysical positions – irrealism,
reductionism, metaphysical pluralism and additive (non-pluralist) realism.
The irrealist denies that things of some type exist, be they belief-states,
universals, moral values or entities of another type. He wants to do away
with all talk of such things (and either substitute a new vocabulary, or else
leave only silence). One variety of irrealism is eliminativism, according to
which talk of the kind in question is strictly false. Another variety is nonfactualism, a position which maintains that the linguistic role of such talk is
not fact-assertive, but rather emotive, prescriptive, or in some other way nonfactive. The reductionist’s position is perhaps subtler. The existence of things
of the type in question is not denied as such, but only their ontological
primitiveness. The reductionist’s thesis is that statements mentioning those
things can, without loss of content, be translated into statements not
mentioning those things. A reductionist about universals will translate
statements mentioning universals into statements about classes. A
reductionist about belief-states translates the statements of intentional
psychology into statements about mental events or some other favoured
category of basic constituents of the mental. The original statements are still
evaluable as true or false, but have been divested of their manifest
ontological commitments. Pluralism and additive realism, on the other hand,
both take the statements at face value, as really being about (made true by)
entities of the type mentioned. Where they differ is in the additive realist’s
commitment to there being a single proper language of metaphysics, in
contrast to the pluralist’s commitment to the existence of many irreducible
kinds of language use.1 We have so far encountered a version of irrealism –
Nagarjuna and the Madhyamaka school, and an account of additive realism
– the Vaisesika type-hierarchy. In Chapter 5, we will see how the
consequences of pluralism are explored by the Jaina metaphysicians.
Dinnaga completes the line-up. He is a reductionist. He wants to preserve the
structure of the common-sense scheme, but to divest it of its overt ontological
commitments. He wants to translate all talk of universals, wholes, inherence,
qualities, motions and absences into a language with only a minimal
primitive vocabulary. And the thoroughness with which he executes this
programme is nothing short of extraordinary.
4.2 A SKELETAL ONTOLOGY
What is it for an object to possess a property? The naive answer – the answer
given by common sense and encoded in Vaisesika ontology – is that the object
and the property are distinct entities linked together by an entity of a third
type, the concrete inherence connector. A state of affairs, an object’s having a
property, is an ordered triple. Something similar is true for the relationship
Reduction, exclusion and rational reconstruction
99
between a whole and its parts – the whole ‘resides’ (again by the concrete
relation of inherence, or so claim the Vaisesikas) in each and every one of the
parts that constitute it.
Here is a way to achieve an ontological gain. The world of individuals
and their properties can be reconstrued – following G. F. Stout2 and D. C.
Williams3 – in terms of ‘thin’ properties or tropes, e.g. the particular blue of
this vase rather than blueness as such. Blueness as such is to be identified with
the class of all particular blues. What the particular blues have in common is
being ‘exactly similar’ to one another: a property is a similarity class of
tropes under the relation of exact similarity. Another way for two tropes to
have something in common is by being tropes of the same object; e.g. the
particular blue of this vase and the particular shape of this vase. Let us say
that these two tropes stand in a relation of ‘concurrence’. Then an object is a
similarity class of tropes under the relation of concurrence. The relation of
‘possessing a property’ is now easily explained: an object possesses a
property just in case the class of tropes which is the object intersects with the
class of tropes which is the property. And the mereological relation
‘belonging to a whole’ is equally simple: a part belongs to a whole only if the
class of tropes which is the whole subsumes the class of tropes which is the
part.
Our new ontology reduces the world of objects, universals, wholes, parts
and inherence to a domain of tropes and two similarity relations. One similarity
relation binds tropes into objects, the other along a different dimension into
properties. The old idea of a universal – as a class of objects – finds a place
here in the notion of a class of classes of tropes. The universal blueness is the
class of blue objects; that is to say, a class of classes containing a blue trope.
The relations of likeness and unlikeness between objects, which were used in
the early Nyaya theory of rational extrapolation (Chapter 1.6), are themselves
reducible to the new primitive relation of exact similarity. One object is ‘like’
another just in case the first has a trope exactly similar to a trope belonging to
the second.
The ontology I have just described is very close to the one Dinnaga is
developing in his great classic, the Collection on Knowing.4 At the centre of
his system is a new theory of concepts. Dinnaga rethinks the very nature, role
and function of a concept. The traditional theory is that a concept is a criterion
and has a boundary. The criterion ‘. . . possesses blueness’ delimits a region
in the space of objects. It marks out a group of objects on the basis of a
common shared trait. Dinnaga’s new theory is that a concept is a boundary
and has a criterion. Objects are indeed brought together, but only as groups
of essentially disparate things, which happen to be penned in by a single
perimeter fence. It is a mistake to think of concepts as bringing objects together
on the basis of their sharing a common trait. The function of a concept, like a
fence, is rather to keep things out. So Dinnaga says that the role of a concept
is to exclude. The boundary of a concept is a line drawn in the space of
objects. On one side falls the excluded, and whatever is left falls within the
100
Philosophy in classical India
concept. A concept’s function is to exclude, to keep things out, to prevent
entry. A concept is not a criterion, which some objects meet and others do not
(like being red, or living in Paris). It is a pure boundary, a fence, keeping
some objects out and leaving the remainder within.
A concept excludes what is other. The relation of ‘otherness’ here is a
relation of exact dissimilarity. This is the basic relation in Dinnaga’s system.
We have defined a property as a similarity class of tropes. Indeed, from any
arbitrary trope, one can construct a property – the class of tropes exactly
similar to the arbitrary one. If we take exact dissimilarity instead as our
primitive relation, then what we have now to construct is that property which
is the class of tropes not exactly dissimilar to the arbitrary trope. A property
is the complement of a dissimilarity class.
The reduction of ordinary statements about objects, qualities and universals
is a translation into exclusion-statements. For reasons that I will explain later,
I am going to take the exclusion relation to be the relation of non-intersection
(so a class of tropes excludes all those other classes which do not intersect
with it). Then the task facing us will be to show how an ordinary statement
such as ‘the lotus is blue’, which apparently attributes the universal blueness
to an object of a certain type, can be translated into a statement concerning
the non-intersection of classes of tropes. If we succeed, we will have shown
that the rich ontology of common sense is reducible to a minimal ontology of
tropes and two similarity relations.
4.3 MARKING AND SIMILARITY
The key ingredients of Dinnaga’s new ontology are set out in a few sentences
in the first chapter of the Collection on Knowing:
There are two means of knowing, perception and inference, because
two marks are knowable. (I 2ab)
Apart from the self-marked (svalaksasa) and that which is marked by
generality (samanya-laksana) there is nothing else. What we shall prove
is that perception has the self-marked as its object, and inference has as
its object that which is marked by generality.
Among these,
Perception is that which is free from conceptual construction (kalpana).
What then is this conceptual construction? – the association of name,
genus, etc. (I 3cd)
In an Abhidharma treatise, too, the following is stated: ‘One who has the
ability to perceive grasps something blue, but does not grasp “this is blue”.’
‘One grasps an object in the object, but one does not grasp an element (dharma)
in the object.’ If perception is completely devoid of conceptual construction,
Reduction, exclusion and rational reconstruction
101
then why is it [further] stated that ‘the five kinds of sensory cognition have
aggregates as their support’? Again, it is mentioned that ‘they take as an
object a self-marked in so far as it is self-marked by a sensory field not in so
far as it is self-marked by a substance.’ (ad I 4ab)
How is this to be understood?
Being caused by many objects, [a perception] reaches a whole as its
own object. Since it is caused by many substances, it is said, in
respect of its field, that it takes the whole as its object; but not by
conceptually constructing a unity within that which is many and
separate. (I 4cd)
A thing possessing many forms (rupa) cannot be cognised in all its
aspects by a sense-faculty. The object of a sense-faculty is the form
(rupa) which is indescribable and self-revealing. (I 5)
Illusory cognition, cognition of the conventional truth, inference, that
which is inferred, memory and desire are pseudo-perceptions
(pratyaksabhasa), accompanied by obscurity. (I 7cd–8ab)
An illusory cognition is a pseudo-perception because it arises conceptually
constructing water, etc. out of such things as vapour floating over sand.
Cognition of the conventional truth is a pseudo-perception because it
superimposes something extraneous upon things which are only
conventionally true, and thus functions through the conceptualisation of
forms of these. Inference and that which is inferred are pseudo-perceptions
because they arise through the conceptualisation of what formerly has
been perceived.
Dinnaga developed his system out of the Abhidharma in which he had been
educated, and in which he had initially written. It is a cardinal doctrine of
Abhidharma Buddhism that there is a single kind of thing: the category of
dharma. A dharma is an ingredient, a factor, a fundamental constituent. It is
neither a substance nor a property, but that which constitutes both. The
Abhidharma literature suggests several different schemes for the classification
of dharmas. Of these, the chief divisions are those into the five Groups, the
twelve Spheres (the six sense-faculties and their six fields), and the eighteen
sorts of Base (the six sense faculties, their six fields and six corresponding
kinds of mental event).5 Although there is a strong phenomenalistic bias in
these classifications, the fundamental meaning of dharma is not ‘sensedatum’
as such, but ‘basic ingredient’ of any kind. They are the ingredients out of
which ordinary physical objects and their properties, as well as our sensefaculties and mental lives, are all constructed.
Dinnaga’s opening assertion is that there are precisely two sorts of thing.
There are the entities which are the ‘self-marked’ (sva-laksana), and there are
102
Philosophy in classical India
the things which are the ‘marked by generality’ (samanya-laksana). What are
they? An influence, certainly, must be the distinction made in the same terms
in the Abhidharmika literature. An architect6 of the Abhidharma states:
One examines the body by its own and general marks, as well as sensation,
mind and dharmas. Their own-mark is precisely [their] own nature
(svabhava), while the mark of generality is the non-eternality of the
conditioned [dharmas], the unhappiness of the defiled [dharmas], and the
emptiness and non-substantiality of all dharmas.
Here the self-mark of a dharma is its essence or ‘own nature’, while its general
mark is something that it shares with others. A particular shade of blue – for
example, the blue of this vase – has both common and unique qualities. Its
common attributes are the things it shares with other dharmas, for example,
being blue, being a colour. Its unique qualities are things it does not share
with others, such as its specific blue shade. The self-mark in Abhidharma is
not identical to a dharma or trope, but something unique to one.
In Dinnaga’s new system, the self-marked things are characterised in three
ways. Dinnaga says that they are: (1) the objects of perception; (2) free of
conceptual construction; and (3) indescribable. How do we explain these
three features? One option is to take it that a ‘mark’ of a trope is a class
containing it. Objects and properties are grouped together as classes that are
multiply occupied and so ‘general’, while individual tropes are classified by
themselves into singleton classes, and so ‘particular’. One can then fit the
three features by interpreting conception and language as having only
multiply occupied classes of tropes in their field of operation, and by taking
perception to be a vehicle for perceiving single tropes. Broadly speaking, this
is the interpretation of Dinnaga preferred, for example, by Richard Hayes7
and Bimal Matilal.8
A second option is to take it that by ‘mark’ Dinnaga is referring to a way
in which tropes can be grouped. Tropes can be grouped by the relation of
concurrence into objects, or else by the relation of exact similarity into
properties. Given a particular trope, one can form the class of tropes exactly
similar to it, or, along a different axis, the class of concurrent tropes. The
property blueness is then said to be ‘marked by generality’ in the sense that it
is the class which collects together all the particular blues. An object such as
the vase, on the other hand, can be said to be ‘self-marked’ in the sense that it
is the class which collects together all the tropes that constitute the particular
object. The explanation of the three characteristics of the self-marked is now
that language and conceptual construction are operations which group tropes
by exact similarity into properties, and perception is an operation which
groups tropes by concurrence into objects.
This seems to be the interpretation preferred by Masaaki Hattori9 and
Shoryu Katsura.10 Hattori writes that ‘[t]he thing in itself, which exists as the
indivisible unity of various aspects, is grasped in its totality only by means of
Reduction, exclusion and rational reconstruction
103
perception free from conceptual construction’ (1980, p. 62). Katsura’s
interpretation of Dinnaga is a development of Hattori’s position. He says
(1991, pp. 137–8):
I would like to propose an even more radical version of the framework
than Hattori’s. Namely,
There cannot be anything (in the external reality) which possesses
either svalaksana or samanyalaksasa at any time.
I would like to assume that in Dinnaga’s system svalaksana is the object
itself which is to be grasped directly by perception, which is neither
expressible nor identifiable at that moment, but which is later identified by
our conceptual thinking (kalpana) and given a certain name, while
samanyalaksana is the general feature common to individual objects which
is to be grasped by our conceptual thinking, e.g. inference and verbal
communication, and which is a concept or a name itself.
I favour this second interpretation. According to it, Dinnaga’s understanding
of self-mark and generality-mark differs from the Abhidharmika theory, which
follows more closely the first interpretation. This indeed is the innovation in
Dinnaga’s new system. The Abhidharmika holds that a dharma is the bearer
of both specific and general marks. Dinnaga’s view is that the ‘marks’ are not
types of properties of tropes at all, but rather kinds of similarity relation
among them. Indeed, it would not be correct to say that a trope ‘possesses’ an
object or a property, as these have here been defined. The relation, rather, is
one of constitution. An object possesses a property if it intersects with it, and
objects and properties are both constituted from tropes, but neither stands in
the possession relation to its constituents.
Dinnaga says that self-marked objects are objects of perception, but are
not conceptually or linguistically constructed. We need not infer from this
that he is introducing a notion of uninterpreted data of pure sensation. The
ineffability and unconstructedness of objects might be a simple consequence
of the fact that language and conceptual construction are vehicles for the
relation of exact similarity. Language and thought group tropes along the
axis of generality and not on the axis of concurrence: they ‘construct’ properties,
not objects. As to being the pure objects of perception, this does not imply that
tropes are mere sense-data either. The alternative is to take Dinnaga as asserting
that perception is the vehicle for grouping tropes along the axis of concurrence.
For as we can see from the passage cited, Dinnaga thinks that we perceive an
aggregate when our perception is caused by a multitude, and that this multiple
causation does not involve conceptual construction. Perception is a nonconstructive, purely causal, process of grouping tropes via concurrence into
objects. Inference is a conceptual process of grouping tropes via exact similarity
into properties.
104
Philosophy in classical India
4.4 THE ROLE OF LANGUAGE IN CONCEPTUAL
CONSTRUCTION
Dinnaga’s view of conceptual construction is thoroughly linguistic:
What then is this conceptual construction? – the association of name,
genus, etc. (I 3d)
In the case of proper names, a thing is expressed as discriminated by a
name; e.g. ‘Dittha’. In the case of universal-terms, [it is] as discriminated
by a universal; e.g. ‘the cow’. In the case of quality-terms, [it is] as
discriminated by a quality; e.g. ‘the white thing’. In the case of actionterms, [it is] as discriminated by an action; e.g. ‘the cook’. In the case of
substance-terms, [it is] as discriminated by a substance; e.g. ‘the staffbearer’ or ‘the horned’.
Here, some maintain that what is expressed is a thing discriminated by a
relationship. Others hold that a thing is expressed as discriminated by
nothing but empty (arthasunya – ‘meaningless’) words. [In any case,]
that which is devoid of such conceptual construction is perception.
Conceptual construction is the association of an object with a feature in tandem
with the application to that object of a noun-phrase. One conceptually constructs
whenever one judges that an object possesses a feature. A ‘feature’ here is any
group collected together by a similarity relation; it is a predicative notion
spanning all the categories in the Vaisesika type hierarchy.11 Conceptual
construction is a linguistic activity, because features are those classes whose
extensions are fixed by noun-phrases. A noun-phrase collects together objects
on the basis of an exact similarity relation.
Dinnaga sometimes writes in a nominalist vein, taking the order of
explanation here to run from word to collection:
One must necessarily admit that what an object has in common belongs
to the particular object. But it is not in the object. Therefore,
the word itself is the thing that objects have in common. (V 10b)
The instantiations such as the pot and so forth are similar owing to their
being expressible by the word ‘real’, but not owing to any intrinsic
property of the objects named.
We should then say that objects have exactly similar tropes because denoted
by the same noun-phrase. But whichever order one takes the explanation to
flow in, the important point is that language is a vehicle for the relation of
exact similarity.
We can now see better why objects in Dinnaga’s ontology are inexpressible.
To denote an object, a word would have to be able to pick out a concurrence class
Reduction, exclusion and rational reconstruction
105
of tropes, but words always and only pick out exact similarity classes. So words
never denote objects.
Might not one argue that it is nevertheless just the role of a proper name to
denote particular objects? Dinnaga himself mentions proper names such as
‘Dittha’, which he says express things possessing names. Can we not say that
the name ‘Dittha’ picks out that class of concurrent tropes which constitute
Dittha? If Dinnaga is a nominalist about the exact similarity relation, why
not also about the relation of concurrence? But this is not Dinnaga’s intention.
What he has in mind, perhaps, is rather the use of a name to track an object
over a period of time. A proper name is semantically akin to a general term
in that its denotation spans any temporal slice of an object. That is in fact the
grammarians’ explanation of the function of proper names within a theory
that all terms are general,12 and it is from grammarians that Dinnaga borrowed
in his philosophy of language.13 Proper names group temporal slices by the
exact similarity relation into a diachronically extended object; their function
is not to group tropes into an object at a single time.14
Might one not denote objects indirectly, via a suitably large conjunction of
noun-phrases? The simple noun-phrase ‘lotus’ denotes the class of lotuses.
The compound noun-phrase ‘blue lotus’ denotes the class of blue lotuses – a
smaller class. Surely if one were to conjoin sufficiently many noun-phrase
qualifiers, one would eventually construct a compound noun-phrase which
denotes a singleton class containing just one object.
Dinnaga’s argument against this possibility rests on what Nicholas Rescher15
has called the ‘cognitive opacity of real things’, the fact that an object has
more properties than can ever be cognised. Thus Dinnaga:
A thing possessing many properties cannot be cognised in all its aspects
by the sense. (I 5ad)
An object has many properties. But we do not become aware of them all
through the inferential sign. (II 13ab)
Although that which is expressed by a word has many properties, it is not
cognised in its entirety through a word. (V 12ab)
To cognise an object as such is to cognise it along with all its properties. A
sense-faculty, touch say, informs us only about the tactile properties of the
object. So through no one sense-faculty can we perceive all the states of
affairs involving the object. Likewise, inferential signs and words inform us
only about specific properties of the object, the property with which the sign
or word is correlated. So if to cognise an object is to cognise it along with
all its properties, then objects cannot in this way be constructed in conception.
Rescher makes out the contrast as one between real and fictional things.
Fictional particulars, he says in a nice phrase, are of ‘finite cognitive depth’.
There is a limit to the amount of new non-generic information one can find
out about them. But –
106
Philosophy in classical India
[w]ith real things, on the other hand, there is no reason in principle why
the provision of non-generically idiosyncratic information need ever be
terminated. On the contrary, we have every reason to presume these
things to be cognitively inexhaustible. A precommitment to descriptiontranscending features – no matter how far description is pushed – is essential
to our conception of a real thing. Something whose character was
exhaustible by linguistic characterization would thereby be marked as
fictional rather than real.
For Dinnaga, the salient contrast is the one between the self-marked and the
generically marked – the objects and properties in his system. Properties are
conceptual constructs. They are potential contents of conception because it
is possible, in principle, to know everything about them. What this means,
if the trope-theoretic analysis of the contrast is the correct one, is that one
can in principle know every member of a class of exactly similar tropes –
the entire set of blues, for example. (Is this really possible? See below.)
Objects, on the other hand, are not potential constructs of conception because
it is not possible, even in principle, to know everything about them. Again,
on the trope-theoretic analysis, what this means is that one cannot know
every member of a class of concurrent tropes – all the trope-constituents of
this vase, for example.
How then do objects enter one’s mental life, if not by our constructing
them in conception? Dinnaga’s answer is that they are non-conceptually made
available to us in perception. The concurrent tropes that comprise an object
jointly cause a perception of that object (ad I 4ab). Such perception is nonpropositional: one sees the blue thing, but not that it is blue (I 4cd). Perception
is the vehicle for apprehending concurrency, conception the vehicle for
apprehending exact similarity.
4.5 THE EXCLUSION THEORY OF MEANING
Dinnaga’s fundamental insight is into the nature of concepts. It is that concepts
delimit by exclusion. The insight is encoded in his theory of meaning:
That which is based on words is not a means of knowing separate from
inference. Because [a word] expresses its own meaning through the
exclusion of others. (V 1)
A word excludes others. (V 11d)
A word indeed speaks about things qualified by the exclusion of others.
(ad V 36)
The role of a word is to exclude what is other. A more traditional Indian
theory of meaning associates terms with ‘bases for application’ (pravrtti-
Reduction, exclusion and rational reconstruction
107
nimitta). The basis of a term is a universal (or quality or motion), and it is in
virtue of an object’s possessing that universal that the term is able to denote it.
Terms denote basis-possessors. Dinnaga, the reductionist, does not discard
this theory so much as reconstruct it. He finds a new entity, defined in terms
of the primitive relations of exclusion and otherness, which can act as a proxy
for a universal (ad V 36):
Only under our hypothesis are the properties of a universal established,
namely, unity, permanence and the condition of belonging to each
member of a class. An exclusion of contrary meanings has unity,
because it is undivided. It has permanence, because its substratum is not
destroyed. And it has the condition of belonging to each member in a
class, because it is cognised in every object in the word’s extension.
Therefore, since it is free from problems and possessed of excellent
virtues, it is only things that are qualified by the exclusion of contrary
things that a word denotes.
The universal blueness (U, say) has as its extension the class of blue objects.
Trope-theoretically, it is a class of classes – the class of all concurrency classes
containing a blue trope. Since the property blue (P, say) is the class of blue
tropes, U is the class of all concurrency classes intersecting with P:
U = {X : X ∩ P ≠ Ø}
The challenge is to construct these classes using only the relations of exclusion
and otherness. Let us begin by defining a new trope-theoretic property, nonblue – the property comprising what is other than blue. ‘Non-’ is here a termforming negation, a functor from terms for things to terms for what is other
than those things. Non-blue is the class of all tropes other than any blue trope.
Now we form the class of all classes non-blue excludes – the class of all
classes non-intersecting with non-blue. This is the class Dinnaga identifies as
the semantic value of the term ‘blue’.16 It is the anyapoha, the exclusion of
what is other. If we follow the usual convention of signifying the semantic
value of a term by placing that term within double brackets,17 then Dinnaga’s
exclusion theory of meaning for terms is:
!blue" = {X : X ∩ non-P = Ø}
According to Dinnaga, semantic values of this type can replace our talk of
universals. What is the relation between a universal and such a semantic value?
The trick is to see that the semantic value !non-blue" is now the class {X : X ∩
P = Ø}. So, since every class X either does or does not intersect with P, this class
is the complement of U. U and !non-blue" exclude each other, and together
partition the domain. The universal blueness is that which excludes the semantic
108
Philosophy in classical India
value of ‘non-blue’. Trope-theoretically, the point is that ‘exclusion of others’ is
a device for switching between classes of objects and classes of properties.
Dinnaga has to be able to show that his new theory of meaning for primitive
terms can sustain a compositional account of the meaning of complex terms.
His detailed explanation of the grammatical operations called ‘agreement’
(samanadhikaranya) and ‘qualification’ (vaisistya) is a response to this demand.
Suppose we introduce a concatenation of terms, ‘B^A’. This stands for ‘Awhich-is-B’: for example ‘blue^lotus’ stands for ‘lotus-which-is-blue’. Here ‘B’
qualifies or restricts ‘A’. Dinnaga gives the obvious composition rule governing
concatenation:
Although the words ‘blue lotus’ do differ in the complements that they
exclude, the words are in grammatical agreement in virtue of the
conjunction of the respective complement-exclusions in one object. This
conjunction serves the purpose of pointing out particulars in each word’s
extension, like a crow standing on a house. (ad V 14)
So
– ‘blue lotus’ excludes what is excluded by ‘blue’ and
what is excluded by ‘lotus’.
What is the relation between the semantic values of ‘lotus’ and ‘blue lotus’?
The phrase ‘blue lotus’ excludes everything the phrase ‘lotus’ excludes and
more – its meaning is narrower. So
, and likewise
.
Dinnaga, of course, will express this relationship as an exclusion:
With this relation, one can order terms by extension:
A term does not exclude terms of wider extension, terms of narrower
extension or coextensive terms, even though they differ from it. A wider
term does not exclude its narrower terms, because it creates anticipation
for them alone. Neither does it entail them, because uncertainty arises
concerning which of its narrower terms is applicable. In either case the
two terms can apply to the same set of objects. A narrower term precludes
the objects denoted by other narrower terms because of hostility. Because
particulars of another wider term are contradicted by the word simsapa’s
own wider term. The one term does not preclude the other directly,
because the narrower term is not synonymous with the wider term. If
this were the case, then it would not preclude other narrower terms. (V
25–29)
The implication is that there is a branching hierarchy of terms derived
from relations of exclusion among their extensions. Indeed, it was to recover
this hierarchy that we took exclusion to be a relation of non-intersection.
A term excludes another term if it is governed by a branching node also
Reduction, exclusion and rational reconstruction
109
Figure 4.1 Dinnaga’s hierarchy of terms.
governing the other term, and the exclusion might be direct or indirect (see
Figure 4.1).19
The progressive addition of more and more qualifiers leads to a honing in
of the description onto a narrower and narrower class of objects – the exclusion
of more and more of the domain. But although one can continually refine
one’s description, one can never describe a single object – objects are
linguistically obscure. And so the process of description is asymptotic, reaching
ever nearer, but never actually touching the world of objects.
Dinnaga, recall, argues that objects cannot be constructed in conception
because their properties are unlimited. It might seem, however, that universals
are in no better shape than objects in this regard, for universals too are
potentially infinite classes. Indeed, Dinnaga’s highly influential criticism of
the traditional theory of meaning, again derived from Bhartrhari, rests on
this point.20 He says that a general term cannot denote merely the objects,
because they are potentially ‘infinite’ in number, and if one thinks that the
term’s meaning is fixed only with reference to some finite class of objects, one
will be unable to explain the potential of that term to ‘wander’ onto new
objects (V 2ab). The new theory needs to be immune to these difficulties:
If a term expresses its own meaning by excluding other meanings, why
do the faults mentioned above not arise?
Because a term is not observed to apply to objects in the extension of a
contrary term, and because it is observed to apply to members of its
own extension, it is easy to connect [the term to its meaning], and the
term is not errant in its meaning. (V 34)
Association and dissociation are the two ways that a word expresses its
object. They consist respectively in applying to what is alike and in not
applying to what is unalike. It is not necessary to say that a word applies
to every instance of what is alike, because in some cases it is not possible
to express an extension that is unlimited. But it is possible to say that it
does not occur in the unalike – although it too is unlimited – simply on
110
Philosophy in classical India
the basis of its not being observed to apply to any unalike instance. For
this reason, because a term is not observed to apply to anything other
than that to which it is related, its expression of its own object is said to
be a negative inference.
Dinnaga’s use of the method of association and dissociation (anvayavyatireka),
as well as his concepts of what is alike and what is unalike (tulya, atulya) are
very important, and we will see them playing a large part in his theory of
inference (Chapter 4.7). He concedes that likeness classes cannot be determined
directly, but argues that they can be determined via an indirect route. The
idea is that unlikeness classes can be determined by mere non-observation,
and a likeness class is then fixed as the complement of an unlikeness class.
This doctrine has puzzled scholars for understandable reasons. As a principle
of inductive reasoning, it looks disastrous. Is Dinnaga really saying that one
is entitled to believe that all Fs are G as long as one has not observed an F
which is non-G?
What we need here is a principle of epistemic closure. Such a principle is
a rule on what else one knows if one knows some one thing. Knowledge is
often said to be deductively closed, meaning that one knows all the
deductive consequences of anything one knows. Thus, if S knows that p, and
p entails q, then S knows that q. Dinnaga rejects the following closure
principle: if S knows that x is in the extension of ‘A’, and x is like y, then S
knows that y is in the extension of ‘A’. If this were valid, then one would
know the extension of ‘A’ simply by knowing some one member of it. Of
course, a stronger rule is valid: if S knows that x is in the extension of ‘A’,
and S knows that x is like y, then S knows that y is in the extension of ‘A’.
The problem with this principle of epistemic closure is that it applies only to
objects known to be like x – but the whole problem is that the extension of
‘A’ contains too many objects to be individually known. What Dinnaga
does endorse is the indirect closure principle: if S knows that x is in the
extension of ‘A’, and x is unlikey, then S knows that y is not in the extension
of ‘A’. Again, it would not do to require that one knows that y is unlike x –
that is the point of Dinnaga’s insistence that non-observation is the basis of
our knowledge of the counter-extension of ‘A’. One knows that ‘A’ does not
apply to y because y is unlike x, not because one knows that y is unlike x. If
this indirect closure principle is true, then one can know the counterextension of ‘A’, and so by implication (the ‘negative inference’ of
contraposition), know the extension of ‘A’.
The problem with all this is that it is difficult to see why the negative
epistemic principle should be true, but not the corresponding positive
principle. What seems right is one cannot have the capacity to recognise
some one instance as blue without thereby having the capacity to recognise
any blue instance. Such a person knows what it is to count something as
blue. But this does not imply the much stronger thesis, that to be acquainted
with one blue instance is to be acquainted with all, or that acquaintance
Reduction, exclusion and rational reconstruction
111
with every instance of blue is necessary for the possession of the concept.
The best one can say is that there is a serious lacuna in Dinnaga’s
epistemological theory here; indeed, it is a hole later Buddhist epistemologists
would attempt to fill (see Chapter 4.9).
4.6 SENTENCE MEANING
Suppose I utter the sentence ‘A lotus is blue.’ What thereby have I said? The
classical Vaisesika answer is that I have described a fragment of the inherence
hierarchy, namely, the fragment in which a certain complex substance is
inhered in by the universal lotus-hood, and also by a quality blue which in
turn is inhered in by the universal blueness:
Dinnaga has a quite different idea. Borrowing again from Bhartrhari, he
asserts that the meaning of a sentence is a pratibha – an immediate
consciousness of a single unity, a holistic ‘flash of understanding’.21 One listens
to the words being uttered in succession, and suddenly there comes a moment
(perhaps even before the whole sentence has been finished) when one ‘gets the
point’ of what is being said. Bhartrhari says:22
When the [word] meanings are understood by separating [the words from
the sentence], there arises a pratibha which is different [from the meanings
of the words]. That [pratibha] effected by the word meanings is called the
meaning of the sentence.
Bhartrhari is a sentence-holist. Sentence meanings are, he claims, the
fundamental units of meaning. Words, the phonetic constituents of sentences,
are assigned meanings by ‘extraction’ (apoddhara), a process of analysis,
synthesis and abstraction, disclosing correlations between recurring sentenceconstituents and recurring meaning-ingredients. And Dinnaga borrows this
doctrine without significant modification:
The meaning of the word has been clarified after extracting the word
from the sentence. The meaning of the sentence, which is called pratibha,
first arises by dint of that [word meaning]. (V 46)
There is no philosophical tension between the doctrine that words acquire
meaning only in the context of sentences, and the doctrine that the meaning of
the sentence is a function of the meaning of the parts.23 The point has already
arisen in connection with the relation between simple and compound
nounphrases. Dinnaga is a compositionalist; indeed he explicitly formulates
112
Philosophy in classical India
the relevant composition rule relating the meaning of the compound to the
meaning of its components. He sees no tension between this and the doctrine
that component meanings are analytical fictions. Referring to the compound
‘blue lotus,’ he says:
But given that that which is expressed by the compound ‘blue lotus’ is
neither the quality blue nor the substance lotus, how is it that the expression
‘blue lotus’ expresses a single object, namely, one that is both blue and a
lotus?
Since the thing expressed is a complex entity, neither blue in isolation
nor a lotus in isolation is expressed. (V 15ad)
From the two words, ‘blue’ together with ‘lotus,’ one is aware of the two
things combined, but one is not aware of them individually. The two
words functioning as elements of a complex expression individually
have no meaning, just as the individual phonetic components of a
word have no meaning. (V 15cd)
The situation here is like that of the word nila [‘blue’], which is meaningful
despite the fact that the individual phonetic components ni and la are
meaningless.
What we want, then, is a composition rule for sentence meaning, a rule which
shows how the semantic value of a sentence is a function of the semantic values
of the individual words. Dinnaga, unfortunately, is not very informative here.
As Masaaki Hattori24 has commented, ‘[i]t is understood that Dinnaga was
primarily concerned with the meaning of a word when he formulated the apoha
theory. Regarding the meaning of a sentence, he simply accepted Bhartrhari’s
doctrine, without discussing the problem how the meaning of a single word is
related to the meaning of the sentence.’ I do not think, however, that it is too
difficult to discover a composition rule of the kind we are looking for.
Dinnaga thinks that subject–predicate sentences involve a suppressed use
of the restrictive particle only (Sanskrit: eva).25 The particle only can be attached
to either the subject or the predicate position, and its explicit insertion in one
rather than another place disambiguates the sentence. For example, beginning
with ‘A lotus is blue’, we can disambiguate it either as ‘Only a lotus is blue’
or else as ‘A lotus is only blue’. Having (re)inserted the particle only, one can
appeal to a theory about the semantics of only to discover the sentence meaning.
Inserting only into a sentence does not add new semantic content. Instead,
like brackets or commas, its function is to make manifest and unambiguous a
semantic content (the Sanskrit grammarians say that it is a dyotaka, a ‘manifester’
of meaning, not a vacaka, an ‘expressor’ of meaning). Dinnaga’s theory,
strikingly, is that only constructions are explicit devices for the expression of
Reduction, exclusion and rational reconstruction
113
‘exclusion of others’. Take the sentence ‘Only a lotus is blue.’ It means that
nothing but a lotus is blue, that blueness is excluded from what is other than a
lotus. The phrase ‘other than a lotus’ is a noun-phrase denoting objects that
stand in the unlikeness relation with lotuses. As before, let us write such a nounphrase ‘non-lotus’. The equivalence then is between (1a) and (1b):
1a.
1b.
only S is P.
no non-S is P.
What is the meaning of a statement when only is inserted in the predicate
position? The natural reading of ‘A lotus is only blue’ is as stating that no
lotus is non-blue:
2a.
2b.
S is only P.
no S is non-P.
The symmetry between the disambiguations in (1) and (2) is appealing. Indeed,
it seems to be implied by the metarule of the pre-Paninian grammarian Vyadi:
‘restriction should be made to the item other than that which is accompanied
by the particle only.’26 It is important, however, to note that constructions
such as (1b) and (2b) lack existential import. For example, one can say ‘no
non-members will be admitted’ without saying anything about what will
happen to members. The sentence conversationally implicates, but does not
state, that members will be admitted.
There is another reading of (2a). It can be read as asserting that some S is
P. I’m not sure that the English word only has this emphatic reading, but the
Sanskrit particle eva, like the Hindi particle hi, certainly does. It is often best
translated as ‘really’, ‘indeed’ or ‘just’. This is the reading to take when the
sentence does have existential import. If one asserts ‘Mosquitoes are indeed
malarial,’ what one asserts is that mosquitoes are not non-malarial. One does
not assert that no mosquito is non-malarial. So when eva takes the predicate
position, a second possible reading is:
3a.
3b.
S is indeed P.
S is not non-P.
If ‘non-’ is a complement-like negation (so that everything is either P or nonP), then the following equivalencies will hold:27
1b.
2b.
3b.
no non-S is P
no S is non-P
S is not non-P
all P are S.
all S are P.
some S is P.
The meaning of a sentence, then, is in general the exclusion of one class from
what is other than a second class. Exclusion is the non-intersection relation, a
114
Philosophy in classical India
class excluding every non-intersecting class. So (1b) asserts that non-S excludes
P, and (2b) that S excludes non-P. (3b) is different – it asserts that S does not
exclude P. In set theory, the three truth-conditions are (1) that S ∩ P = P, (2)
that S ∩ P = S, and (3) that S ∩ P ≠ Ø.
Now that we know what the meaning of a sentence actually is, we can go
back to our initial question – what is the relationship between word and
sentence meaning? The first thing to see is that there is a systematic connection
between the meaning of the sentence ‘A lotus is blue’ and the meaning of the
compound noun-phrase ‘blue lotus’. Dinnaga’s composition rule for compound
noun-phrases is that the semantic value of a compound is the intersection of
the semantic values of its constituents. In his terms, ‘blue lotus’ excludes what
is excluded by ‘blue’ and what is excluded by ‘lotus’. Now the sentence ‘A
lotus is blue’ makes an assertion about this class of objects. It asserts either
that the class is identical to the class of blue objects, or to the class of lotuses,
or is non-empty. And so truth-values are assigned to sentences as follows:
1. !only S is P" = T iff !S^P" = !P".
2. !S is only P" = T iff !S^P" = !S".
3. !S is indeed P" = Y iff !S^P" ¹ Ø.
In connection with the third of these composition rules, we may note an
expositor’s comment that when a word is uttered alone, the verb ‘there exists
. . .’ is understood.28 So the compound noun-phrase ‘blue lotus’ uttered alone
means the same as ‘there exists a blue lotus’, and this is the meaning assigned
to ‘a lotus is indeed blue’. These three truth-clauses discharge the obligation
to show how ordinary subject–predicate sentences are reduced in the language
of exclusion.
4.7 CONDITIONS ON RATIONAL EXTRAPOLATION
Dinnaga uses his new theoretical framework in a fundamental restructuring of
the early Nyaya analysis of reasoned extrapolation and inference. Recall that
analysis (Chapter 1.6–7). It is an inference from likeness and unlikeness. In the
one case, some object is inferred to have the target property on the grounds that
it is ‘like’ a paradigmatic example. The untasted grain of rice is inferred to be
cooked on the grounds that it is in the same pan as a test grain which is found
to be cooked. In the other case, the object is inferred to have the target property
on the grounds that it is ‘unlike’ an example lacking the target property. Likeness
and unlikeness are matters of sharing or not sharing some property, the reason
property or evidence grounding the inference. Examples are either ‘positive’ –
having both the reason and the target property, or ‘negative’ – lacking both.
Extrapolation is the process of extrapolating a property from one object to
another on the basis of a likeness or unlikeness between them.
The difficulty is that not every such extrapolation is rational or warranted.
Reduction, exclusion and rational reconstruction
115
The extrapolation of a property from one object to another is warranted
only when the two objects are relevantly alike or relevantly unalike. (In
what follows, ‘alike’ and ‘unalike’ are used when the adjectives occur in the
predicate – the statement ‘A and B are alike’ is synonymous with ‘A is like
B’.) That two objects are both blue does not warrant an extrapolation of
solidity from one to the other; neither can we infer that they are different in
respect to solidity because they are of different colours. What one needs,
then, is a theory of relevant likeness or unlikeness, a theory, in other words,
of the type of property (the reason property) two objects must share if one is
to be licensed to extrapolate another property (the target property) from one
to the other.
This is exactly what Dinnaga does in his celebrated theory of the ‘reason
with three characteristics’. Dinnaga’s thesis is that relevant likeness is, once
again, an exclusion relation. Two objects are relevantly alike with respect to
the extrapolation of a property S just in case they share a property excluded
from what is other than S. In other words, a reason property H for the
extrapolation of a target property S is a property no wider in extension than
S (assuming again that ‘non-’ is such that H ∩ non-S = Ø iff H ⊆ S). Here is
the crucial passage in the Collection on Knowing:
The phrase [from II 1b] ‘through a reason that has three characteristics’
must be explained.
[A proper reason must be] present in the site of inference and in what is
like it and absent in what is not. (II 5cd)
The object of inference is a property-bearer qualified by a property. After
observing [the reason] there, either through perception or through inference,
one also establishes in a general manner [its] presence in some or all of
the same class. Why is that? Because the restriction is such that [the
reason] is present only in what is alike, there is no restriction that it is
only present. But in that case nothing is accomplished by saying that [the
reason] is ‘absent in what is not’. This statement is made in order to
determine that [the reason], absent in what is not [like the site of inference],
is not in what is other than or incompatible with the object of inference.
Here then is the reason with three characteristics from which we discern
the reason-bearer.
Dinnaga’s important innovation is to take the notions of likeness and unlikeness
in extrapolation to be relative to the target property rather than the reason
property. Two objects are ‘alike’ if they both have, or both lack, the target
property. Two objects are ‘unalike’ if one has and the other lacks the target
property. We want to know if our object – the ‘site’ of the inference – has the
target property or not. What we do know is that our object has some other
property, the reason property. So what is the formal feature of that reason
116
Philosophy in classical India
property, in virtue of which its presence in our object determines the presence
or absence of the target property? The formal feature, Dinnaga claims, is that
the reason property is present only in what is like, and absent in whatever is
unlike, our object.
This can happen in one of two ways. It happens if the reason property is
absent from everything not possessing the target property and present only in
things possessing the target property. Then we can infer that our object too
possesses the target property. It can also happen if the reason property is
absent from everything possessing the target property and present only in
things not possessing the target property. Then we can infer that our object
does not possess the target property.
Call the class of objects which are like the site of the inference the ‘likeness
class’, and the class of objects unlike the site the ‘unlikeness class’ (Dinnaga’s
terms are sapaksa and vipaksa). Interpreters have traditionally taken the
likeness class to be the class of objects which possess the target property, and
the unlikeness class to be the class of objects which do not possess the target
property. I read Dinnaga differently. I take his use of the terms ‘likeness’ and
‘unlikeness’ here at face value, and identify the likeness class with the class of
things in the same state vis-à-vis the target property as the site of the inference.
We do not know in advance what that state is, but neither do we need to. The
pattern of distribution of the reason property tells us what we can infer – that
the site has the target property, that it lacks it, or that we can infer nothing.
My approach has several virtues, chief among which is that it preserves the
central idea of likeness as a relation between objects rather than, as with the
traditional interpretation, referring to a property of objects. I think it also
avoids many of the exegetical problems that have arisen in the contemporary
literature with regard to Dinnaga’s theory.
One of the traditional problems is whether the site of the inference is included
in the likeness class or not.29 If the likeness class is the class of objects possessing
the target property, then to include it seems to beg the question the inference
is trying to resolve: does the site have that property or not? But to exclude it
implies that the union of the likeness and unlikeness classes does not exhaust
the universe (the site cannot, for obvious reasons, be unlike itself). So one is
left with two disjoint domains, and an apparently insuperable problem of
induction – how can correlations between the reason property and the target
property in one domain be any guide to their correlation in another, entirely
disjoint, domain?30
If we take Dinnaga’s appeal to the idea of likeness at face value, however,
the problem simply does not arise. The site of the inference is in the likeness
class on the assumption that likeness is a reflexive relation – but that begs no
question, for we do not yet know whether the likeness class is the class of
things which possess the target property, or the class of things which do not
possess it. It is the class of things which are in the same state vis-à-vis the
target property as the inferential site itself. We can, if needs be, refer to objects
‘like the site but not identical to it’; or we can take likeness to be non-reflexive,
Reduction, exclusion and rational reconstruction
117
and refer instead, if needs be, to ‘the site and objects like it’ – but this is a
matter only of semantics, with no philosophical interest.
Another of the traditional problems with Dinnaga’s account is an alleged
logical equivalence between the second and third conditions.31 The second
condition states that the reason property be present only in what is alike. The
third condition states that it be absent in what is not. But if it is present only
in what is alike, it must be absent in what is not; and if it is absent in what is
not alike, it must be present only in what is. Now it is clear that Dinnaga’s
reason for inserting the particle only into his formula is to prevent a possible
misunderstanding. The misunderstanding would be that of taking the second
condition to assert that the reason property must be present in all like objects.
That would be too strong a condition, ruling out any warranted inferences in
which the reason property is strictly narrower than the target. Recalling our
discussion of the meaning of the particle only, we can see that it is also one of
the two readings of the statement:
In what is alike, there is only the presence [of the reason]
where the particle only is inserted into the predicate position. Dinnaga eliminates
this unwanted reading of the second condition, but he does so in a disastrous
way. He eliminates it by inserting the particle into the subject position:
Only in what is alike, there is the presence [of the reason].
The reason this is disastrous is that it makes the second condition logically
equivalent to the third. Recall, however, that when only is in predicate position,
there are still two readings. The reading one needs to isolate is the second of
these two readings:
In what is alike, there is indeed the presence [of the reason].
That is, the reason is present in some of what is alike.
Accordingly, the theory is this. The extrapolation of a property S to an
object is grounded by the presence in that object of any property X such that
X excludes non-S but not S. A reason property for S is any member of the
class
{X : X n S ≠ Ø & X n non-S = Ø}
The clause ‘but not S’ (the second of Dinnaga’s three conditions) has a clear
function now. It is there to rule out properties which exclude both non-S and
S. Such properties are properties ‘unique’ to the particular object which is the
site of the inference, and Dinnaga does not accept as warranted any
extrapolation based on them. I will look at his motives in the next section.
118
Philosophy in classical India
Reason properties are non-empty subsets of the properties whose
extrapolation they ground. If two objects are ‘alike’ in sharing a property,
and one has a second property of wider extension than the first, then so does
the second. Inductive extrapolation, in effect, is grounded in the contraposed
universal generalisation ‘where the reason, so the target.’ A difficult problem
of induction remains – how can one come to know, or justifiably believe, that
two properties stand in such a relation without surveying all their instances?
Dinnaga has no adequate answer to this problem. Dharmakirti, Dinnaga’s
brilliant reinterpreter, does. His answer is that when the relation between the
two properties is one of causal or metaphysical necessity, the observation of a
few instances is sufficient to warrant our belief that it obtains (Chapter 4.9).
Dinnaga, however, is not interested in such questions. For him, the hard
philosophical question is that of discovering the conditions for rational
extrapolation. It is another, for him quite secondary, issue whether those
conditions can ever be known to obtain.
To sum up, Dinnaga’s three conditions on the reason are:
(1) Presence in the site a
(2) Presence (only) in what is like a
(3) Absence in what is unlike a
attachment
association
dissociation
(paksadharmata)
(anvaya)
(vyatireka)
If we take these conditions to be independent, it follows that there are exactly
seven kinds of extrapolative inferential fallacy – three ways for one of the
conditions to fail, three ways for two conditions to fail, and one way for all
three conditions to fail.32 So the new theory puts the concept of a fallacy on a
more formal footing. A fallacy is no longer an interesting but essentially ad
hoc maxim on rationality. It is now a formal failing of the putative reason to
stand in the correct extrapolation-grounding relation. One way for the reason
to fail is by not attaching to the site at all, thereby failing to ground any
extrapolation of other properties to it. This is a failure of the first condition.
Another way for the reason to fail is by ‘straying’ onto unlike objects, thereby
falsifying the third condition. The presence of one property cannot prove the
presence of another if it is sometimes present where the other one is not. (It
can, however, prove the absence of the other if it is present only where the
other is not – and then the absence of the first property is a proof of the
presence of the second.) We might then think of the third condition as a ‘no
counter-example’ condition, a counter-example to the extrapolation-warranting
relation of subsumption being an object where the allegedly subsumed property
is present along with the absence of its alleged subsumer. An extrapolation is
grounded just as long as there are no counter-examples.
4.8 REASONING FROM SPECIFICS
I have said that an extrapolation-grounding property is a non-empty subproperty
– a property narrower in extension than the property being extrapolated, and
Reduction, exclusion and rational reconstruction
119
resident at least in the object to which that property is being extrapolated. The
sweet smell of a lotus is a ground for extrapolating that it has a fragrance; its
being a blue lotus is a ground for extrapolating its being a lotus. Extrapolation
is a move from the specific to the general, from species to genus, from conjunction
to conjunct. Extrapolation is a move upwards in the hierarchy of kinds (the
hierarchy which the Vaisesikas explained in terms of their partial order in the
level of universals, Chapter 3.4). This model of extrapolation works well in
most cases, but what happens at the extremes? The extreme in one direction is
a most general property of all, a property possessed by everything. Existence or
‘reality’, if it is a property, is a property like this, and the theory entails that
existence is always extrapolatable – the inference ‘a is, because a is F’ is always
warranted. Dinnaga’s theory faces a minor technical difficulty here. Since
everything exists, then everything is ‘like’ the site of the inference (in the same
state as the site with respect to existence), and the unlikeness class is empty. So
Dinnaga has to be able to maintain that his third condition – absence of the
reason property in every unlike object – is satisfied when there are no unlike
objects. The universal quantifier must have no existential import. His innovative
distinction between inference ‘for oneself’ (svarthanumana) and inference ‘for
others’ (pararthanumana) is a help here. It is the distinction between the logical
preconditions for warranted extrapolation and the debate-theoretic exigencies
of persuasion. While it might be useful, even necessary, to be able to cite a
supporting negative example if one’s argument is to carry conviction and meet
the public norms on believable inference, there is no corresponding requirement
that the unlikeness class be non-empty if an extrapolation is to be warranted.
What happens at the other extreme? Extrapolation is a move from the
more specific to the less specific, and the limit is the case when the reason
property is entirely specific to the site of the inference. There is no doubt
that Dinnaga thinks that extrapolation breaks down at this limit. He calls
such reason properties ‘specific indeterminate’ (asadharananaikantika), and
classifies them as bogus reasons.33 Indeed it is the entire function of his
second condition to rule out such properties. That is why the second condition
insists that the reason property must be present in an object like the site.
This condition is an addition to the first, that the reason property be present
in the site – it demands that the reason be present in some other object like,
but not identical to, the site. Dinnaga’s example in the Collection on Knowing
(II 7d) is:
[Thesis] Sound is non-eternal.
[Reason] Because it is audible.
In the Chart of Reasons (5cd–7a), he gives another example:
[Thesis] Sound is eternal.
[Reason] Because it is audible.
120
Philosophy in classical India
What is the difference? In fact, the difference between these two examples
holds the key to what Dinnaga thinks is wrong. The property audibility,
something specific to sound, does not determine whether sound is eternal or
non-eternal. In either case, audibility is absent from what is unlike sound
(because it is unique to sound), but also from what is like sound (except for
sound itself). This symmetry in the distribution of the reason property
undermines its capacity to discriminate between truth and falsity. To put it
another way, if we take the universal quantifier to range over everything
except the site of the inference, sound, then it is true both that everything
audible is eternal and that everything audible is non-eternal – both are true
only because there are no audibles in the range of the quantifier.
This seems to be Dinnaga’s point, but it is not very satisfactory. Sound is
either eternal or non-eternal, and so audibility is a subproperty of one or the
other. One and only one of the above universal quantifications is true when
the quantifier is unrestricted. In any case, just why is it that we should not
reason from the specific properties of a thing? We do it all the time. Historical
explanations are notoriously singular – unrepeated historical events are
explained by specific features of their context. Dinnaga, it seems, is like the
follower of the deductive-nomological model in insisting on repeatability as a
criterion of explanation. What about mundane cases such as this one: the
radio has stopped because I have unplugged it? Being unplugged by me is a
property specific to the radio, and yet the form of the explanation seems
unapproachable. Perhaps, however, what one should say is that the explanatory
property is ‘being unplugged’, and not ‘being unplugged by me’, and the
explanation rests on the generalisation ‘whenever a radio is unplugged, it
stops.’ So then the restriction is not to any property specific to the site, but
only to those which are not merely tokens of some more general explanatory
property. And yet there are still intuitively rational but specific inferences –
that salt is soluble in water because it has a certain chemical structure, that
helium is inert because it has a certain atomic number, flying creatures fly
because they have wings. Why shouldn’t the specific properties of a thing be
implicated in inferences of its other properties?
What we see here is Dinnaga’s adherence to a strictly inductivist model of
extrapolation. The specific property audibility does not ground an extrapolation
of eternality or non-eternality because there can be no inductive evidence for
the extrapolation. Inductive evidence takes the form of objects in the likeness
and unlikeness classes known to have or not to have the reason. One might
think that one does have at least ‘negative’ evidence, for one knows that
audibility is absent from any object in the unlikeness class. So why can one
not infer from the fact that audibility is absent in unlike objects that it must be
present in like objects? The answer is that one can indeed make that inference,
but it does not get one very far. For we must recall again the way these classes
are defined – as classes of objects like or unlike the site with respect to eternality.
We do not know whether the site is eternal or non-eternal, and in consequence
we do not know whether unlike things are things which are non-eternal or
Reduction, exclusion and rational reconstruction
121
eternal. So while we have plenty of examples of eternal inaudibles and noneternal inaudibles, we still do not know which are the ‘like’ ones and which
the ‘unlike’.
The explanation of salt’s solubility by its specific chemical structure
exemplifies a quite different model of explanation. It is a theoretical explanation
resting on the postulates of physical chemistry. It is from theory, not from
observation, that one infers that having an NaCl lattice structure is a subproperty of being soluble. Similarly, within the context of suitable theories
about the nature of sound and secondary qualities, one might well be able to
infer from sound’s being audible to its being non-eternal. Dinnaga, in spite of
his brilliance and originality, could not quite free himself from the old model
of inference from sampling. His inclusion of the second condition was a
concession to this old tradition. He should have dropped it. Later Buddhists,
beginning with Dharmakirti, did just that – they effectively dropped the second
condition by adopting the reading of it that makes it logically equivalent to
the third.
4.9 ARE REASON–TARGET RELATIONS LAW-LIKE?
Dharmakirti (AD 600–660) offers a substantive account of the conditions
under which the observation of a sample warrants extrapolation. His claim is
that this is so if the reason property is one of three types: an ‘effect’ reason
(karya-hetu), a natural reason (svabhava-hetu), or a reason based on nonobservation (anupalabdhi-hetu).34
In each case, the presence of the reason in some sense necessitates the
presence of the target. An effect reason is a property whose presence is causally
necessitated by the presence of the target property – for example, inferring
that the mountain has fire on it, because of smoke above it. The reason–target
relation is a causal relation. Clearly one can, and later philosophers35 indeed
did, extend this to cover other species of causal inference, such as cases when
reason and target are both effects of a common cause. The generalisation
‘night follows day’ is true, not because day causes night, but because both
day and night are caused by the rotation of the earth. An example often cited
is the inference of lemon-colour from lemon-taste, when both are products of
the same cause, viz. the lemon itself. Still another example is the inference of
ashes from smoke: ashes and smoke are both effects of fire. Such an inference
has two steps. First, fire is inferred from smoke; second, ash is inferred from
fire. The second step, in which we infer an effect from its cause, is possible
only because ash is a necessary effect of fire.
A natural reason is one whose presence metaphysically necessitates that
of the target property, for example the inference that something is a tree
because it is a simsapa (a species of tree). Dharmakirti appears to regard
the law ‘all simsapas are trees’ as necessarily true, even if its truth has to be
discovered by observation, and thus to anticipate the idea that there are a
posteriori necessities.36 He states, surprisingly, that the reason–target relation
122
Philosophy in classical India
in such inferences is the relation of identity. Why? Perhaps his idea is that
the two properties being-a-simsapa and being-a-tree are token-identical, for
the particular tree does not have two distinct properties, being-a-simsapa
and a separate property being-a-tree, any more than something which weighs
one kilogram has two properties, having-weight and having-weight-onekilogram. The properties as types are distinct, but their tokens in individual
objects are identical. Trope-theoretically, the point can easily be understood.
The very same trope is a member of two properties, one wider in extension
than the other, just as the class of blue tropes is a subset of the class of
colour tropes. But a blue object does not have two tropes – one from the
class of blue tropes and one from the class of colour tropes. It is the selfsame trope.
Is absence of evidence evidence of absence? According to Dharmakirti,
non-observation sometimes proves absence: my failure to see an object,
when all the conditions for its perception are met, is grounds for an inference
that it is not here. The pattern of argument such inferences exemplify was
known to the medievals as argumentum ab ignorantiam, or an ‘argument
from ignorance’. The pattern occurs whenever one infers that p on the grounds
that there is no evidence that p is false. Dharmakirti states that the argument
depends on the object’s being perceptible, i.e. that all the conditions for its
perception (other than its actual presence) are met in the given situation.
Douglas Walton, in a major study of arguments from ignorance,37 claims
that they depend for their validity on an implicit conditional premise – if p
were false, p would be known to be false. The characteristics of an argument
from ignorance are then a ‘lack-of-knowledge’ premise – it is not known
that not-p, and a ‘search’ premise – if p were false, it would be known that
not-p. The underlying hidden premise mentioned by Dharmakirti seems to
be exactly the one Walton gives: if the object were here, one would see it.
The necessity here is subjunctive. The argument has a presumptive status –
one has a right to presume the conclusion to be true to the extent that one
has searched for and failed to find counter-evidence. It is this idea that is
strikingly absent in Dinnaga. Warranted extrapolation depends not on the
mere non-observation of counter-examples, but on one’s failing to find them
in the course of a suitably extensive search.
In each of the three cases, the universal relation between reason and target
is a relation not of coincidence, but of necessity – causal, metaphysical or
subjunctive. Dharmakirti’s solution to the problem of induction, then, is to
claim that observation supports a generalisation only when that generalisation
is law-like or necessary. In this, I think he anticipates the idea that the distinction
between law-like and accidental generalisations is that only the former support
the counter-factual ‘if the reason property were instantiated here, so would be
the target property’. In such a context, let us note, the observation of even a
single positive example might sometimes be sufficient to warrant the
extrapolation: I infer that any mango is sweet having tasted a single mango;
I infer that any fire will burn having once been burnt.
Reduction, exclusion and rational reconstruction
123
Extrapolation from a number of observed instances is warranted when the
reason–target relation is law-like. What Dharmakirti has succeeded in doing
is to describe the conditions under which extrapolation works – the conditions
under which one’s actions, were they to be in accordance with the extrapolation,
would meet with success. It is a description of the type of circumstance in
which extrapolation is rewarded (i.e. is true – if, as it seems, Dharmakirti has
a pragmatic theory of truth38). As to how, when or whether one can know that
one is in such a circumstance, that is another problem altogether and not one
that Dharmakirti has necessarily to address. For a general theory of rationality
issues in conditions of the form ‘in circumstances C, it is rational to do φ,’ or
‘in circumstances C, it is rational to believe p.’ And this is precisely the form
Dharmakirti’s conditions take.
4.10 THE PROBLEM OF GROUNDING
The idea of a ‘support’ or ‘ground’ (alambana) is a very significant one. We
have already seen that Nagarjuna’s philosophical method consists in an
attempt to prove the supportlessness of thought. A thought is supported if it
has empirical content, if it makes a claim about some objective state of
affairs. Supportless thoughts are empty fictions – like the magician’s illusion,
the dream or the hologram. So an explanation of the notion of ‘support’ is an
account of what it is for mental states to have informational content. Now
Dinnaga, in an early work entitled The Examination of Supports,39 offered an
astute definition of the notion of a support for a perceptual experience. He
said that the support is both the cause and the content of a thought. An entity
is a support
because it has the form of the awareness itself and because it is the causal
condition of the awareness. (AP 6cd)
Somethin g is the support of a thought only if it satisfies the following ‘matching’
condition:
An entity x supports a thought y iff
(i) x is among the set of causes of y, and
(ii) x is in the representational content of y.
A hallucination has a representational content (for example, dagger-like), but
is caused, not by any dagger, but by aberrances of the perceptual system. The
same is true of a perception of a rainbow – it is caused, not by great arcs of
colour in the sky, but by droplets of water. If a thought is to be supported,
there must be a match between its cause and its content. The object mentioned
in the causal explanation of a thought’s occurrence must be alike in form with
what is represented in its content.40
124
Philosophy in classical India
In the Examination of Supports, Dinnaga’s aim is to defend the
Abhidharmika thesis that thought is not supported by anything external, but
by ‘internal’ objects of awareness. While Madhyamika argues that nothing of
the sort which appears in thought is relevant to the causal explanation of
thought (the notion of a support is supportless), the Abhidharmika argues for
an explanatory closure within the domain of thought. An adequate causal
explanation of the arrangement and succession of thoughts can be given without
reference to anything external to thought itself. Dinnaga’s double criterion
seemed to allow him to draw the same conclusion:
Those who believe that the supports of the types of awareness such as the
visual are external objects propose either that the supports are atoms,
since atoms are the material cause of the awareness, or that the supports
are collections of atoms, since awareness occurs with the appearance
thereof. About that view, I say first of all
even if atoms are the material cause of the sensory phenomenon, the
atoms are not its field of operation (visaya), because the phenomenon
no more has the appearance of atoms than it has the appearance of
the sense-faculty. (AP 1 a–d)
The so-called ‘field of operation’ is that whose character awareness
ascertains, because it is what causes awareness to arise. But atoms,
although they are the material cause of awareness, are not that whose
character awareness ascertains, in the same way that the sense-faculty is
not that whose character awareness ascertains. And so, to begin with,
atoms are not the supports. As for the collection, although it is that whose
appearance awareness has,
the phenomenon does not come from that whose appearance it has.
(AP 2a)
It is correct that the support is whatever object generates the awareness of
its own appearance, for it was taught thus as a causal condition of the
occurrence [of awareness]. But the collection is not what generates the
awareness of its own appearance,
because, like the second moon, it does not really exist. (AP 2b)
In seeing a second moon, owing to a deficient sense-faculty, although
there is the appearance of a second moon, that is not its field of operation.
Similarly, a collection, although it is the material cause of awareness, is
not the support, because it does not exist.
Thus neither external object can be the field of operation of awareness.
(AP 2cd)
The support is neither the external object called the atoms nor the external
object called the collection of atoms, because each of these is deficient in
some respect.
Reduction, exclusion and rational reconstruction
125
Cause, but not content, content, but not cause – nothing external can meet the
matching condition. An object such as a vase or a table is in composition
merely an aggregate of atoms. The atoms no doubt cause the perception as of
a vase, but what we see is not a cluster of atoms. What we see is a solid,
extended body, but no such thing is the cause of the perception. But, Dinnaga
goes on to argue, something internal can satisfy both conditions simultaneously,
namely, that ‘internal cognisable form which represents itself as external’.
This is how, in his early period, he tries to defend the Abhidharma
phenomenalism.
What becomes of the problem of grounding in Dinnaga’s new system, the
system of the Collection on Knowing? The factorisation of content into nonconceptual perceptual content and non-perceptual conceptual content – and a
corresponding factorisation in the domain of things – seems to result in a
trivialisation of the notion of a support. Perception is of an object (= a class of
concurrent tropes), and caused by the means of apprehending concurrence,
viz. multiple sensory contact. Conception is of a property (= a class of exactly
similar tropes), and caused by the means of apprehending exact similarity,
viz. inference. The new system is structured from the very outset in such a
way that there is no substantive problem of matching cause and content. One
could be forgiven for thinking that the problem of grounding has been solved
(or dissolved) only at the expense of introducing an unbridgeable gap between
the domains of perception and conception, domains in order to relate which
one would need some notion akin to Dharmakirti’s ‘perceptual judgment’, a
post-perceptual cognition which makes a perceived object available to
conceptual content.41
Dinnaga, however, is emphatic that there is no special problem of combining
objects and properties in judgment, or of repeatedly recognising one and the
same object; nor is any new means of knowing needed.42 And I think he is
right to be adamant about this. For we must be careful to distinguish between
the claim that perceptual objects are not constructed by conception, and the
different claim that they are not available as contents of conceptual thought.
Objects are non-conceptual only in the sense that they are not classes of
exactly similar tropes, and so not constructed by conceptual or linguistic
operations. It would follow that they are not available to thought only if one
thinks of them as being something along the lines of an uninterpretable ‘given’.
In fact, however, the trope-theoretic analysis shows that we should not think
of the objects and properties in Dinnaga’s system as belonging to distinct
ontological domains at all. They are simply groupings along different axes in
a single two-dimensional space of tropes. Regions in this space are marked
out in different ways by perception and conception, but once marked out,
they are equally available as contents of judgment.
Between the additive realism of Nyaya-Vaisesika and Dinnaga’s Buddhist
reductionism, it would seem that there is profound philosophical disagreement.
On the old and intractable problem of persistence and change, especially,
there is a strong divergence in inclination, intuition and emphasis. Nyaya-
126
Philosophy in classical India
Vaisesika conceives of a stable world whose objects persist by being wholly
present at different times and change in the gain, loss and replacement of
qualities and motions. Quite different is the world of Dinnaga’s Buddhism, a
world of change in which objects are merely tropes gathered into sums, and
persistence is a matter only of sequence. In this clash of opposites, can it
really be true that one is right and the other wrong? Surely there must be a
grain of truth in the intuitions that drive both, a real insight that exaggeration
has turned into dogma. This belief in the possibility of philosophical
rapprochement is what drives the Jaina search for a rationality of reconciliation.
Not least for this reason, Jaina theory has an ineliminable place in Indian
philosophical theory. I examine the Jaina analysis in Chapter 5, before turning
in Chapter 6 to the problem that has lain before so much of our discussion –
is any form of rational activity itself rationally justified? Is the pursuit of
reason a reasonable pursuit?
FURTHER READING
Texts
Dinnaga c. AD 480–540, Pramanasamuccaya (PS, Collection on Knowing).
Dinnaga, Hetucakradamaru (HC, Chart of Reasons).
Dharmakirti c. AD 600–660, Pramanavarttika (PV, Commentary on Knowing).
Dharmakirti, Nyayabindu (NB).
Metaphysics and epistemology (4.1–3)
1
Masaaki Hattori, Dignaga, On Perception, being the Pratyaksapariccheda
of Dignaga’s Pramanasamuccaya from the Sanskrit fragments and the Tibetan
versions (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1968).
2
Richard Hayes, Dignaga on the Interpretation of Signs (Dordrecht:
Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1988).
3
B. K. Matilal and J. G. D. Evans eds., Buddhist Logic and
Epistemology: Studies in the Buddhist Analysis of Inference and Language
(Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1982).
4
Bimal Matilal, Perception (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), Chapters
7, 10.
Language, meaning, exclusion (4.4–6)
1
Katsura Shoryu, ‘Dignaga and Dharmakirti on apoha,’ in E.
Steinkellner ed., Studies in the Buddhist Epistemological Tradition (Vienna:
Österreichische Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1991), pp. 129–146.
2
Hattori Masaaki, ‘The Sautrantika Background of the apoha Theory,’
in Leslie S. Kawamura and Keith Scott eds., Buddhist Thought and Civilization:
Essays in Honour of Herbert V. Guenther on his Sixtieth Birthday (Emeryville:
Dharma Press, 1977), pp. 47–58.
Reduction, exclusion and rational reconstruction
127
3
Hattori Masaaki, ‘Apoha and Pratibha,’ in M. Nagatomi et al. eds.
Sanskrit and Indian Studies: Essays in Honour of Daniel H. H. Ingalls
(Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1980), pp. 61–74.
4
Bimal Matilal, Perception (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), Chapter
12.
5
Jonardon Ganeri, ‘Dharmakirti’s Semantics for the Particle eva (only),’
in Shoryu Katsura ed., Dharmakirti’s Thought and Its Impact on Indian and
Tibetan Philosophy (Vienna: Österreichische Akademie der Wissenschaften,
1999), pp. 101–116.
Extrapolation, the triple condition (4.7–9)
1
Katsura Shoryu, ‘Dignaga on trairupya,’ Journal of Indian and
Buddhist Studies 32 (1983), pp. 15–21.
2
Bimal Matilal, ‘Buddhist Logic and Epistemology,’ in B. K. Matilal
and R. D. Evans eds., Buddhist Logic and Epistemology: Studies in the Buddhist
Analysis of Inference and Language (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company,
1982), pp. 1–30; reprinted in his The Character of Logic in India (Albany:
State University of New York Press, 1998), Chapter 4.
3
Tom F. Tillemans, ‘On sapaksa,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 18
(1990), pp. 53–80.
4
Claus Oetke, Studies on the Doctrine of trairupya (Vienna: Wiener
Studien fur Tibetologie und Buddhismuskunde, 1993).
5
Motoi Ono, ‘Dharmakirti on asasarananaikantika,’ in Shoryu Katsura
ed., Dharmakirti’s Thought and Its Impact on Indian and Tibetan Philosophy
(Vienna: Österreichische Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1999), pp. 301–316.
6
Richard Hayes, ‘On the Reinterpretation of Dharmakirti’s
svabhavahetu,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 15 (1987), pp. 319–332.
5 Rationality, harmony and
perspective
5.1 A RATIONALITY OF RECONCILIATION
The rationality of the debating hall is confrontational. It is a winner-takes-all
rationality. In the purest form of debate, victory consists in adducing such a
reason as proves the truth of one’s thesis and so the falseness of one’s opponent’s.
To be sure, in the debating model, the end of reason is the resolution of a
conflict. But there are limits on the extent to which that end is in practice
achieved. The ancient philosophical controversies – is there permanence or
only change? is the soul immortal? is the world finite or infinite? – seem to
persist through all argument. They represent a deeper, more embedded level
of commitment, intractable to the up-front reasoning of debate and argument.
If the end of reason is harmony, then a new model of rationality is required.
The search for a rationality of reconciliation is the programme of the Jaina
philosophers in India. There is, they say, a core of truth in every deeply held
metaphysical belief. But what more dogmatic philosophers fail to realise is
that there are hidden parameters in belief and assertion. The conflict that
arises when thesis and antithesis are opposed is a spurious one. It is a conflict
based on a failure to recognise that the thesis is true when certain hidden
parameters have one set of values, the antithesis true when they have another.
Failure to recognise that all assertion is parameterised is now to be exposed
as a deep philosophical error. It leads to dogmatism and one-sidedness. It is
an error embedded in the ordinary concept of assertion. A new model of
rationality is needed, a new method whose function is to subvert the way
ordinary language works, a technique which makes explicit the hidden
parameters in assertion and so enables the reasoner to harmonise apparently
conflicting beliefs. Harmony, the proper goal of reason, follows when we
realise that most of the time there is no genuine conflict.
5.2 THE MANY-SIDED NATURE OF THINGS
How does one construct an ontology which begs no metaphysical question? It
must be an ontology flexible enough to respect the core of truth in all – even
Rationality, harmony and perspective
129
opposing – metaphysical theories. Objects in Jaina ontology are held, first
and foremost, to be ‘many sided’ (anekanta). We have already seen how
Dinnaga exploits the idea that an object has many properties in his argument
that no process of cognising which grasps an object through its properties can
grasp the object in its entirety (Chapter 4.4). There was, though, no implication
there that a single object could be the bearer of both members of a pair of
conflicting properties. Indeed, for the Buddhist, conflicting properties must
have different loci – the dissolution of contradiction is a dissolution of the
object itself as a single bearer of multiple properties. That is not rapprochement,
but separatism.
Haribhadra1 (c. AD 800) sheds considerable light on the nature of the
doctrine of many-sidedness when he redescribes it as a theory of the
manifoldness of every real entity, as a theory of integration, and as a theory
of the entanglement and intermixture of conflicting aspects. The goal of reason
is harmony, and harmony consists in an integration of information from a
diversity of sources. The Jainas will say that, at the limit, integration leads to
the acquisition of complete knowledge of things. What is not yet clear is
whether completeness must imply totality – knowledge of everything about
the object – with the problems attendant upon such an idea of omniscience, or
if not, where the epistemic boundaries of integration lie. This is a question we
shall be able to answer only when the mechanics of rapprochement are
understood.
Persistence and change are twin poles in the concept of an object. An
object is something that persists through change, and something that changes
even though persisting. The view that objects exist only in a state of change is
as one-sided as the view that they are only stable and enduring. The truth is
that things are both constants and variables. Identifying the stable and enduring
nature of a thing with its ‘substance’ (dravya) aspect, and the changing nature
of a thing with its ‘modification’ (paryaya) aspect, the Jaina analysis is that
an object is a thing whose nature is to be both substance and modification. An
object is an inextricable mixture of being and becoming. Hemacandra (AD
1089–1172), a versatile philosopher and biographer2 of the Jaina elders, invents
an etymology to bring out the intended contrast:3
The domain of a means of knowing is an object, the nature of which is to
be substance and modification. (PM 1.1.30)
(para. 118) . . . The word ‘substance’ (dravya) is derived from [the verb]
‘to run’ (dru) – it is that which runs through the modifications. It is thus
the head commonality running through and grounding the connection
between earlier and later changing states. Modifications are states of
change. They are what change and they exist in the two properties of
arising and ceasing. An object, the nature of which is to be substance and
modification, is one whose nature is that [running through] and those two
[arising and ceasing]. This is what is meant by ‘objectively real’
130
Philosophy in classical India
(paramarthasat). As it is said in the canonical text of Vacaka, ‘the real is
what is linked with persistence, origin and decay.’
The reference is to sutra 5.29 of Vacaka Umasvati’s Tattvarthasutra. Y. J.
Padmarajiah4 has said with justifiable exaggeration that sutra 5.29 is ‘[t]he
most celebrated text the implications of which form almost the entire theoretical
foundation of the Jaina philosophy of being.’ The juxtaposition of the twin
polarities of persistence and change in a single definition is meant to confront
all one-sided definitions. Hemacandra again:
Here, by including the phrase ‘substance and modification’, the ideas of
those who have a one-sided substance theory and those who have a onesided modification theory are blocked. By including the phrase ‘nature of
which’, the belief of the Yauga [=Vaisesika] school of Kanada that substance
and modification are completely different is blocked. As it is said by
Siddhasena,5 ‘Uluka [=Kanada] has built his system in pursuance of both
respects, yet it is vitiated by falsity, because he has advocated that substance
and modification are mutually independent and that each is supreme in
its own sphere.’ (PM 1.1.30, para. 119)
The idea is that an object is neither that whose nature is to persist, nor that
whose nature is to change – it is something in which persistence and change
are intertwined. It is a centre of origin, endurance and decay. This integration
of opposites within a single entity is what blocks one-sided views of the nature
of a thing and sustains an inclusive conception in which different partial
views can be reconciled.
5.3 DISAGREEMENT DEFUSED
If the theory really is that a single object is the bearer of conflicting properties
(such as origin and decay, stability and flux, generality and specificity), does
it not fall into contradiction? The criticism is pressed by Samkara6 and by the
Buddhist Santaraksita.7 The thoroughness of the Jaina philosophers leads them
to consider contradiction as but one of a list (usually of eight) potential defects
in their theory. Let me follow Hemacandra once more:
[Opponent:] The syadvada [= Jaina] theory, rejecting as one-sided both
the identity and the non-identity of [an object with] substance and
modification, allows somehow both identity and non-identity. But this is
not reasonable, for there are faults such as that of contradiction (virodha).
(1) There cannot be both the assertion and denial [of identity or nonidentity] with respect to a single object, just as [it cannot be both]
blue and non-blue.
Rationality, harmony and perspective
131
(2) Suppose the identity is [asserted] in some respect, and the non-identity
is [asserted] in some respect – then the identity has one locus and the
non-identity a different locus; so there is the fallacy of a division of
loci.
(3) One-sidedness is granted otherwise than if those two things, one in
which identity has been placed and the other in which non-identity
has been placed, are [themselves said to be] both identical and
different – that being so, the fallacy of a regress [follows].
(4) The respect in which there is non-identity is one of both identity and
non-identity, and the respect in which there is non-identity is also
one of both identity and non-identity – [this is] a fallacy of crossmixing.
(5) Non-identity is the respect in which there is identity, and identity is
the respect in which there is non-identity – [this is] a fallacy of
reciprocal dependence.
(6) Since it is impossible to determine a distinct respect for an object
whose nature is one of both identity and non-identity, [there will
occur] the fallacy of doubt.
(7) Then too follows the fallacy of non-ascertainment.
(8) Then the fallacy of no establishment of an object [also follows]. (PM
1.1.32, para. 130)
The most serious problem is contradiction, of which indeed the others are
merely corollaries. Thus objects as bearers of contradictory properties lack
determinate identity conditions (a fault perhaps akin to the medieval logicians’
doctrine that ‘anything follows from a contradiction’). The faults are countered
by an appeal to common sense. Hemacandra continues:
[Reply:] This is not so, for an object actually brought to mind cannot be
contradictory. One thing is the contradictory of another when, if present,
the other is not found – this is well attested. When an object is actually
found, what space is there for even a whiff of contradiction? Even as
regard blue and non-blue, if [indeed] found in one place, then there is no
contradiction. For the Buddhists do not admit there to be a contradiction
between blue and non-blue in a cognition of a cloth’s mixed colours in
one and the same place, while the Vaisesikas admit there to be a single,
mixed, colour. And if contradictory properties like moving and nonmoving, red and non-red, covered and non-covered are found in a single
cloth, is there even a whiff of doubt about [the presence of] a contradiction?
By this means, the fault of division of loci is set aside, for as has already
been said, the two are cognised in a single locus. . . . [The other faults too
are set aside in a similar way] . . . and so our claim that an object has the
nature of both substance and modification is not contradicted either by
what is perceived or by what is wished for. (PM 1.1.32, para. 130)
132
Philosophy in classical India
The problem of a cloth with mixed colours embarrassed the Buddhist and
Nyaya-Vaisesika metaphysicians alike. The problem is to say what colour is
the cloth, when some parts are one colour and others another, without attributing
to the cloth contradictory colours. The Buddhist solution is to deny that one
can meaningfully ascribe any colour to the cloth at all. Some threads have
one colour, other threads have the other, and nothing has both. There is no
common substratum of different colours (Chapter 4.2–3). The standard NyayaVaisesika solution is that the cloth has a single new colour, produced by the
mixing together of the pure colours of its parts (Chapter 3.6). The cloth is
coloured, but has just one mixed colour, not two contradictory ones.
Hemacandra reasons differently. One colour contradicts another only if the
first is never found where the second is present. We do find different colours in
one and the same piece of cloth. So the different colours cannot be
contradictory! The moral seems to be that extreme views falsify common
sense. It is better to follow common sense and let the problems fall where they
will. Objects are by nature subject to both stability and instability, to
modification and non-modification – these are the facts which cannot be denied.
So stability and instability cannot after all be contradictory properties,
appearances notwithstanding.
At stake is the notion of contradiction itself. When are two properties in
contradiction? The Jaina answer is that two properties are in contradiction
just in case one is ‘not found’ where the other is. Two properties are not in
contradiction simply because one is truly assertible of an object and the other
is truly deniable. We will see, however, that denial for the Jaina is assertion of
the negation (Chapter 5.5). So the claim is that the statements ‘Fa’ and ‘notFa’ are not contradictory, even though the statement ‘Fa & not-Fa’ is a
contradiction! One can truly assert that the pot exists and, without contradiction,
truly assert that it does not exist. But one cannot truly assert that the pot exists
and does not exist. What we need is a way to make sense of this idea.
Two strategies for analysing out contradictions are disallowed by the
integrationist. One is to break apart the object into plural subjects of
predication, so that no one object has both properties. The other is to merge
the properties into a single new predicate. In both of these approaches, the
metaphysics is revisionary rather than reconciliatory. The Jainas want a new
technique for the dissolution of contradictions, one which remains true to
common sense. The new idea is that there are hidden parameters in assertion.
It is then possible both to assert and deny that an object has a certain property,
because the hidden parameters have different values in each case. The basic
idea can be seen already in the way Mahavira, the founder of Jainism, explains
the questions the Buddha refused to answer:8
According to substance, the world has an end; according to space, the
world has an end; according to time, the world has no end; according to
state, the world has no end.
Rationality, harmony and perspective
133
The world has an end and does not have an end. Why is this not a contradiction?
It is because the assertion ‘the world has an end’ is not yet complete – it
requires for completion one of the four ‘determinants’ that constitute a canonical
niksepa, viz. substance (davva), place (khetta), time (kala) and state (bhava).
The substance of the world is not endless, neither is its spatial extent; but it
has no beginning or end in time and has endless states or properties. The
point to stress is that the idea is not that an expression such as ‘end’ is
ambiguous. A possible strategy for defusing the apparent contradiction would
be to say that ‘an end’ means ‘a spatial boundary’ and ‘no end’ means ‘no
temporal boundary’. The apparently contradictory statement would not, after
all, ascribe conflicting properties to a single object. This is another inadmissible
way of defusing the contradiction – it is a sort of incommensurability thesis,
in which one denies that the two parties are in genuine conflict on the ground
that their uses of the terms have different meanings. There is no disagreement
here, but there is no agreement (common subject matter) either.
The Jaina idea is rather that an expression has a hidden indexical element
within its meaning. The idea is semantically respectable and the phenomenon
has been studied in detail both by classical Indian9 and modern10 semantic
theorists. If one wants to say that the term ‘today’ is unambiguous, even
though its reference changes from one day to the next, what one has to do is
to find some constant element in the meaning, an element that determines the
reference on any occasion of use. A natural way to think of the common
element is as a function from contexts or indices to referents. Thus the constant
meaning of the term ‘today’ is the function expressed by ‘the referent of an
utterance of “today” is the day on which the utterance is made.’ Of course,
there is nothing hidden about the indexicality of ‘today’. But the indexicality
of other expressions is disguised. Incomplete definite descriptions are an
important case.11 A description such as ‘the house’ is not ambiguous, even
though it denotes different houses on different occasions – there is a hidden
indexicality in its meaning.
The paradigmatic idea, that contradictions can be defused by discovering
a hidden parameterisation in their statement, is encoded in the post-canonical
literature in two specific theories. One is the theory of standpoints (nayavada),
the other the theory of the conditionalisation of assertion (syadvada). The
first gives the epistemology, the second the semantics. I will examine each
technique in detail, but one thing is already clear. The source of conflict and
disagreement lies in the use of language. It is not that the parties to a controversy
talk at cross-purposes or mean different things by their assertions. The point
of the Jaina dialectic is that the language used by each party is underspecific
– it fails fully to specify the proposition being expressed. What each party
states is not false but incompletely specific. Rationality, in the hands of the
Jaina, is a method for exposing the underspecification implicit in ordinary
language use. When this is properly done, conflict and contradiction drop
away of their own accord.
134
Philosophy in classical India
5.4 THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF PERSPECTIVE
Tattvarthasutra 1.6 is another fundamental verse: ‘acquiring [knowledge] is
through a means of knowing (pramana) or a perspective (naya)’. The traditional
epistemic processes – perception, inference, testimony and so on – are not the
only methods of acquiring knowledge. There is another way. A naya is a
perspective, a point of view, a standpoint, an angle, a take, an attitude. The
intended contrast is between a method that gives complete (sakaladesa)
knowledge of the object and a method that gives only partial (vikaladesa)
knowledge. There may be ways of acquiring complete knowledge of an object,
knowledge of every fact about it. If such there be, they are not the ways of
acquiring knowledge normally employed. For if an object has many facets,
how can one know the whole truth about it? Siddhasena:12
An object whose nature is to be many-sided is the content of complete
knowledge.
The field of a naya is a thing qualified by one aspect. (NA 29)
Complete knowledge is knowledge of everything about the object, partial
knowledge the knowledge of something about it. As a metaphor from the
Tattvarthaslokavarttika13 has it, just as a part of the ocean is not the whole of
the ocean, but neither is it something other than the ocean, so too a naya is
not a pramana, but neither is it something other than a pramana.
Crucial to the Jaina concept of a naya (a perspective, a method of
acquiring partial knowledge) is the idea that the knowledge of one aspect of
the object does not exclude knowledge of its other aspects. The traditional
philosophical systems, to be sure, encode partial knowledge about the nature
of things, but each does so in a way that implies the others are wrong. That
makes each of them a ‘pseudo-method’ (nayabhasa). The intended distinction
concerns the validity of the following epistemological principle: ‘If one knows
that a is F then one does not know that a is not F.’ This principle states that
the knowledge that an object has a property entails knowledge that it does
not have the contrary property. But if one can truly assert and deny F of an
object, because there are hidden parameters on assertion and denial, then
this principle must be invalid. Knowing that an object has a certain property
does not imply that one is not in a position to know that it also does not
have the property. The theory of standpoints is a doctrine of epistemic
openness. The philosophical error to which the traditional schools are prone
is one of mistaking methods of acquiring partial knowledge for methods of
acquiring complete knowledge, and so of failing to recognise the nature of
the knowledge they have. The way to complete knowledge is through the
accumulation and integration of partial knowledge – collating all the facts
about a single object and defusing apparent contradictions by an evaluation
of the hidden parameters.
Rationality, harmony and perspective
135
There are traditionally said to be seven different types of standpoint. They
are: (1) naigama, the indiscriminate; (2) samgraha, the collective; (3)
vyavahara, the practical; (4) rjusutra, the straight to what is manifest; (5)
sabda, the verbal; (6) samabhirudha, the subtle; (7) evambhuta, the actual. It
is usual to group the first three together as substance-affirming, and the
remainder as modification-affirming. One type relates to a level at which we
emphasise general, universal features, the other to a level at which particulars
and differentiations are highlighted. Another grouping is also found, in which
the first four are classified together as metaphysical (artha-naya), while the
last three are linguistic (sabda-naya). Paul Dundas14 has summarised the
traditional division:
The first three relate to the fact that entities must in ontological terms be
interpreted as being conjoined either with both general and specific
properties, or with general properties only, or with specific properties
only. The fourth naya relates to entities as necessarily rooted in the present
when judgements are being made about them, while the last three
demonstrate the manner in which language is implicated in ontological
analysis. Thus, according to the fifth and sixth nayas, verbal statements
have to be carefully differentiated on the basis both of an understanding
of the way in which their sense can be modified through tense and
grammatical inflection, and through a consideration of the etymology of
words as a means of gaining information about their meaning or nuance.
The seventh naya delimits individual words to one particular meaning:
that is, a word only has its proper meaning when something is carrying
out the function designated by it.
Let us look in more detail. The ‘indiscriminate’ reflects a broad level of
metaphysical description in which all the features of an object, general or
particular, are represented and ordered. No distinction is made between
substance and attribute, or between an attribute and an attribute of that attribute.
It is the position, perhaps, of someone who is concerned merely to catalogue
what there is, without worrying about the different kinds of thing. Such a
position becomes misguided only when turned into a dogmatic assertion that
such categorial distinctions are bogus. The ‘collective’ is a level of description
at which we pay attention only to the most general commonalties between
things. We ignore the specific properties which distinguish one thing from
another, but note, for example, that everything shares the property of being
an existent. When adopted dogmatically, not as just one possible standpoint,
this attitude leads to monistic metaphysics of, for instance, Advaita Vedanta.
The ‘practical’ is the complement of the ‘collective’, stressing the special
distinguishing features of things, and classifying them under a variety of
headings suitable for practical activities. It becomes a dogmatic pseudo-standpoint when bogus distinctions are invented, or real distinctions are denied.
The Jainas place the Carvaka ‘materialists’ in the latter group.
136
Philosophy in classical India
The ‘straight to what is manifest’ is a level of metaphysical description
which pays attention only to what is present, or what is perceived in the
present time. It takes as primitive the immediate givens, such as presently
occurring pleasure or pain sensations. When such a view is taken to be the
correct method, it leads to a typically phenomenalist stance, an attempt to
reduce talk of enduring substances, etc. to talk about sense-data or the logical
atoms of present experience. As a dogmatically held pseudo-standpoint, it is
the doctrine adopted by two Buddhist factions, the Sautrantikas and the
Yogacarins.
The previous four standpoints have all been concerned with the question
of what sorts of object we should take as basic in our metaphysics. The last
three standpoints concern instead their proper linguistic expression. Each
picks out certain syntactic categories which, it is claimed, reflect underlying
semantic distinctions. The ‘verbal’ standpoint is one in which differences in
grammatical inflection (tense, number and gender) are held to have a semantic
basis. Thus a sentence such as ‘The Sumeru mountain used to exist’ means
something different from ‘The Sumeru mountain will exist’. Clearly, taking
tense, gender and number to be indicators of semantic distinctions will have
consequences for the sort of metaphysics we construct. In the standpoint
called the ‘subtle’, we make a ‘subtle’ etymological distinction between the
meanings of words, even if they refer to the same object. For example,
‘Indra’ (so-called because possessing sovereign authority) and ‘Sakra’ (socalled because possessing mighty power) both refer to the lord of the gods.
The ‘subtle’ attends to the difference in their meanings; the ‘verbal’ to the
identity in their referents.
Finally, the ‘actual’. Many words have ‘functional’ meanings – they
refer to objects on the basis of a kind of capacity the object instantiates, or
function which the object can perform. For example, ‘cook’ refers to someone
who has the capacity to cook, ‘swimmer’ to someone who has the capacity
to swim. According to this standpoint, we should use such terms only
when the object is actually performing its function, and not at other times.
If we wish to construct a metaphysics in which objects are picked out by
means of the capacities and powers they possess, we use here names which
pick out the objects when they are actually exercising the capacity. Thus,
we only call someone ‘a cook’ when that person is actually cooking.
What is interesting is to see how later Jainas rationalise the list. Here is the
proposal endorsed by the systematising Yasovijaya (c. AD 1650).15 Thought
of as levels of description, the order is one of increasing specificity. The first
describes everything, whether existent or non-existent. The second describes
only existents, but describes all existents. The third describes only the existence
of a single particular, but does so at all times. The fourth describes only the
existence of a particular at the present time, but allows any name of that
particular. The fifth describes only the existence of a particular at the present
time under a name, but under any co-referring name. The sixth describes only
the existence of a particular at the present time under a single specific name.
Rationality, harmony and perspective
137
The seventh describes only the existence of a particular at the present time
under a single name of a specific sort, one which denotes via the actions the
thing is capable of performing.
The move, I think, is in the direction of a discourse pluralism, an acceptance
that there is a plurality of irreducible kinds of language use, organised into a
vertical hierarchy. 16 The descriptions are neither incompatible nor
incommensurable, but represent different levels of talk about the same domain
of things.
5.5 THE LOGIC OF ASSERTION
Two models of assertion have been in play in the earlier chapters of this
book. On one model, the primary assertoric force of a statement in the
declarative mode is inclusive. To say of a thing that it is an F is to include
that thing in the class of things satisfying some condition. This is the classical
model, developed by the Nyaya-Vaisesika philosophers. The other model is
Dinnaga’s. A concept delimits a class by exclusion. Its extension is a class of
objects not failing some condition. Denial, not assertion, is the primary
assertoric force of a statement. To say of a thing that it is F is to exclude it
from what is other than F. The difference between these two models lies in
their respective ontological commitments – only the first, allegedly, is
committed to the existence of a real property all Fs share. The two models
nevertheless rest on a common assumption. This is the assumption that
assertion and denial are exclusive. One cannot consistently both assert and
deny that the thing is F.
This assumption is the target of the Jaina integrationist meaning theory.
For if one can develop a theory in which assertion does not exclude denial,
then one can make respectable the leading Jaina insight, that one philosophical
truth does not exclude its rival. Vadideva Suri (twelfth century AD) presents
the developed Jaina theory:17
A word, always expressing its own meaning through assertion and denial,
follows a seven-fold division. (PNTA, 4.13)
The formal similarity between this statement and Dinnaga’s celebrated thesis
(Chapter 4.5) is striking:18
Because [a word] expresses its own meaning through the exclusion of
others.
It is clear that the intention is to develop a theory of meaning parallel to
Dinnaga’s, but without commitment to the troublesome presupposition that
assertion and denial are exclusive. Assertion and denial are non-exclusive
because of the hidden parameters with respect to which each is made, in
virtue of which one can consistently assert that the object is F (with respect to
138
Philosophy in classical India
one set of parameter-values) but deny that it is F (with respect to another set).
But what is this ‘seven-fold division’ (saptabhangi)? Vadideva Suri again:
A seven-fold division is the use of a statement in seven ways, [each]
marked by the particle ‘somehow’ (syat), made without contradiction out
of assertion and denial, either combined or separated, with respect to an
inquiry about just one property in a single object. (PNTA 4.14)
It might seem at face value that, even if one accepts the non-exclusiveness
thesis, there are still only three ways of combining an assertion and a denial:
(1) asserting that the object is F; (2) denying that it is F; or (3) both asserting
and denying that it is F (with different values of the hidden parameters).
Suppose, however, that there is a way of combining assertion and denial ‘in
the same breath’ into a new kind of speech-act assert-deny. Whether or not
this is a genuine possibility requires careful examination. But if it is possible,
then there are seven ways of combining an assertion and a denial: (1) asserting
that the object is F; (2) denying that it is F; (3) assert-denying that it is F; (4)
both asserting and denying that it is F (with different values of the hidden
parameters); (5) both asserting and assert-denying that it is F (with different
values of the hidden parameters); (6) both denying and assert-denying that it
is F (with different values of the hidden parameters); and (7) asserting, denying
and assert-denying that it is F (with different values of the hidden parameters).
The simple combinatorial point of the Jainas seven-fold division is that there
are 2n - 1 ways to choose at least one thing from a group of n (here n = 3 and
‘thing’ = type of speech-act).
Let me postpone discussion of the viability of ‘assert-deny’ as a speech-act
(Chapter 5.6). It is not vitally important anyway – if it is not viable, then the
division ought really to be three-fold rather than seven-fold. Of much greater
interest and importance is the introduction of the conditionalising particle
‘somehow’ (syat) before any statement. Grammatically, syat is the third
person singular of the optative form of the verb vas, ‘to be’. Semantically, it
is a modal operator on a par with ‘possibly’, and, like ‘possibly’, can be
treated as an existential quantifier, ranging here not over possible worlds, but
over possible valuations of the hidden parameters. So in Jaina theory it comes
to mean ‘in some respect’, ‘in some way’, ‘for some value of the parameters
substance, place, time and state’. The effect of inserting ‘somehow’ into a
statement is precisely to suspend the normal implicative force of an assertion,
and so to free the assertion from the troublesome presupposition. R. C.
Pandeya19 has put the idea well: ‘syadvada represents a formal programme
whereby you can distinguish an exclusive statement from a non-exclusive
statement, and it is a recommendation to use all statements in a non-exclusive
sense. The scheme of saptabhangi is therefore to be taken as a device for
converting an exclusive statement into a non-exclusive statement.’
Rationality, harmony and perspective
139
How does this happen? The formal structure of an assertion is now:
(1)
syat
somehow
ghatah
the pot
asti
exists
eva
indeed.
Notice again the use of the restrictive particle eva (we have seen it before in
Chapter 4.6). Here it attaches neither to the subject nor to the predicate, but
to the verb, and its force is emphatic: the pot indeed exists. Mallisena (twelfth
century AD) explains the construction in (1):20
‘syat’ – somehow, through its own substance, place, time and state, the
pot and all indeed exists, not through another substance, place, time and
state. So a pot exists as regards substance by being made of earth, but not
by being made of water. As regards place, [it exists] by being in Paliputra,
not by being in Kanyakubja. As regards time, [it exists] by being in the
winter, not by being in the spring. As regards state, [it exists] by being
black, not by being red. Otherwise, its own nature would be lost on
account of its having the nature of another.
Assertions are evaluated only with respect to values of the four hidden
parameters. Simply to say ‘the pot exists’ is not yet to say anything. It would
be like the sentence written on a piece of paper ‘I will be coming back today’,
but with no indication as to which day the note was written or who wrote it.
The sentence is not false, but it is underspecific – it makes no statement.21 One
way to eliminate the underspecification would be to give actual values to the
hidden parameters. Another way is to quantify over those parameters. This is
the effect of the insertion of the particle ‘somehow’. The incomplete assertion
‘the pot exists’ is now transformed into the complete assertion ‘with respect to
some substance, place, time and state, the pot exists.’ And of course, once we
have made clear that this is the logical form of the assertion, it is obvious that
the assertion might be true with respect to one set of parameter-values and
false with respect to a different set.
One can think of ‘somehow’ as a kind of assertion sign. The unmodified
statement ‘the pot exists’ expresses a dummy proposition ‘the pot exists at s,
x, t, p’. There are many different sorts of assertion one can make with this
dummy proposition. One can assert that it is true for some set of parametervalues, without saying anything about its truth or falsity at other values. This
is the assertoric force carried by the ‘somehow’ sign. A different sign might
have indicated a different assertoric force – that the proposition is true for
every set of parameter-values, that it is true for only some set, and so on.
What about denial? The second member of the seven-fold division is a
denial that the pot exists. It is represented by the construction:
(2)
syat
somehow
ghatah
the pot
na
not
asti
exists
eva
indeed.
140
Philosophy in classical India
Denial, then, is assertion of a sentential negation – to deny that an object is F
is to assert that it is not the case that the object is F. The denial-negation has
narrow scope with respect to the assertion sign ‘somehow’. Because this is a
quantifier over parameter-values, it is possible both to assert and to deny that
the object is F, giving the third construction:
(3)
syat
somehow
na
not
asti
exists
ghatah
the pot
asti
exists
eva
indeed,
syat
somehow
ghatah
the pot
eva
indeed.
There is a set of values at which it is F and a set of values at which it is not the
case that it is F. The difference between the second and third positions in the
seven-fold division is this. The assertoric force of a straight denial is that the
proposition is false for some set of values without saying anything about its
truth or falsity at other values. The assertoric force carried in the third position
is that the proposition is true for some, but only some, set of values – true at
some, false at others. The point is that it is possible to assert that the pot
exists, to deny that it exists, and both to assert and to deny that it exists, and
that these are three different speech acts with different assertoric forces. Each
says something not said by either of the other two.
We find reading (3) of the third construction in the later Jainas, such as
Vadideva Suri, Hemacandra and Mallisena. But in some earlier Jaina writings
(and following them unfortunately in a good deal of the contemporary literature),
we find the third position represented as:
(3*)
syat
somehow
ghatah
the pot
asti
exists
na
not
asti
Exists
eva
indeed.
What this would assert is that there is a set of parameter-values with respect
to which the pot both exists and does not exist. That is genuinely contradictory,
and so makes no assertion at all.
The move to the proper formulation is an important advance in the Jaina
understanding of the logic of assertion. It brings the Jaina theory into line
with the idea behind non-adjunctive logics of discourse. Graham Priest et al.22
conjecture that ‘the Jains anticipate contemporary discursive logic, initiated
by Jaskowski.’ I believe this conjecture is correct. A single quotation from
Jaskowski23 will be sufficient for our present purposes:
To bring out the nature of the theses in such a system it would be proper
to precede each thesis by the reservation: ‘in accordance with the opinion
of one of the participants in the discourse’ or ‘for a certain admissible
meaning of the terms used’. Hence the joining of a thesis to a discursive
system has a different intuitive meaning than has assertion in an ordinary
Rationality, harmony and perspective
141
system. Discursive assertion includes an implicit reservation of the kind
specified . . .
The adjunction rule states that ‘A & B’ is entailed by ‘A’ and ‘B’. But as we
have seen, what we need is to be able to assert ‘Fa’ and assert ‘not Fa’ without
being committed to asserting ‘Fa & not Fa’. Embedding assertion within a
modal operator is a standard way to get this result in a non-adjunctive logic,
and ‘somehow’ has exactly the same function in the Jaina theory.
5.6 ASSERTION AND THE UNASSERTIBLE
Is it possible to assert that the pot exists and in the same ‘breath’ or speech-act
(saharpana) deny that it exists? According to the Jainas, this represents a
genuine possibility. Since denial is defined to be the assertion of negation, the
possibility envisaged is one of asserting that the pot exists and asserting ‘in
the same act’ that it does not exist. We have already seen that the alleged
possibility cannot be that of asserting that there is a set of parameter-values
with respect to which the pot both exists and does not exist. The Jainas say
that what one asserts in an ‘assert-deny’ speech-act is that the pot is unassertible!
They represent the new possibility with the construction:
(4)
syat
somehow
ghatah
the pot
avaktavyam
unassertible
eva
indeed.
Matilal24 expresses a popular view when he says that ‘the direct and unequivocal
challenge to the notion of contradiction in standard logic comes when it is
claimed that the same proposition is both true and false at the same time in
the same sense. This is exactly accomplished by the introduction of the third
value “inexpressible”, which can be rendered also as paradoxical.’ But it
can’t really be true that the Jainas are deliberately setting out to introduce
paraconsistency in so strong a sense into their system, for they say quite
clearly that all seven of the modes of assertion are meant to be combinations
of assertion and denial without contradiction, and we have seen Hemacandra
responding to the charge that the Jaina system is contradictory with a firm
rebuttal.
Is there any non-paraconsistent understanding of the simultaneous assertion
and denial of a proposition, given that denial is assertion of the negation?
The only suggestion I have found is one in the late (seventeenth century AD)
Jaina philosopher Yasovijaya. Yasovijaya’s aim is to redescribe the Jaina
system in the technical language of Navya-Nyaya, a precise formal language
developed in order to eliminate ambiguity from philosophical discourse.
What Yasovijaya says is that what one asserts when one asserts a thing to
be simultaneously both existing and non-existing is in the form of an
‘alternation’ (anyataratvadina). The term ‘alternation’ is a technical one in
Navya-Nyaya. It is defined as ‘that which possesses a difference to which
142
Philosophy in classical India
the absenteeness is limited by both differences’. The alternation of fire and
water is that which is different from what is both different from fire and
different from water. Daniel Ingalls25 identifies this with the standard
definition for the inclusive ‘or’: p ∨ q iff ~ (~p & ~q). If he is right, then
Yasovijaya’s point is that a simultaneous assertion and denial is an assertion
that the pot either does or does not exist. It is an assertion of ignorance. The
fourth position is one in which one asserts that, with respect to certain
parameter-values, the object is one of the two: F, not-F. This is identical
neither to an assertion that it is F there, nor an assertion that it is not-F
there, nor an assertion that it is F with respect to some values, but not-F with
respect to others. Nor is it an attempt to assert that it is both. It is a speechact with a distinctive assertoric force.
Let us take Σ to be the totality of points in the four-dimensional space
whose coordinates are the parameters on assertion. A description of the object
distributes values for the proposition ‘x is F’ at points in Σ. It does so by
determining a function from points in the parameter space to values in the set
{true, false, unassertible}. The proposition ‘x is F’ is assigned the value ‘true’
at a point if the description specifies that the object is F at that point, with
respect to those parameters. It is assigned the value ‘false’ at the point if the
description specifies that the object is not-F at that point.26 The third value,
‘unassertible’, is assigned if the description does not specify which of F and
not-F the object is at that point.27 Perhaps there are ‘optimal’ descriptions,
descriptions that specify whether the object is F or not-F at every point in the
parameter space (for example, the description of the number 4 as the sum of
3 and 1). Admitting the new value ‘unassertible’ is a way of recognising that
most descriptions are not optimal, but simply fail to specify whether the object
is F or not at many points in the parameter space. They admit ignorance.
Why is it that one is said to be asserting the unassertible? Let me quote
Yasovijaya:28
The fourth is made when assertion and denial have predominance at the
same time – thus, ‘somehow it is indeed unassertible.’ [It is called
‘unassertible’] because it is impossible to assert both at the same time
through a single word. Even a convention-based term like satr–sanac [a
term in Panini’s grammar for the two sorts of present participle affix]
denotes its two meanings consecutively. Even when both are somehow
understood through alternation, it would be difficult even for God to
understand both from a single word having its own unique character.
A simultaneous assertion about both existence and non-existence is not
necessarily an assertion of both existence and non-existence. It could be the
assertion that one or the other obtains (but we do not know which). This is an
assertion which can only be made by a succession of uttered terms. An analogy
might be the way one can build up a single idea of an object from a succession
of tactual experiences. Sequential order in the vehicle of thought (tactual
Rationality, harmony and perspective
143
experience, language) does not imply sequential order in the content of thought.
In our case, although the content of the thought is a single disjunction, the
vehicle by which it is expressed is, necessarily, a sequential statement of the
disjuncts.
The point is made clearly by Mallisena, from whom Yasovijaya derives
his ‘satr–sanac’ example:29
An object such as the soul is [said to be] unassertible because it is impossible
for a word to denote a single object giving predominance at the same
time to both existence and non-existence in the same act. For the two
qualities of existence and non-existence cannot be asserted at the same
time by the word ‘exists’, for it lacks the capacity to denote non-existence.
Thus too by the word ‘non-exists’, for it does not have the capacity to
denote existence. Nor can it be denoted by a single conventional term
such as puspavant [meaning ‘sun or moon’], because it too can denote
both meanings only in succession. This is like the conventional term
satr–sanac. Whether a conjunctive or a descriptive determinative
compound, the sentence does not denote it. So the object is unassertible
because there is no expression denotative of the whole. Even when
simultaneous existence and non-existence have equal prominence, the
ordering cannot be passed over. But it is not totally unassertible, because
then it would not be asserted by the word ‘unassertible’! Thus the fourth.
The remaining three of the seven modes of assertion now follow in the same
non-adjunctive pattern as the third. The point to stress is that it is possible to
make all seven kinds of assertion about the same object and the same property.
Each one carries a distinctive type of information about the distribution of
truth and falsity of ‘x is F’ over the space whose co-ordinates are the parameters
(substance, place, time, state).
An ancient and rather obscure group of Jainas known as the Trairasikas
(‘followers of the doctrine of the three heaps’) were so-called because they
admitted only a three-fold division. Their view is reported in a commentary
on the Nandisutra,30 where it is assimilated with that of the heretical Ajivikas:
The Ajivika heretics founded by Gosala are likewise called Trairasikas,
since they declare everything to be of triple character, viz. living, not
living, and both living and not living; world, not world, and both world
and not world; existent, non-existent, and both existent and non-existent.
In considering standpoints (naya) [they postulate that a standpoint may
be] substance-affirming, modification-affirming, or both-affirming. Thus,
since they maintain three heaps (rasi), they are called Trairasikas.
The Trairasikas, perhaps, are worried that no sense can be made of a speechact with the force of ‘assert-deny’ other than as a paraconsistent assertion of
simultaneous existence and non-existence. In this, they may be right. My
suggestion, following Yasovijaya, is that the introduction of the new kind of
144
Philosophy in classical India
speech-act is a device for allowing there to be descriptions which are less than
optimally s~pecific. A little more can be said, but first let us take a look at the
consequences of the non-exclusiveness thesis for the classical theory of
extrapolative inference.
5.7 THE MARK OF A GOOD REASON
The doctrine that objects are many-faceted has important ramifications for
the theory of inference. Dinnaga had argued that there are three marks
individually necessary and jointly sufficient for the warranted extrapolation
from reason to target (Chapter 4.7). They are: (1) that the reason be present in
the site of the extrapolation; (2) that the reason be present (only) in what is
similar to the target; and (3) that the reason be absent in what is dissimilar to
the target. The second of these conditions is, arguably, equivalent to the third,
which asserts that the reason property is absent when the target property is
absent. That was supposed to capture the idea of a ‘no counter-example’
condition, according to which an extrapolation is warranted just in case there
is nothing in which the reason is present, but not the target. What happens to
this account if one allows, as the Jainas do, that a property and its absence be
compossible in a single object? What happens is that the three marks cease to
be sufficient for warranted extrapolation. In particular, the third mark no
longer captures the idea behind the ‘no counter-example’ condition. For now
the absence of the reason property in a place where the target is absent does
not preclude its presence there too! So the third mark can be satisfied and yet
there still be counter-examples – cases of the presence of the reason together
with the absence of the target.
The Jainas indeed claim that the three marks are neither necessary nor
sufficient for warranted extrapolation. Their response is to substitute for the
three marks a new, single, mark. It is clear that, if the presence and absence of
a property are compossible, then a distinction needs to be drawn between
absence and non-presence. The first is consistent with the presence of the
property; the second is not. Early post-Dinnaga Jainas such as Akalanka and
Siddhasena described the new mark in quasi-Buddhistic terms, as ‘no presence
without’ (avinabhava) – i.e. no presence of the reason without the target.
Thus Akalanka:31
An extrapolation is a cognition of what is signified from a sign known
to have the single mark of no presence without the target
(sadhyavinabhava). Its result is blocking and other cognitions.
The relata of the causality and identity relations cannot be cognised
without the suppositional knowledge (tarka) of their being impossible
otherwise, [which is] the proof that this is the single mark even without
those relations. Nor is a tree the own-nature (svabhava) or the effect
(karya) of such things as shade. And there is no disagreement here.
Rationality, harmony and perspective
145
There is an obvious reference to and criticism of Dharmakirti here,32 and also
a mention of the important idea, to which we shall return in Chapter 6, that
suppositional reasoning (tarka) is what gives us knowledge of the universal
generalisations grounding extrapolations. The crucial difference from the
Buddhists is in the meaning of ‘no presence’. For the Jainas, it has to stand for
non-presence and not for absence. That led them to reformulate the reason–
target relation as a relation of necessitation. Siddhasena:
The mark of a reason is ‘being impossible otherwise’ (anyathanupannatva).
(NA 22)
Vadideva Sari gives the developed Jaina formulation:
A reason has a single mark, ‘determined as impossible otherwise’. It does
not have three marks, for fallacies are then still possible. (PNTA 3.11–12)
The idea is that the reason cannot be present if the target is not. It is impossible
for the reason to be present otherwise than if the target is present. The presence
of the reason necessitates the presence of the target. The necessity introduced
by the new definition is in fact a universal quantification over parametervalues. What the new definition states is that there is no set of parametervalues for which the reason is present, but not the target. That rules out the
worrisome case – the case where the target is non-present, but the reason is
both absent and present. For a property is absent if it is not present at some set
of values, and it is non-present if it is not present at any set of values. And if
we read ‘no presence without’ as ‘non-presence without’ then what the
definition states is that there is no set of parameter values at which the reason
is present, but not the target.
The problem is discussed in detail by Prabhacandra (eleventh century AD).
While commenting on the definition provided by Siddhasena, he probes the
proper logical form of the extrapolation relation:33
[Opponent:] And again, is it that smoke is impossible when some one fire
is absent or when all fire is absent? Not some one, because even when
one fire is absent the presence of smoke is possible if another fire [is
present]. Nor all, for it is impossible to comprehend [every absence of
fire] without comprehending a condition [qualifying the absences
generally]. A condition (upadhi) for the absence of smoke is the absence
of fire in general, and that cannot be comprehended when every fire is
not comprehended, since to comprehend an absence it is necessary to
comprehend the locus of the absentee.
And also, even when the absence of a certain fire is absent, an opposition
(virodha) is seen between the presence of smoke and the absence of smoke.
So the condition for opposition to the presence of smoke is not the absence
of fire but the absence of smoke . . .
146
Philosophy in classical India
[Reply:] Whatever was said on the lines of ‘is it that smoke is impossible
when some one fire is absent or when all fire is absent,’ that is not right at
all. For the extrapolation relation (vyapti) is understood in dependence
on all, as in ‘any particular smoke is impossible when all fire is absent’,
and not by mentioning each and every locus, as in ‘smoke is impossible
when fire is absent on the mountain or in the house or in the forest.’ For
if that were required no extrapolation relation could be proved even with
an infinite amount of time, since there are infinitely many loci. And
because an extrapolation would be useless, since the time of
comprehending the extrapolation relation would be the same as that of
comprehending the loci of fire and smoke together.
Now one should not say that, if the qualifying condition for the
impossibility of smoke concerns all fire, and this is not comprehended,
then neither can one comprehend its absence. For the absence of the [fire]
is it’s presence at other places, etc. [i.e. other parameter values], and
because the absence is being present at other presences, which [in turn] is
because presence expels absence. That is how a place, etc. is cognised
perceptually as disjoined from all fire . . .
And whatever was said on the lines of ‘even when the absence of a
certain fire is absent, an opposition is seen between the presence of smoke
and the absence of smoke,’ that too is mere words. For when fire is absent,
the presence of smoke is necessarily ruled out. This is because both the
absence of fire and the absence of smoke can be the bases of an opposition
to [smoke]. That which is necessarily ruled out when something is present
is a basis of an opposition to it. For example, cold touch in the presence
of hot touch. The presence of smoke is necessarily ruled out when fire is
absent; so it is the basis of an opposition to smoke . . .
The distinction between some fire being absent and all fire being absent is
just the one between fire being absent (not present with respect to some
parameter) and non-present (not present with respect to any parameter).
Prabhacandra is emphatic that it is the latter that we need. One property
contradicts another if its presence ‘necessarily rules out’ the presence of
the other. The absence of fire does not contradict its presence, but its nonpresence does. And the logical form of the extrapolation relation is: if
there is no set of parameter values for which fire is present, then there is
no set of parameter values for which smoke is present. Non-presence of
target implies non-presence of reason. We can also now understand the
point of the negative formulation of the extrapolation relation by the
Buddhists and Jainas – the essential contrast between absence and nonpresence could not be made out if the formulation were attempted solely
in terms of presence.
I said that Dinnaga’s three marks are, for the Jainas, neither necessary nor
sufficient. They are not sufficient because they permit extrapolation when the
reason is both present and absent, and the target non-present. On what grounds
Rationality, harmony and perspective
147
are they thought not to be necessary? The theory of extrapolation as developed
first by the early Naiyayikas and then by Dinnaga has a built-in simplifying
assumption (Chapter 1.6). The assumption is that extrapolation is always a
matter of inferring from the presence of one property in an object to the
presence of a second property in that same object. But that assumption excludes
many intuitively warranted extrapolations. The main examples considered
by the Jainas are: (1) the sakata star-group will rise because the krttika stargroup has risen; (2) the sun is above the horizon because the earth is in light;
(3) there is a moon in the sky because there is a moon in the water.
These examples are said to prove that the first of Dinnaga’s three marks,
that the reason property is present in the site, is not a necessary condition on
warranted extrapolation. And yet, while it is certainly desirable to broaden
the reach of the theory to cover new patterns of extrapolative inference, it is
not very clear what these examples show. What is the underlying generalisation?
What are the similar and dissimilar examples? In the first case, the extrapolation
seems to be grounded in the universal generalisation ‘whenever the krttika
arises, so too does the sakata.’ But then there is indeed a single site of
extrapolation – the present time. The inference is: the sakata will rise now
because krttika has now risen. A similar point could be made about the second
example. There seems indeed to be an implicit temporal reference in both of
the first two cases, an extrapolation grounded in a universal generalisation
over times.
The third case is more convincing, yet here too one might try to discern a
common site. For the true form of the extrapolation is: the moon is in the sky
because it is reflected in the water, an extrapolation grounded in a universal
generalisation of the form ‘objects cause their own reflections’. Certainly,
however, there are patterns of extrapolation for which the ‘single site’ condition
does not hold. If, for example, one can find a universal generalisation of the
form ‘!x ∃y (Fx´Gy)’, then from ‘∃x Fx’ one can infer ‘∃x Gx’. Perhaps this
is the pattern of extrapolation the Jainas intend to exemplify with their example
of a sky-moon and a water-moon. If so, it represents an important criticism of
a simplifying, but in the end also restricting, assumption in the classical theory
of extrapolation.
5.8 INTEGRATION AND COMPLETE KNOWLEDGE
The means and methods of acquiring knowledge are perspectival. Each gives
knowledge of a part or aspect of the object, but none gives knowledge of the
whole. The Jainas, however, are not sceptics but syncretists. There is a way of
knowing the whole – it is through the integration of one’s knowledge of the
parts. Akalanka:34
A scriptural statement is of two sorts – a somehow-statement (syadvada)
and that called a perspective (naya). A somehow-statement is complete; a
perspective is a partial statement.
148
Philosophy in classical India
A somehow-statement is a statement the nature of whose meaning is to be
many-sided. For example, ‘the person, [his] matter, principle of motion
and rest, space and time’. Here, the person is many-sided, marked in a
way common [with other sorts of thing] by being the bearer of qualities
and of properties, having equal status, being knowable and being existent;
and marked in a way both common and uncommon by being subtle,
having non-denumerably many spatial atoms, being intangible; and
marked in an uncommon way by happiness, exertion, perception and
belief. As this is the whole of a person, the somehow-statement is a complete
means of knowing (pramana). According to some, they have the capacity
for transformation. A perspective is a partial statement, for instance ‘a
person is a thinker, because known to be happy, unhappy and so on.’. . .
Here, the word ‘person’, [governed by] a convention resting on the notion
of capacity, denotes, through exclusion of what is other, [only] a state. . .
. Now because the use of ‘somehow’ destroys all one-sided assertion, the
person is denoted as qualified by the four sorts of qualifier, like ownnature, etc. . . . Even so a perspective is precisely a single side. When one
says ‘somehow the person indeed [exists]’, the word ‘somehow’ has many
sides as its scope. When one says ‘the person somehow exists indeed’, the
word ‘somehow’ has one side as its scope.
Akalanka tells us that the name must occur within the scope of the modal
operator ‘somehow’, and that when it does the statement is many-sided. I have
chosen this passage because it counters a common misconception of the Jaina
theory. The misconception is that we should understand a statement
conditionalised by ‘somehow’ as a statement of how things are from a particular
perspective. But, as this passage makes clear, the fundamental contrast is between
statements from a certain perspective and statements conditionalised by the
‘somehow’ operator. Embedding a statement within the scope of the operator
quantifies over the values of the four hidden parameters (substance, place, time,
state). A complete description of an object is a description with explicit reference
to the state of the object at each of the values of those parameters. What the
insertion of ‘somehow’ allows us to do is to begin to build up such a pointwise
description of the object, each somehow-conditionalised statement carrying
information along a line of sight of points. As more statements are added, a
picture gradually builds up of the whole object, just as (to use a favourite
metaphor of Sukhlalji Sanghvi) we build up a picture of the whole house by
inspecting it from different sides, inside and out.
I have said that each new statement adds new information about the object.
But a question still remains – can we ever, by this means, reach a complete
description of the object? A complete description is a truth-value specification
at each of infinitely many points, but we do not have infinitely many
conditionalised statements. In fact, we have only seven, or rather only seven
types, of statement. Perhaps then the contrast is this: a statement conditionalised
by ‘somehow’ gives one partial knowledge of the full object, while a
Rationality, harmony and perspective
149
perspectival statement gives one full knowledge of part of the object.
Siddhasena:
Since scriptural statements occur as nayas, which reside in one [aspect].
A scriptural statement ascertaining the full object is called a ‘somehowstatement’. (NA 30)
One frequent suggestion is that description in all the modes of the seven-fold
division (saptabhangi) is a method for reaching a complete description. The
seven-fold division is a division into seven types of partial statement about
the whole. Given any partial description of the object, we can classify the
description according to the type of speech-act it is and so the type of
information it conveys. What is the effect of adding further new descriptions?
Do we ever attain, by this method, a specification of truth-value at every
point? This is a common understanding of the Jaina position. ‘The Jainas,’
Matilal35 says, ‘contend that one should try to understand the particular
point of view of each disputing party if one wishes to grasp completely the
truth of the situation. The total truth . . . may be derived from the integration
of all different viewpoints.’ The contention, however, is non-trivial. Perhaps
it can be done, but it is far from clear. The Jaina rationality of reconciliation
certainly leads to ever more complete descriptions, but does the description
ever become complete? The attainment of the ‘total truth’ does not seem
obviously to follow from the Jaina method of integrating different viewpoints
(the parameterisation of assertion, the use of ‘somehow’ as a quantifier over
parameters). It may follow, if by the ‘total truth’ one means something less
than optimal truth, or if there exist simplifying constraints on the distribution
of a property in parameter space, or if there are parameter-specific correlates
of ‘somehow’.
Mahavira is reported to have said that it is only when ‘one understands the
true nature of all substances by all the means of knowing and all the
perspectives that one’s knowledge is complete.’36 Another possibility is that
‘complete knowledge’ is knowledge of everything that can be known about
things, not necessarily knowledge of everything about them. The goal of
rational harmonisation would then be to acquire complete knowledge of the
truth, and not knowledge of the complete truth. Knowledge of the complete
truth (kevalajñana) is the sole preserve of the omniscient.
FURTHER READING
Texts
Siddhasena Divakara c. AD 700, Nyayavatara (NA).
Hemacandra AD 1089–1172, Pramanamimamsa (PM).
Vadideva Suri c. AD 1150, Pramananayatattvalokalamkara (PNTA).
150
Philosophy in classical India
Many-sidedness (5.1–3)
1
Sukhlalji Sanghvi, ‘Anekantavada: The Principal Jaina Contribution
to Logic,’ in his Advanced Studies in Indian Logic and Metaphysics (Calcutta:
Indian Studies Past and Present, 1961), pp. 15–28.
2
Y. J. Padmarajiah, Jaina Theories of Reality and Knowledge (Bombay:
Jain Sahitya Vikas Mandal, 1963).
3
Jayandra Soni, ‘Dravya, Guna and Paryaya in Jaina Thought,’ Journal
of Indian Philosophy 19.1 (1991), pp. 75–88.
4
Frank Van Den Bossche, ‘Jain Relativism: An Attempt at Understanding,’
in R. Smet and K. Watanabe eds. Jain Studies in Honour of Jozef Deleu (Tokyo:
Hon-No-Tomosha, 1993), pp. 457–474.
5
Frank Van Den Bossche, ‘Existence and Non-Existence in Haribhadra
Suri’s Anekantajayapataka,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 23 (1995), pp. 429–
468.
Standpoints, logic of assertion (5.4–6)
1
Pradeep Gokhale, ‘The Logical Structure of Syadvada,’ Journal of
Indian Council of Philosophical Research 8 (1991), pp. 73–81.
2
R. A. Kumar, T. M. Dak and A. D. Mishra eds., Anekantavada and
Syadvada (Landun: Jain Visva Bharati, 1996).
3
B. K. Matilal, ‘Anekanta: both yes and no?,’ Journal of Indian Council
of Philosophical Research 8 (1991), pp. 1–12; reprinted as ‘The Jaina
Contribution to Logic,’ in The Character of Logic in India (Albany: State
University of New York Press, 1998), pp. 127–139.
4
Piotr Balcerowicz, ‘The Logical Structure of the naya Method of the
Jainas,’ unpublished typescript.
Logical theory (5.7)
1
Sukhlalji Sanghvi, ‘On Problems of Inference,’ in his Advanced Studies
in Indian Logic and Metaphysics (Calcutta: Indian Studies Past and Present,
1961), pp. 77–110.
2
Atishi Uno, ‘Vyapti in Jainism,’ in N. K. Wagle and F. Watanabe
eds., Studies on Buddhism in Honour of Professor A. K. Warder (Toronto:
University of Toronto, 1993), pp. 160–167.
3
Muni Shri Nyaya-vijayaji, Jaina Philosophy and Religion, trans.
Nagin J. Shah (Delhi: B. L. Institute of Indology and Motilal Banarsidass,
1998), chapter 5.
6 Reason in equilibrium
6.1 REASON AND THE MANAGEMENT OF DOUBT
Reason is imperfect – there is a permanent possibility of error. Knowledge is
achieved through the elimination of doubt, and what eliminates doubt is the
existence of a compelling reason. But doubt is more infectious than it first
appears, for one might doubt whether one’s reason really is compelling, doubt
whether the reason for thinking that it is compelling is itself compelling, and
so on forever along a familiar evidential regress. Doubts cascade, and truly
compelling reasons are scarce. Even when they are to hand, their value is
limited – for not even psychological certainty can exclude the logical possibility
of error. So it transpires that the hard question is not how to free one’s inner
space from all doubt (an impossible project of dubious value), but how to live
with the uncertainty with which it is necessarily infused.
What is reason’s role in the management of doubt? Later Nyaya
epistemologists develop a theory of what they call ‘suppositional reasoning’
or tarka. It is a theory about the burden of proof and the role of presumption,
about the conditions under which even inconclusive evidence is sufficient for
warranted belief. That the term tarka is used in this context is significant in
itself. For in the canonical and early literature, tarka is virtually synonymous
with reasoned thinking in general. The free-thinkers so derided in the epics,
we have seen, were called tarkikas or ‘followers of reason’ (Chapter 1.1).
Even later on, when the fashion was to adorn introductory surveys of philosophy
with such glorious names as The Language of Reason (Tarkabhasa,
Moksakaragupta), Immortal Reason (Tarkamrta, Jagadisa), Reason’s
Moonlight (Tarkakaumudi, Laugaksi Bhaskara), it was usual to confer on a
graduate of the medieval curriculum an honorific title such as Master or Lord
of Reason (tarkavagisa, tarkatirtha). Such a person is a master in the art of
evidence and the management of doubt, knowing when to accept the burden
of proof and also when and how to deflect it. In its popular use, tarka is the
nearest one gets to a Sanskrit synonym for ‘rationality’.
Extrapolative inference rests on the knowledge of universal generalisations,
and it is the possibility of such knowledge that some of the most troubling
152
Philosophy in classical India
forms of scepticism call into question. How can one be entitled to believe that
something is true of every member of a domain without inspecting each member
individually? How does one cope with the ineliminable possibility that an
unperceived counter-example exists in some distant corner of the domain?1
The difficulty here is with the epistemology of negative existentials. We have
seen Dinnaga’s formulation of the extrapolation relation as a ‘no counterexample’ relation (Chapter 4.7). For him, x extrapolates y just in case there is
no x without y (y-avina x-abhava). The Navya-Nyaya logicians of the New
Epistemology prefer a different negative existential condition, one derived
from the reflexivity and transitivity of the extrapolation relation. Given
transitivity, if x extrapolates y then, for any z, if y extrapolates z, so does x.
The converse of this conditional holds too, given that the extrapolation relation
is reflexive (proof: let z = y). So let us define an ‘associate condition’ (upadhi)
as a property which is extrapolated by y, but not x. Then x extrapolates y just
in case there is no associate condition.2 One can infer fire from smoke, but not
smoke from fire, for there is an associate condition, dampness-of-fuel, present
wherever smoke is, but not wherever fire is. Tinkering with the definition,
though, does not affect the epistemological problem; it remains the one of
proving a non-existence claim.
As if the justification of extrapolation were not problem enough, it turns
out that the sceptical worry cuts deeper still. It threatens the very tenability of
the pramana-theoretic conception of an epistemic agent as someone endowed
with generally truth-conducive processes of belief-acquisition. For a person is
not merely a belief-forming automaton, but is able to reflect upon (revise,
reject, overrule) the epistemic processes with which they are endowed. Ernest
Sosa3 appropriately calls the state of being a rational epistemic agent one of
having an ‘epistemic perspective’ on the deliverances of one’s epistemic
faculties. There is a distinction to be drawn between mere ‘animal knowledge’,
knowledge produced by one’s epistemic faculties in direct response to one’s
environment, and ‘reflective knowledge’, something that involves an
understanding of the place the deliverances of the epistemic faculties have in
a ‘wider whole that includes one’s belief and knowledge of it and how these
came about’. An explanatory inference sustains the epistemic perspective, the
reflective justification of the beliefs produced by a certain faculty being derived
from the inference that attributes those beliefs to the faculties from which they
derive.
The problem then is that an epistemic perspective itself rests on a knowledge
of generalities. Like Sosa, the Nyaya understanding of reflective knowledge
sees it as derived from an explanatory inference. The epistemic agent is entitled
to have confidence in her beliefs and belief-acquisition procedures because, or
to the extent that, actions performed in agreement with the beliefs so produced
meet with successful outcomes. The accord between belief and success in
action is the basis of a perspective on one’s global epistemic ‘set-up’, and it is
also the warrant for local belief in the truth of individual beliefs. One infers
from success to truth – success in action confirms truth in belief. A perspective
Reason in equilibrium
153
on one’s own epistemic capacities is gained in the reflective justification of
one’s beliefs based on an inference from their behavioural effects or an inference
from the epistemic ‘likeness’ of one belief with another.4 And so the reflective
equilibrium of the rational epistemological agent rests on their entitlement to
believe in a general relation between success in action and truth in belief.
Scepticism about the possibility of general knowledge hits not merely firstorder belief-acquisition processes, but the very possibility of achieving epistemic
stability.
6.2 THE BURDEN OF PROOF
Suppositional reasoning, tarka, is a device for appropriating a presumptive
right – the right to presume that one’s own position is correct even without
conclusive evidence in its support. One is, let us imagine, in a state of doubt
as to which of two hypotheses A and B is true. A and B are exclusive (at most
one is true), but not necessarily contradictory (both might be false). Technically,
they are in a state of ‘opposition’ (virodha).5 The doubt would be expressed
by an exclusive disjunction in the interrogative – Is it that A or that B?
Uncertainty initiates inquiry (Chapter 1.2), and at the beginning of any inquiry
the burden of proof is symmetrically distributed among the alternative
hypotheses. A piece of suppositional reasoning shifts the burden of proof by
adducing a prima facie counter-factual argument against one side. The form
of the argument is the same in all cases. It is that one alternative, supposed as
true, would have a consequence in conflict with some set of broadly defined
constraints on rational acceptability. The existence of such an argument gives
one the right to presume that the other alternative is true, even though one has
no conclusive proof of its truth, and even though the logical possibility of its
being false remains open. In the psychologised language of the Naiyayika, a
suppositional argument is a ‘blocker’ (badhaka) to belief in the supposed
alternative, and an ‘eliminator’ (nirvartaka) of doubt. The Naiyayika
Vacaspati (ninth century AD) comments:6
Even if, following a doubt, there is a desire to know [the truth], the doubt
still remains after the desire to know [has come about]. This is the situation
intended for the application of suppositional reasoning. Of two theses,
one should be admitted as known when the other is rejected by the reasoning
called ‘suppositional’. Thus doubt is suppressed by the application of
suppositional reasoning to its subject matter. . . . A method of knowing is
engaged to decide a question, but when there is a doubt involving its
opposite, the method of knowing fails [in fact] to engage. But the doubt
concerning the opposite is not removed as such by the undesired
consequence. What makes possible its removal is the method of knowing
[itself].
154
Philosophy in classical India
Vacaspati stresses that a thesis is not itself proved by a suppositional
demonstration that the opposite has undesired consequences; one still needs
evidence corroborating the thesis. But there is now a presumption in its favour,
and the burden of proof lies squarely with the opponent. Suppositional
reasoning ‘supports’ one’s means of acquiring evidence, but is not itself a
source of evidence. Its role is pragmatic and situational: to change the standard
of evidence required for proof in the specific context.
A radical sceptical hypothesis is a proposition inconsistent with ordinary
belief, but consistent with all available evidence for it. The aim of the radical
sceptic is to undermine our confidence that our beliefs are justified, to
introduce doubt. The New Epistemology’s response to scepticism is not to
deny that there is a gap between evidence and belief, or to deny the logical
possibility of the sceptical hypothesis. It is to draw a distinction between
two kinds of doubt, the reasonable and the reasonless. A doubt is reasonable
only when both alternatives are consistent with all the evidence and the
burden of proof is symmetrically distributed between them. One paradigmatic
example is the case of seeing in the distance something that might be a
person or might be a tree-stump (recall the clause in the Nyayasutra definition
of perception as ‘definite in nature’, a clause specifically inserted to rule out
such doubt; Chapter 1.4). Udayana gives the epistemology of such a case: it
is a case in which one has knowledge of common aspects, but not of specific
distinguishing features. What we can now see is that the example gets its
force only on the assumption that there is a level epistemic playing field,
with both hypotheses carrying the same prima facie plausibility. Suppositional
reasoning has the potential to break the impasse – imagine, for example,
that the unidentified lump is just one of ten in an orderly row known not to
be there an hour ago. The perceptual evidence remains the same, but the
burden of proof is on anyone who wants to maintain in this situation that
the lump is a stump.
The other paradigm is knowledge of extrapolation relations. The problem
here is that the thesis is one of such high generality that the burden of proof is
already heavily against it! How can a few observations of smoke with fire
ground a belief that there is fire whenever there is smoke? Suppositional argument
has a different supportive role here. Its function is to square the scales, to neutralise
the presumption against the belief in generality. It does so by finding prima
facie undesirable consequences in the supposition that an associate condition or
counter-example exists. Then sampling (observation of only confirmatory
instances in the course of a suitably extensive search for counter-examples),
though still weak evidence, can tilt the scale in favour of the generalisation.
Gangesa (c. AD 1320), the definitive systematiser of the New Epistemology,
distinguishes two kinds of doubt as relevant to the problem of justifying
extrapolation.7 The two kinds are the sort of doubt produced by a worry over
whether an associate condition is present, and the sort of doubt produced by
an awareness of some general feature (lumpiness) in the absence of any
identified distinguishing mark (arms, branches). Of course, there are plenty
Reason in equilibrium
155
of other sources of doubt in so far as a doubt is just a mental state, but not
every such doubt is reasonable, and it is only reasonable doubt that need
trouble the constructive epistemologist. Gangesa admits that mere observation
of confirming examples is an insufficient basis on which to rest belief in
general relations. What he insists on is observation in tandem with the
principled absence of doubt, and, since reasonable doubt is a product of
evidential balance between rival alternatives, its elimination consists in finding
a presumption in favour of one side.
6.3 CRITERIA FOR RATIONAL REJECTION
A suppositional argument moves from conjecture to unacceptable
consequence. Modern writers often identify it with the medieval technique
of reductio ad absurdum, but in fact its scope is wider. The ‘unacceptable
consequence’ can be an out-and-out contradiction, but need not be so. For
we are not trying to prove that the supposition is false, but only to shift the
burden of proof onto anyone who would maintain it. And for this it is enough
simply to demonstrate that the supposition comes into conflict with wellattested norms on rationality or deeply held beliefs. Udayana, the first to
offer any systematic discussion, does not even mention contradiction as a
species of unacceptable consequence. He says8 that suppositional reasoning
is of five types:
1 self-dependence
2 mutual dependence
3 cyclical dependence
4 lack of foundation
5 undesirable consequence
atmasraya
itaretarasraya
cakraka
anavastha
anistaprasanga
The last of these is really just the generic case, what distinguishes
suppositional reasoning in general. The first four form a tight logical group.
If the supposition is the proposition A, then the four types of unacceptable
consequence are: (1) proving A from A; (2) proving A from B, and B from A;
(3) proving A from B, B from C, and C from A – or any higher number of
intermediate proof steps eventually leading back to A; and (4) proving A from
B, B from C, C from D, . . ., without end. So what suppositional reasoning
must show is that the supposition is ungrounded, its proof being either
regressive or question-begging.
Two points are noteworthy about Udayana’s list. First, rational
unacceptability bears upon the proof adduced for the supposition, not the
supposition itself. The underlying implication is that one has the right to
presume that one’s thesis is correct if one can find fault with the opponent’s
proof of the antithesis. Principles of this sort are familiar from discussion of
the informal logic of arguments from ignorance9 in which one claims entitlement
to assert A on the grounds that it is not known (or proved) that ¬A. In general
156
Philosophy in classical India
such a claim must be unfounded – it amounts to the universal appropriation
of a presumptive right in all circumstances.
The second point to notice about Udayana’s list, however, is that it is
very narrow. Udayana places strict constraints on what will count as an
unacceptable consequence, constraints which are more formal than broadly
rational. Conflict with other well-attested belief is not mentioned, for instance.
Udayana severely limits the scope of suppositional reasoning. His motive,
perhaps, is to disarm the sceptic. For suppositional reasoning is the favoured
kind of reasoning of the sceptic-dialecticians (and indeed the term Udayana
uses is prasanga, the same term Nagarjuna had used for his dialectical
method). Sceptics typically will want to loosen the conditions on what
constitutes an unacceptable consequence of a supposition, so that the scope
for refutation is expanded. So what Udayana seems to be saying is that one
does indeed have the right to presume that one’s thesis is correct when the
argument for the counter-thesis commits a fallacy of a particularly gross
type – not mere conflict with other beliefs, but formal lack of foundation. If
the best argument for the antithesis is that bad, then one has a prima facie
entitlement to one’s thesis.
Sriharsa (c. AD 1140) is an Advaita dialectician, a poet and a sceptic.10 He
expands the notion of unacceptable consequence, noticing several additional
types unmentioned by Udayana.11 One is ‘self-contradiction’ (vyaghata). It
was Udayana himself12 who analysed the notion of opposition as noncompossibility, and cited as examples the statements ‘My mother is childless,’
‘I am unable to speak,’ and ‘I do not know this jar to be a jar.’ In the first
instance, the non-compossibility is in what the assertion states, in the second
it is in the speech-act itself, while in the third the propositional attitude selfascription is self-refuting (a case akin to the Cartesian impossibility of thinking
that one is not thinking).
Another refutation-exacting circumstance is the one called ‘recrimination’
(pratibandi). This is a situation in which one’s opponent accuses one of
advancing a faulty proof, when his own proof suffers exactly the same fault!
There is a disagreement about what this state of equifallaciousness does to the
burden of proof. The practice of Naiyayikas is to take the circumstance as
tilting the balance against the opponent – the opponent discredits himself in
pressing an accusation without seeing that it can be applied with equal force
to his own argument. But Sriharsa quotes with approval Kumarila’s assertion
that ‘all things being equal, where the same fault afflicts both positions, one
should not be censured [and not the other]’.13
Sriharsa, qua sceptic, would like to see both parties refuted by this
circumstance. The same point underlies his mention as an unacceptable
consequence the circumstance of ‘lack of differential evidence’
(vinigamanaviraha), when thesis and antithesis are in the same evidential
situation. Again, what we see is a jostling with the burden of proof. Here
Sriharsa is saying that absence of differential evidence puts a burden of proof
Reason in equilibrium
157
on both thesis and antithesis – doubt itself refutes. It is the sceptic’s strategy
always to seek to maximise the burden of proof, and so to deny that anyone
ever has the right to presume their position to be correct. That is, as Stanislaw
Schayer observed a long time ago, a difference between the tarka of the
Naiyayika and the prasanga of a sceptic such as Sriharsa or Nagarjuna.14 For
the latter, the demonstration that a thesis has an allegedly false consequence
does not commit the refuter to an endorsement of the antithesis. Nagarjuna,
as we saw in chapter 2, wants to maintain instead that thesis and antithesis
share a false existential precommitment.
Simplicity (laghutva) is, Sriharsa considers and the Naiyayikas agree,
a ceteris paribus preference-condition. Of two evidentially equivalent and
otherwise rationally acceptable theses, the simpler one is to be preferred.
The burden of proof lies with someone who wishes to defend a more complex
hypothesis when a simpler one is at hand. The Nyaya cosmological
argument appeals to simplicity when it infers from the world as product to
a single producer rather than a multiplicity of producers. Here too the
role of the simplicity consideration is to affect the burden of proof, not
itself to prove. Cohen and Nagel15 make a related point when they diagnose
as the ‘fallacy of simplism’ the mistake of thinking that ‘of any two
hypotheses, the simpler is the true one.’ In any case, simplicity can be a
product not of the content of a hypothesis, but only of its mode of
presentation – the distinction is made by the Naiyayikas themselves.16
And it is hard to see how it can be rational to prefer one hypothesis to
another only because it is simpler in form.
We have assumed that the rival hypotheses are both empirically adequate,
that is to say, they are both consistent with all known facts. Sriharsa mentions
an unacceptable consequence involving empirical evidence (utsarga). It is an
objection to the usual idea that if there is empirical evidence supporting one
hypothesis, but not the other, then the first is confirmed. Sriharsa’s sceptical
claim is that a hypothesis must be considered refuted unless it is conclusively
proved; non-conclusive empirical evidence does nothing to affect this burden
of proof. Likewise, he says, a hypothesis must be considered refuted if it is
incapable of being proved or disproved – this at least seems to be the import
of the unacceptable consequence he calls ‘impertinence’ (anucitya) or
‘impudence’ (vaiyatya).
Other varieties17 of suppositional refutation have been suggested along
lines similar to the ones we have reviewed. Different authors propose
different sets of criteria for rational non-acceptance. What we have seen is
that there is, in the background, a jostling over the weight and place of the
burden of proof. The sceptic presses in the direction of one extreme – that a
thesis can be considered refuted unless definitively proved. The pramanatheoretic epistemologist tries to press in the direction of the opposite extreme
– that a thesis can be considered proved unless definitively disproved. The
truth lies somewhere in between, and it is the role of suppositional reason to
locate it.
158
Philosophy in classical India
6.4 SUPPOSITION AND PRETENCE
Suppositional reasoning is counter-factual – were the supposition to be
true, so would the unacceptable consequence. What then is the status of a
supposition? It cannot be a state of knowledge, for the whole point of
suppositional reasoning is that it is a means for the elimination of doubt in
A by showing the unacceptibility of ~A . Udayana’s proposal18 is that a
supposition is an ‘imaginary imposition’ (aharyaropa), a pretence. The
term aharya, let us note, also means an actor’s costume, and aharyasobha is a made-up beauty produced by ornamentation and paint. The
state of affairs with respect to which the counter-factual is evaluated is a
pretend state, a product of the imagination. The new logicians19 define the
mental act of pretence as a thought whose qualifier is contrary to that
property which specifies the qualificand – the thought, for example, that
the fiery mountain is without fire. So it is not so much counter-factual, as
counter to what one believes to be actual. It is the state of mind in which
one pretends that an object is something other than what one believes it to
be, as, for example, in the child’s game where a rock is imagined to be a
boat. Pretence is said by an eighteenth-century Nyaya poetician20 to be
what governs metaphor (rupaka) – one imagines a face to be the moon,
knowing all the time that it is not. It is a ‘willing suspension’,21 a ‘deliberate
self-deception’,22 in which one attempts to think of a thing as something
other than what one believes it to be, and to trace the consequence of so
doing. Udayana maintains that a pretence is a species of false belief, but
this does not seem right. It is better thought of either simply as the antecedent
of a true counter-factual,23 or as not truth-apt at all.24 The imaginary
imposition is an act of mental simulation, the re-creation in imagination
of a fictitious world, and such acts are fundamentally different in character
from states of belief. Another Nyaya suggestion is that the state of pretence
is quasi-perceptual, somewhat akin to the state one is in when experiencing
a perceptual appearance one knows to be illusory. But there is no reason
to suppose the domain of pretence to be limited to possible objects of
perception alone, as indeed is shown by the case of pretending that an
extrapolation relation obtains.
A necessary condition for doubt – Is it that A or that B? – is the possibility
of being able to imagine A and to imagine B, without yet knowing which one
is actual. Doubt is impossible, therefore, if one of the putative alternatives is
unimaginable. Gangesa will say (see below) that the absence of doubt is
sometimes ‘self-established’, and one meaning, perhaps, is that it is impossible
to imagine the alleged alternative hypothesis. The limits of imaginary
supposition are the limits of doubt. Where then do those limits lie? Presumably
one cannot imagine what is logically contradictory. Other limits too follow
from the Nyaya definition. It is an axiom in the Nyaya theory of content that
the constituents of content (the qualificand, the qualifiers, the relation) are
real entities. All error is the misascription of a real qualifier to a real
Reason in equilibrium
159
qualificand.25 Even one’s belief in fictitious objects, such as monsters with
three heads, is explained this way – the fictitious monster is nothing but a
monstrous miscombination of real animal parts. An implication of this theory
of error is that one can never be mistaken about the qualificand; all thought,
no matter how erroneous, must have a real ‘nucleus’ to which the qualifiers
are attributed. It follows that even if one can, in imagination, counterfactually
ascribe qualifiers, one cannot, even in imagination, pretend that the qualificand
does not exist. The Nyaya principle of acquaintance is that every basic thoughtconstituent is real. All thought is the arrangement and rearrangement of those
basic constituents. So even pretence is limited to an available domain of
fundamental thought-constituents. Pretence can only invent new order in an
old world.
The implication of this is that not every metaphysically possible world is
imaginable. Imaginative imposition is limited to worlds sufficiently similar
to ours (or to the way we believe ours to be), in the sense of being made out of
the same basic constituents. This then is a more stringent limit on the possibility
of doubt. We can doubt which of a domain of possible worlds is actual, but
the domain is restricted to worlds constitutively like our own.
It follows that the sceptic is not entitled to formulate the sceptical doubt in
terms of a propositional negation, but must use an internal negation. For the
propositional negation ‘~A’ is true in many worlds inaccessible to thought,
worlds constitutively quite unlike our own. In attempting to imagine ~A,
what we in fact imagine is that the constituents of ‘A’ have some non-actual
arrangement; if ‘A’ is the proposition ‘Fa’, its imaginable negation is the
totality of propositions ‘Ga’, where ‘G’ is a qualifier opposite to (noncompossible with) ‘F’. So a Nyaya response to scepticism is to allow the
possibility of sceptical doubt about the arrangement of the fundamental
constituents of thought, but to deny the possibility of sceptical doubt about
those constituents themselves. There are resonances here with modern treatments
of scepticism.26 To know that A, one’s evidence must exclude every imaginable
possibility that one knows to be incompatible with A, but not every possibility
that ~A simpliciter.
6.5 A NEW DOXASTIC ASCENT
Let us return again to the extrapolation problem, which is the problem of
knowing when or whether one property proves another (Chapters 1.6, 4.7).
Suppositional reasoning was meant to level the playing field and defuse the
initial presumption against beliefs of such generality. In an often-quoted and
sometimes parodied couplet, Udayana says:
If there be doubt, there is inference indeed
All the more if doubt does not occur.
Doubt has its limit in opposition
Suppositional reasoning is regarded as the limit of doubt.27
160
Philosophy in classical India
In his commentary on this couplet, Udayana first argues that a global
scepticism about extrapolation – as advanced, allegedly, by the ‘perceptualist’
Carvaka – is self-refuting. Those who doubt that extrapolation is ever
warranted, on the grounds that the purported inferential relation might fail at
future times or unobserved places, commit themselves to a belief in unobserved
times and places, and that commitment can only be grounded in an
extrapolation from past times and observed places! The possibility of global
doubt about extrapolation presupposes the possibility of extrapolation. This
is not quite the Humean point that extrapolation rests on a belief that nature
is uniform, a belief that itself presupposes extrapolation from past to future
uniformity. For Hume’s intention is to show that inductive justifications of
induction are self-defeating, while Udayana’s aim is to show that it is global
scepticism about induction that is self-defeating.
The second half of the couplet refers to the threatened infinite regress. A
doubt (about the obtaining of an inferential relation) is resolved by a piece of
suppositional reasoning, but does not that piece of suppositional reasoning
itself rest on one’s knowing a general relation, being an inference from
supposition to unacceptable consequence? And since a doubt might arise in
connection with this second general relation, is there not a regress in the
making? It is far from clear that this line of thought ought to worry Udayana,
for counterfactual statements are not in general true in virtue of corresponding
universal generalisations and so it is not necessarily correct to say that pieces
of suppositional reasoning are themselves extrapolative. Udayana’s response
is different. He argues that there is a practical contradiction in basing one’s
actions on a set of beliefs and at the same time doubting whether those beliefs
are true. The beliefs upon which one’s actions rest are a practical limit to
doubt. So an infinite regress of doubt is impossible. The idea is clarified by
Gangesa, in his response to Sriharsa’s criticism of Udayana. So let us see first
of all what Sriharsa has to say.
Sriharsa28 seeks, of course, to switch the burden of proof:
You are not able to establish an extrapolation relation as the basis of
inference by arguing that when doubt should arise about a failure of
extrapolation then by suppositional reasoning an opposition would be
revealed in the ‘deviating’ option of an opposed pair that the doubt would
presuppose. For suppositional reasoning of this sort brings about
(according to you) an understanding of an opposition, and since this
reasoning may not be well-founded, you would still face the problem of
not being able to rule out the possibility of merely ostensible suppositional
reasoning (tarkabhasa).
Since such reasoning can lead to what you would call an opposition
when the reasoning is fallacious, you face the problem of possible
opposition equally on each side, i.e., on both sides of the option and the
opposing pair, one of which the reasoning is undertaken to eliminate.
Reason in equilibrium
161
Because of the possibility of fallacious suppositional reasoning, opposition
on the side that you, sir, wish to establish (as opposed to eliminate) could
occur as (fallaciously) deduced.
Then if it is held that the suppositional reasoning has its foundation in
an extrapolation relation, that won’t help. When there is doubt about
deviation from a true extrapolation relation, there will be an infinite
regress. In trying to prove another opposition with respect to the unwanted
option that the new doubt involves, the difficulty arises ad infinitum.
Therefore, on this topic it is not difficult for us to read your couplet
with the words ever so slightly altered:
If there is opposition, there is doubt
If none, there is doubt all the more.
Opposition includes doubt within its borders;
How then can suppositional reasoning be the limit of doubt?
We have seen the sceptical use of doxastic ascent before (Chapter 2.5).
Sriharsa’s application is in connection with the distinction between true and
false counterfactuals. Suppositional reasoning eliminates a doubt ‘Is it that A
or is it that B?’ by means of a counterfactual ‘if B were true, then there would
be an opposition (with accepted fact or attested behaviour).’ As a piece of
reasoning, it is persuasive only if one can be assured that the counterfactual
on which it is based is true – otherwise, the reasoning would be at best
unpersuasive and at worst fallacious. So the claim that the alternative
hypothesis B would lead to an opposition, far from eliminating doubt, only
produces more.
Gangesa’s solution is to reclaim a presumptive right. It is not always
necessary to prove that an extrapolation relation obtains in order to be justified
in making extrapolations on its basis. One needs further proof (i.e. a piece of
suppositional reasoning) only when there is a reasonable doubt about the
obtaining of the relation. In all other cases, one is entitled to extrapolate
without involving oneself in a proof regress. It is, of course, always possible
to doubt whether the extrapolation relation obtains – but not every such doubt
is a reasonable one. In particular, when the doubt is in conflict with the
doubter’s actual beliefs, as attested by their actions, then their doubt is merely
capricious. Gangesa:29
When there is doubt, there is no regular pattern of behaviour. When there
is a regular pattern, doubt does not occur. Thus it has been said (by
Udayana): ‘That is doubted concerning which as doubted there occurs no
opposition with the doubter’s action.’ For it is not possible at once to
resort regularly to fire for smoke and to doubt that fire causes it. This is
how we should understand (Udayana’s) saying. Thus we may reject the
argument that contradiction, understood as opposition, governing precisely
which x cannot occur along with precisely which y, cannot block an
162
Philosophy in classical India
infinite regress. It is the doubter’s own behaviour that proves the lie to the
doubt, that blocks it. Therefore, the view that [Sriharsa,] the author of the
Khandanakhandakhadya expresses [in his parody of Udayana’s couplet]
may be rejected.
Gangesa’s point is clear. A person’s actions are explained by attributing to
them a set of beliefs and desires. If people nevertheless claim to doubt one of
these beliefs, or even actually to get themselves into a mental state of doubt,
that mental state will still be an inoperative one in their psychological life,
and as such need not be taken seriously.
6.6 EPISTEMIC EQUILIBRIUM
What is the function of reason? Reason’s proper work, it is sometimes said,
is to provide us with a maximum of explanatory coherence and
comprehensiveness in our body of beliefs. That is the role assigned by
Gangesa to suppositional reasoning. It is an ‘incoherence-seeking’ reason,
testing a putative belief or principle for coherence-failure against a
background of other beliefs, principles and theories. It might seem as if
incoherence-seeking reason has no place in the justification of belief. For
the claim of the pramana epistemology is that a belief is justified when it is
the product of a truth-conducive belief-forming process or method. The
justification attaching to any particular belief is defeated, however, by
reasonable doubt as to the truth-conduciveness of the process or method that
produced it. The epistemic function accorded to incoherence-seeking reason,
then, is to eliminate potential justification-defeaters. It does so by showing
that belief in alternatives to the principles sustaining the belief-forming
processes – fundamentally the relations that ground ampliative inference –
has unacceptable consequences, unacceptable, that is, by the standards of
incoherence-seeking reason itself.
Gangesa’s thesis is that justification is the result of an equilibrium in a
person’s beliefs, actions, principles and background theories. He concludes
his examination of our knowledge of extrapolation relations with a summing
up of his considered view:30
[It seems that] doubt persists through repeated observation, and
suppositional reasoning only generates an infinite regress – how then is
the inferential relation to be proven?
Here’s what to say. The proof of an extrapolation relation is the
observation of co-existence [of reason and target] without ‘cognition’ of
any counter-examples. ‘Cognition’ means both definite belief as well as
doubt. That [doubt] results sometimes from a worry concerning the
existence of an associate condition, and sometimes from the observation
of a general characteristic without any observed distinguishing mark.
Reason in equilibrium
163
And its absence is sometimes the result of a suppositional reason blocking
the alternative, and sometimes [the absence of doubt] is given by nothing
but itself (svatah siddha eva).
Might it not be said that since suppositional reasoning is grounded in
the proof of an[other] general relation, an infinite regress will ensue? No,
because one follows a line of suppositional reasoning [only] when there is
a doubt. So where, thanks to some opposition, no doubt falls, the
extrapolation relation is proven even without suppositional reasoning.
Particular extrapolative judgements are justified if licensed by general
extrapolation relations. Those general relations are themselves justified just
as long as there is no reasonable doubt concerning their validity. The state of
being free from such doubt is created and sustained by suppositional arguments,
the effect of which is to shift the burden of proof in favour of the putative
principle of extrapolation. It does this by showing that alternatives fail to
match some standard of coherence with one’s wider beliefs, principles and
theories.
What Sriharsa questions is the justification of suppositional reason itself.
The problem is to distinguish justified from merely ostensible suppositional
reasoning (tarkabhasa). On what grounds can I be sure that my capacity to
detect incoherence is itself reliable? Might it not be a merely ostensible piece of
reasoning, not a genuine inference? My capacity to derive the consequences of
counterfactual suppositions is what removes the defeaters of the justification
induced by the belief-forming methods and processes with which I am endowed.
Sriharsa’s scepticism brings into question my right to place my trust in that very
capacity.
Shall we then say that specific acts of suppositional reasoning are themselves
justified by principles of extrapolation – not, to be sure, the very same principle
that the piece of suppositional reasoning is meant to justify, but another, higherorder, principle, relating suppositions and unacceptable consequences? The new
principle is, in its turn, justified just in case there is a principled absence of doubt,
and the absence of such doubt is created and sustained by still another intervention
of coherence-seeking, suppositional reason. The chain of justification threatens to
be regressive.
Nelson Goodman’s influential proposal is that there is a virtuous circle of
justification:31
Principles of deductive inference are justified by their conformity with accepted
deductive practice. Their validity depends upon accordance with the particular
deductive inferences we actually make and sanction. If a rule yields
unacceptable inferences, we drop it as invalid. Justification of general rules
thus derives from judgements rejecting or accepting particular deductive
inferences.
I have said that deductive inferences are justified by their conformity to
valid general rules, and that general rules are justified by their conformity to
164
Philosophy in classical India
valid inference. But this circle is a virtuous one. . . . A rule is amended if it
yields an inference we are unwilling to accept; an inference is rejected if it
violates a rule we are unwilling to amend. The process of justification is the
delicate one of making mutual adjustments between rules and accepted
inferences; and in the agreement thus achieved lies the only justification
needed for either.
All this applies equally well to induction. An inductive inference, too, is
justified by conformity to general rules, and a general rule by conformity to
accepted inductive inference.
The idea is that an iterated process of adjustment leads eventually to a
situation in which the specific inferences and the principles of inferences are
in ‘reflective equilibrium’.32 From an initial set of intuitively compelling
inferences, one formulates those principles that give a best fit. Some of the
initial inferences cannot be made to fit, and these we now revise in line with
our newly discovered principles. The eventual state of complete accord is one
in which the principles best explicate the inferences, and the inferences
explicate the principles (Figure 6.1).
Figure 6.1 The virtuous circle
There is a serious difficulty with this proposal.33 It is that the method at
best leads to a characterisation of a person’s inferential skills, but is unable to
determine if the person is inferentially competent. The method of best fit is
conservative, justifying with only minor scope for revision the rules of inference
actually instantiated by the person’s inferential practice. It seems from the
empirical studies of Stich and Nisbett34 that most people reason in accordance
with some version of the gambler’s fallacy when dealing with games of chance.
Applying the reflective equilibrium test here would lead to the certification of
a wholly unacceptable principle of inference.
Gangesa, as we saw, does endorse a reflective equilibrium between specific
inferences and principles of inference. One the one hand, extrapolation relations
are what justify specific extrapolations. On the other hand, Gangesa insists
that certain principles of extrapolation are justified by actual behaviour. It is
Reason in equilibrium
165
not possible for someone rationally to doubt the principle ‘where there is
smoke, there is fire,’ and at the same time to seek out the fire whenever they
encounter smoke. The principle is justified because it cannot reasonably be
doubted, and the absence of such doubt is sustained by the person’s inferentially
grounded behaviour.
What saves the account is that there are other ways for principles of inference
to be revised. The equilibrium is ‘wide’ rather than ‘narrow’.35 Principles of
inference are revised in a process of reflecting, more or less a priori, on
possible alternatives. Being the rule that best fits actual inferential practice is
not sufficient. A principle of inference must also be found on reflection to
cohere with other beliefs, principles and theories. The principle underlying
inference in accordance with the gambler’s fallacy coheres poorly with
probabilistic theory, and a person who knows this will at least attempt to
revise their rules of inference accordingly. The role of suppositional reasoning
in Gangesa’s theory, like that of philosophical argument in standard accounts
of wide reflective equilibrium, is to render any partial or local reflective
equilibrium liable to disruption under the pressure of broad reflective analysis
(Figure 6.2).
Figure 6.2 Reason in balance
Sriharsa’s point is that suppositional reasoning itself depends for its
justification on further, higher-order, principles of inference, and those principles
too require justification. Gangesa blocks the regress by observing that even if
the use of suppositional reasoning is the main way to justify principles of
inference, those principles can also be justified in other ways. They can be
justified pragmatically, with reference to practice and specific judgments –
that is the way of narrow equilibrium. In addition, however, some principles
are, at least in part, self-certifying, in the sense that they themselves
prevent any doubt as to their veracity arising. These are principles to doubt
which itself eliminates the doubt. A strong contender must be the principle of
166
Philosophy in classical India
non-contradiction – for any doubt of the form ‘is it that A or ~A?’ presupposes
that, at most, one of ‘A’ and ‘~A’ is true. The use of coherence-seeking reason
is itself justified by this principle, and so the spiral of doubt and doxastic
ascent is turned in upon itself.
These self-doubt-eliminating principles are foundational elements in an
otherwise coherentist theory. The claim is not that they are necessarily or selfevidently true: a logical possibility remains open that they are false. The
claim is rather that a revision of these principles would catastrophically perturb
the equilibrium of reflective justification. All other principles can be revised
under the pressure of suitably compelling philosophical arguments, but these
are preconditions for there to be a stable rational structure, and so form a
group of principles independent of the others.36
Suppositional reasoning, Gangesa claims, is not always needed in the
justification of general principles, for there are cases when to doubt a principle
would result in a practical contradiction with one’s own actions. True,
reflective or suppositional reasoning alone will never bring the chain of
justification to an end, but, nevertheless, and as a matter of contingent fact,
our belief-forming processes are reliable. It is the fact that they do actually
yield largely true beliefs, that our actions in accordance with their deliverances
do actually meet with success, that belies any doubt concerning them.
Suppositional rationality is an epistemic virtue – it is that which maintains
our beliefs, principles and theories in a virtuous circle of mutual justification.
But rationality by itself provides no guarrantee that our beliefs are generally
free from error, or even free from massive error. The world must cooperate –
we must happen to live in a world in which our belief-forming processes are
generally reliable, so that they are epistemic virtues too. Reflective or
suppositional reasoning by itself is of little epistemic value – the victim of an
evil demon might be entirely rational, in respect of the internal coherence of
their beliefs and principles. Their epistemic failing is not one of internal
rationality, but lies rather in the contingent fact that their external beliefforming processes are unreliable followers of the truth. But suppositional
reasoning is an epistemic virtue for us, nevertheless, because it works in tandem
with our reliable belief-forming processes to give us a comprehensive
understanding of ourselves as truth-seekers and an assurance that we have
beliefs that cohere with our deep intellectual standards.
In a penetrating study of the place of reason in Indian thought, J. N. Mohanty
has raised a foundational problem for Indian epistemological theories.37 Each
of the Indian schools selects certain means and methods of belief-formation
(pramana), and asserts that beliefs derive warrant when acquired from those
preferred methods. The problem is to explain the basis for selection:
[I]t appears as though the laying bare of the rationality of our beliefs and
cognitions, of moral rules and artistic creations, confronts, in Indian
thought, an absolute limit. The pramanas establish them, consciousness
evidences this act of establishment, but the judicative authority of the
Reason in equilibrium
167
pramanas is not, and cannot be, traced back to their origin in the structure
of that consciousness. The concept of rationality as operative – even if
not thematized – in Indian thought depends upon our answer to this
question.
This is rather similar to Roderick Chisholm’s ‘problem of the criterion’ – is it
that beliefs are justified because they meet criteria that are given in advance,
or that criteria are justified because they sanction particular well-attested
beliefs?38 Gangesa, it seems to me, is proposing a solution. He describes a
structure of epistemic support in which one’s beliefs, rules and actions are
brought together into a single body of mutual justification. The selected methods
of acquiring evidence and principles of extrapolation are justified because
they are what we end up with after a process of mutual revision and adjustment,
a process which includes both reflective consideration of the alternatives (tarka)
and empirical testing against the patterns of regular success in one’s behaviour.
Reason alone cannot eliminate all uncertainty: we must also be in a relation
of nonaccidental contact with the external world. Rationality in Gangesa’s
epistemology involves the use of imagination and hypothetical supposition to
bring our beliefs and principles into a state of reflective equilibrium. Reason
alone, contra Descartes, cannot be used to eliminate all uncertainty; rather,
the proper work of reason is in making ourselves epistemically more virtuous
in a cooperative world. Reason is in a fine balance.39
FURTHER READING
Texts
Jayarasi c. AD 800, Tattvopaplasimha (TUS).
Sriharsa c. AD 1140, Khandanakhandakhadya (KhKh).
Gangesa c. AD 1320, Tattvacintamani (TC).
Suppositional reasoning (6.1–4)
1 Sitansusekhar Bagchi, Inductive Reasoning: A Study of Tarka and its
Role in Indian Logic (Calcutta: Munishchandra Sinha, 1953).
2 Vijay Bharadwaja, Form and Validity in Indian Logic (Shimla: Indian
Institute of Advanced Study, 1990), Chapter 5.
3 Esther Solomon, Indian Dialectics (Ahmedabad: B. J. Institute of Learning
and Research, 1976), Chapter 12 (Vol. 1), Chapter 13 (Vol. 2).
Scepticism, doxastic ascent (6.5)
1 Phyllis Granoff, Philosophy and Argument in Late Vedanta: Sriharsa’s
Khandanakhandakhadya (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1978).
168
Philosophy in classical India
2 Stephen Phillips, Classical Indian Metaphysics (La Salle: Open Court,
1995), Chapter 3.
3 Bimal Matilal, Logical and Ethical Issues in Religious Belief (Calcutta:
University of Calcutta Press, 1982), Chapter 4.
4 Bimal Matilal, The Logical Illumination of Indian Mysticism, inaugural
lecture (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977).
5 C. Ram–Prasad, ‘Immediacy and the Direct Theory of Perception:
Problems from Sriharsa,’ Studies in Humanities and Social Sciences 3.2 (1996)
– Epistemology, Logic and Ontology After Matilal (Shimla: Indian Institute
of Advanced Studies), pp. 33–56.
Epistemic equilibrium, the new epistemology (6.6)
1 Stephen Phillips, Classical Indian Metaphysics (La Salle: Open Court,
1995), Chapter 4.
2 Mrinalkanti Gangopadhyay, ‘Gangesa on vyaptigraha: The Means for
the Ascertainment of Invariable Concomitance,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy
3 (1975), pp. 167–208.
3 Bimal Krishna Matilal, Perception: An Essay on Classical Indian Theories
of Knowledge (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), Chapters 4, 5.
Notes
Introduction
1 Taittiriya Upanisad 2.4.
2 Max Müller, The Six Systems of Indian Philosophy (Oxford, 1899); Sarvepalli
Radhakrishnan, Indian Philosophy (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1923);
in the same vein is M. Hiriyanna, Outlines of Indian Philosophy (London, 1932).
The origin of ‘six system’ doxographies goes back in fact to Haribhadra’s eighthcentury saddarsanasamuccaya.
3 J. N. Mohanty, Essays on Indian Philosophy, Purushottama Bilimoria ed., (Delhi:
Oxford University Press, 1993), p. 261. See also J. N. Mohanty, Reason and
Tradition in Indian Thought (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992). Robert Solomon,
in ‘Existentialism, Emotions, and the Cultural Limits of Rationality,’ Philosophy
East and West 42 (1992), pp. 597–621, cautions against Mohanty’s
‘intellectualisation’ of the notion of rationality, an upping of the ante to the point
where only philosophers satisfy their definition of a rational agent. In pressing the
point, however, one must distinguish carefully between practices and norms. A
philosophical theory of rationality describes an ideal against which actual rational
practices are to be judged.
4 See his papers in the section entitled ‘Dharma, Rationality and Moral Dilemmas,’
in B. K. Matilal, Philosophy, Culture and Religion: Collected Essays, Vol. 2: Ethics
and Epics (Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2001).
5 A. K. Ramanujan, ‘Is There an Indian Way of Thinking?’ Contributions to Indian
Sociology 23 (1989), pp. 41–58.
6 Another endorsement of the type-difference hypothesis is to be found in the
earlier work of Max Weber. For anthropological evidence against the hypothesis,
see Jack Goody, ‘East and West: Rationality in Review,’ Ethnos (1992), pp. 6–36.
For an argument in favour of the idea that judgments of rationality can be made
cross-culturally, see Charles Taylor, ‘Rationality,’ in his Philosophy and the Human
Sciences: Philosophical Papers 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985),
pp. 134–151.
7 Lakshmi Ramakrishnan, ‘On Talk of Modes of Thought,’ Journal of the Indian
Council of Philosophical Research 13.2 (1996), pp. 1–17. Quotation at p. 17.
The criticism is pressed in the first instance against views J. N. Mohanty expresses
in his Reason and Tradition in Indian Thought (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992).
8 For the Indian solutions: Jonardon Ganeri, Semantic Powers: Meaning and the
Means of Knowing in Classical Indian Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1999), Chapter 5.
9 See Gary Gutting, Michel Foucault’s Archaeology of Scientific Reason (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1989), Chapter 1.
170 Philosophy in classical India
10 David Seyfort Ruegg, ‘Does the Madhyamika have a Thesis and Philosophical
Position?,’ in B. K. Matilal and R. D. Evans eds., Buddhist Logic and Epistemology
(Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1986), p. 236.
11 David Hume, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, Part VII.
1 The motive and method of rational inquiry
1 Manusamhita 2.11.
2 J. W. McCrindle, Ancient India as Described by Megasthenes and Arrian: Being a
Translation of the Fragments of the Indika of Megasthenes and the First Part of
the Indika of Arrian (Calcutta, 1926); Allan Dahlquist, Megasthenes and Indian
Religion: A Study in Motives and Types (Uppsala: Almquist & Wiksell, 1962).
3 Hermann J. Jacobi, ‘A Contribution Towards the Early History of Indian
Philosophy,’ translated by V. A. Sukthankar, The Indian Antiquary XLVII (1918),
pp. 101–109.
4 Paul Hacker, ‘Anviksiki,’ Wiener Zeitschrift für die Kunde Süd- und Ost-Asiens 2
(1958), pp. 54–83. For a detailed discussion: Wilhelm Halbfass, ‘Darsana,
Anviksiki, Philosophy,’ in his India and Europe: An Essay in Understanding
(Albany: State University of New York Press, 1988), Chapter 15.
5 Franklin Edgerton, ‘The Meaning of Samkhya and yoga,’ American Journal of
Philology 45 (1924), pp. 1–47; Gerald James Larson, ‘Introduction to the
Philosophy of Samkhya,’ in Gerald James Larson and Ram Shankar Bhattacharya
eds., Samkhya: A Dualist Tradition in Indian Philosophy, Encyclopedia of Indian
Philosophies, Vol. 4 (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1987), pp. 3–9, 114–116.
6 Bertrand Russell, Human Society in Ethics and Politics (London: Allen and Unwin,
1954), p. viii.
7 Nyayabhasya 3, 11–14. All references are to page and line numbers in Thakur’s
critical edition: Gautamiyanyayadarsana with Bhasya of Vatsyayana, critically edited
by Anantalal Thakur (Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1997).
8 Nyayabhasya 3, 15–20.
9 Nyayabhasya 1, 6–10.
10 Nyayabhasya on 4.2.29.
11 Herbert Simon and Allen Newell, Human Problem Solving (Englewood Cliffs,
N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1972), pp. 71–105. Robert Nozick, The Nature of Rationality
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993), pp. 163–174.
12 Nyayabhasya 4, 14–18.
13 Uddyotakara. Nyayavarttika, 24, 3.
14 Kalidas Bhattacharya, ‘An Idea of Comparative Indian Philosophy,’ All India
Oriental Conference (Santiniketan, 1980), p. 80.
15 Nyayavarttika 28, 19–29, 1.
16 Roderick Chisholm, Theory of Knowledge (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall,
1966), pp. 56–69.
17 Bimal Krishna Matilal, Perception: An Essay on Classical Indian Theories of
Knowledge (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), p. 314.
18 Dinnaga, Pramanasamuccaya 1, 17; Uddyotakara, Nyayavarttika 208, 12–237,
5 (under 2.1.33–36).
19 Vatsyayana’s comment under NS 1.1.4, and Vaisesikasutra 3.1.13.
20 Nyayavarttika 36, 1–14 (under 1.1.4).
21 Compare Sartre’s criticism of Freud’s concept of a ‘censor’ governing unconscious
repression: ‘. . . the censor in order to apply its activity with discernment must
know what it is repressing . . . the censor must choose and in order to choose must
be aware of choosing . . .’. J-P. Sartre, Being and Nothingness: An Essay on
Phenomenological Ontology, translated by H. E. Barnes (London: Methuen &
Co., 1966), p. 52.
Notes 171
22 Nyayabhasya 19, 2–3 (above 1.1.16).
23 Joerg Tuske, ‘Being in Two Minds: The Divided Mind in the Nyayasutra,’ Asian
Philosophy 9.3 (1999), pp. 229–238. The ‘weak’ division, in which rationality is
attributed only to the whole person and not to any of its subsystems, is that of
Davidson: Donald Davidson, ‘Paradoxes of Irrationality,’ in R. Wollheim and J.
Hopkins eds., Philosophical Essays on Freud (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1982, pp. 289–305).
24 The classic exposition: Udayana, Atmatattvaviveka, pp. 710–719, p. 752. See
also Arindam Chakrabarti, ‘I Touch What I Saw,’ Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research 52 (1992), pp. 103–117.
25 For further analysis of the Nyaya anti-reductionist argument: Jonardon Ganeri,
‘Cross-modality and the Self,’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
(November 2000). There is interesting evidence from developmental psychology
that an infant’s acquisition of cross-modal capacities, specifically the ability to
identify its own tactually perceived facial expressions with the visually perceived
facial expressions of an imitating adult, is instrumental in its development of a
sense of self; see Andrew Meltzoff, ‘Molyneux’s Babies: Cross-Modal Perception,
Imitation, and the Mind of the Preverbal Infant,’ in N. Eilan, R. McCarthy and M.
W. Brewer eds, Spatial Representation: Problems in Philosophy and Psychology
(Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1993).
26 Nyayabhasya 12, 7–16 (below 1.1.5).
27 Carakasamhita, sutrasthana 11.13–14.
28 Upayahrdaya or Prayogasara. G. Tucci, Pre-Dinnaga Buddhist Texts on Logic
from Chinese Sources (Baroda: Oriental Institute, Gaekwad’s Oriental Series 49,
1929), pp. xvii–xviii.
29 G. Tucci, Pre-Dinnaga Buddhist Texts on Logic from Chinese Sources, p. xviii.
30 VS 2.1.8: ‘It has horns, a hump, a hairy tail at the extreme and a dewlap – such is
the perceived mark of cowness.’
31 Nyayabhasya 12, 4 (below 1.1.5).
32 The relations of master to property, matter to its altered condition, cause to effect,
efficient cause to caused, matter to form, concurrent occurrence, and hindering to
hindered. Further discussion: E. Frauwallner, ‘Die Erkenntnislehre des Klassischen
Samkhya-Systems,’ Wiener Zeitschrift für die Kunde Süd- und Ost-Asiens 2 (1958),
pp. 84–139, esp. pp. 123, 126–7; Nancy Schuster, ‘Inference in the Vaisesikasutras,’
Journal of Indian Philosophy 1 (1972), pp. 341–395; M. Nozawa, ‘Inferential Marks
in the Vaisesikasutras,’ Sambhasa: Nagoya Studies in Indian Culture and Buddhism
12 (1991), pp. 25–38; Claus Oetke, ‘Ancient Indian Logic as a Theory of NonMonotonic Reasoning,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 24 (1996), pp. 447–539.
33 Nyayabhasya 12, 16–19 (below 1.1.5).
34 Jayarasi, Tattvopaplavasimha 74, 8–9.
35 H. N. Randle, Indian Logic in the Early Schools (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1930), p. 148.
36 B. K. Matilal, The Character of Logic in India (Albany: State University of New
York Press, 1998), p. 32.
37 For an analysis of such reductive attempts in a wider context: Jonardon Ganeri,
‘Indian Logic and the Colonisation of Reason,’ in Jonardon Ganeri ed., Indian
Logic: A Reader (London: Curzon Press, 2001).
38 Stanislaw Schayer, ‘Über die Methode der Nyaya-Forschung,’ in O. Stein and W.
Gambert eds., Festschrift für Moritz Winternitz (Leipzig, 1933), pp. 247–257.
Schayer’s paper is translated into English by Joerg Tuske in Jonardon Ganeri ed.,
Indian Logic: A Reader (London: Curzon Press, 2001).
39 Nyayabhasya 285, 4–8 [below 5.1.3].
40 B. K. Matilal, The Character of Logic in India (Albany: State University of New
York Press, 1998), p. 63.
172 Philosophy in classical India
41 For detailed analysis: Pradeep P. Gokhale, Inference and Fallacies Discussed in
Ancient Indian Logic (Delhi: Sri Satguru Publications, 1992).
42 Nyayabhasya 14, 4–5.
43 On the status of the mleccha: Aloka Parasher, Mlecchas in Early India: A Study in
Attitudes Towards Outsiders upto AD 600 (New Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal,
1991).
44 Nyayabhasya 96, 16–97, 7 (below 2.1.68).
45 Elizabeth Fricker, ‘Against Gullibility,’ in B. K. Matilal and A. Chakrabarti eds.,
Knowing from Words (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1994), pp. 125–161.
46 For a fuller development of this defence: Jonardon Ganeri, Semantic Powers:
Meaning and the Means of Knowing in Classical Indian Philosophy (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1999), Chapters 1 and 2.
47 Nyayabhasya 87, 11–12 (below 2.1.52).
2 Rationality, emptiness and the objective view
1 David Seyfort Ruegg, The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in
India (Wiesbaden: Otto Harrassowitz, 1981), p. 2.
2 Mark Siderits, ‘Nagarjuna as Antirealist,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 16 (1988),
pp. 311–326; also his ‘Thinking on Empty: Madhyamaka Anti-Realism and
Canons of Rationality,’ in S. Biderman and B-A Scharfstein eds., Rationality in
Question (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1989), pp. 231–250.
3 David Loy, ‘The Clôture of Deconstruction: A Mahayana Critique of Derrida,’
International Philosophical Quarterly 27 (1987), pp. 59–80; Harold Coward,
Derrida and Indian Philosophy (Albany: State University of New York Press,
1990), Chapter 6; Kenneth Liberman, ‘The Grammatology of Emptiness,’
International Philosophical Quarterly 31.4 (1991), pp. 183–195; Bimal K. Matilal,
‘Is Prasanga a Form of Deconstruction?’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 20 (1992),
pp. 345–362.
4 Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press,
1986), p. 4: ‘To acquire a more objective understanding of some aspect of life or
the world, we step back from our initial view of it and form a new conception
which has that view and its relation to the world as its object. In other words, we
place ourselves in the world that is to be understood. The old view then comes to
be regarded as an appearance, more subjective than the new view, and correctable
or confirmable by reference to it. The process can be repeated, yielding a still more
objective conception.’
5 Bernard Williams, Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry (Harmondsworth:
Penguin, 1978), pp. 64–65.
6 E. S. Spelke and G. A. Van De Walle, ‘Perceiving and Reasoning about Objects:
Insights from Infants,’ in Naomi Eilan, Rosaleen McCarthy and Bill Brewer eds.,
Spatial Representation (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), pp. 132–161.
7 Santideva, Bodhicaryavatara 9.35.
8 On presupposition and truth-value gaps: P. F. Strawson, Introduction to Logical
Theory (London: Methuen, 1952).
9 Further examples: MK 25.17, 25.18, 27.15–18. Interesting is the suggestion of
Richard Robinson that the method of reasoning from the four options has two
distinct functions, a positive therapeutic role, as exhibited by the unnegated forms,
and a destructive dialectical role, exhibited by the negated forms. Richard H.
Robinson, Early Madhyamika in India and China (Madison, Milwaukee and
London: University of Winsconsin Press, 1967), pp. 39–58, esp. pp. 55–56.
10 On other patterns in Nagarjuna’s argumentation: Richard H. Robinson, Early
Madhyamika in India and China, p. 48.
11 Bimal Krishna Matilal, The Logical Illumination of Indian Mysticism (Oxford:
Notes 173
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
Clarendon Press, 1977), p. 7; cf. ‘Is Prasanga a Form of Deconstruction?’ Journal
of Indian Philosophy 20 (1992), p. 353. Richard Hayes, ‘Nagarjuna’s Appeal,’
Journal of Indian Philosophy 22 (1994), pp. 309–410. The translation of MK
15.8–9 below follows Hayes, pp. 368–9.
Graham Priest, ‘The Structure of the Paradoxes of Self-Reference,’ Mind 103
(1994), pp. 25–34; Beyond the Limits of Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1995).
For the comparison: Thomas McEvilley, ‘Pyrrhonism and Madhyamika,’
Philosophy East and West 32 (1982), pp. 3–35. Against: Mark Siderits, ‘Matilal
on Nagarjuna,’ in P. Bilimoria and J. N. Mohanty eds., Relativism, Suffering and
Beyond: Essays in Memory of B. K. Matilal (Delhi: Oxford University Press,
1997), pp. 69–92.
Benson Mates, The Skeptic Way: Sextus Empiricus’s Outlines of Pyrrhonism
(New York: Oxford University Press, 1996), p. 176.
Richard Robinson, ‘Some Logical Aspects of Nagarjuna’s System,’ Philosophy East
and West 6 (1957), pp. 291–308; ‘Did Nagarjuna Really Refute All Philosophical
Views?’ Philosophy East and West 22 (1972), pp. 325–331. Richard Hayes,
‘Nagarjuna’s Appeal,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 22 (1994), pp. 299–378.
Jonardon Ganeri, Semantic Powers: Meaning and the Means of Knowing in
Classical Indian Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999), Chapter 5.
Ernest Sosa, Knowledge in Perspective (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1991), p. 181.
My argument in this paragraph follows David Burton, Emptiness Appraised: A
Critical Study of Nagarjuna’s Philosophy (London: Curzon Press, 1999), pp.
160–172. On the debating trick of ‘quibbling’ (chala): B. K. Matilal, The Character
of Logic in India (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1998), pp. 47–48.
Compare Graham Priest on Sextus Empiricus: Beyond the Limits of Thought
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), p. 48.
Bimal K. Matilal, Perception: An Essay on Classical Indian Theories of Knowledge
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986).
Pramanasamuccaya II, 1.
Kamaleswar Bhattacharya, ‘Nagarjuna’s Arguments against Motion: Their
Grammatical Basis,’ in G. Bhattacharya et al. eds., A Corpus of Indian Studies:
Essays in Honour of Professor Gaurinath Sastri (Calcutta: Sanskrit Pustak
Bhandar, 1980), pp. 85–95; ‘The Grammatical Basis of Nagarjuna’s Arguments:
Some Further Considerations,’ Indologica Taurinensia, 8–9 (1980–1), pp. 35–
43; ‘Nagarjuna’s Arguments Against Motion,’ Journal of the International
Association of Buddhist Studies 8 (1985), pp. 7–16. For criticism: George
Cardona, ‘A Path Still Taken: Some Early Indian Arguments Concerning Time,’
Journal of the American Oriental Society 111.3 (1991), pp. 445–464. Reply:
Kamaleswar Bhattacharya, ‘Back to Nagarjuna and Grammar,’ The Adyar Library
Bulletin 59 (1995), pp. 178–189.
Jonardon Ganeri, Semantic Powers: Meaning and the Means of Knowing in
Classical Indian Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999), Chapter 2.1.
Bimal K. Matilal, Epistemology, Logic and Grammar in Indian Philosophical
Analysis (The Hague: Mouton, 1971), pp. 60–2; see also his The Navya-Nyaya
Doctrine of Negation (Harvard: Harvard University Press, 1968), pp. 72–73.
David Lewis, The Plurality of Worlds (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986), pp. 202–
204; E. J. Lowe, ‘Lewis on Persistence versus Endurance,’ Analysis 47 (1987), pp.
152–154; David Lewis, ‘Rearrangement of Particles: Reply to Lowe,’ Analysis 48
(1988), pp. 65–72. For defences of the adverbial solution: Sally Haslanger, Change,
Persistence and Possibility (Ph.D. dissertation, University of California, 1985);
Mark Johnston, ‘Is There a Problem About Persistence?’ Aristotelian Society
Supplementary Volume 61 (1987), pp. 107–135.
174 Philosophy in classical India
26 Mark Siderits and J. Dervin O’Brien, ‘Zeno and Nagarjuna on Motion,’ Philosophy
East and West 26 (1976), pp. 281–299. Brian Galloway, ‘Notes on Nagarjuna
and Zeno on Motion,’ The Journal of the International Association of Buddhist
Studies 10 (1987), pp. 80–87.
27 Physics 239b11–13; 239b14–16; 239b5–9; 239b30–3; 239b33–40a. Translation:
Jonathan Barnes ed., The Complete Works of Aristotle (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1985).
28 Jonathan Lear, ‘A Note on Zeno’s Arrow,’ Phronesis 26 (1981), pp. 91–104.
29 Jorge Luis Borges, Collected Fictions, translated by Andrew Hurley (London:
Penguin Books, 1998), pp. 96–100.
30 David Seyfort Ruegg, ‘Does the Madhyamika have a Thesis and Philosophical
Position?’ in B. K. Matilal and R. D. G. Evans eds., Buddhist Logic and
Epistemology: Studies in The Buddhist Analysis of Inference and Language
(Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1982), pp. 229–238.
31 Some prefer to resolve the tension by dropping the global concept scepticism:
David Burton, Emptiness Appraised: A Critical Study of Nagarjuna’s Philosophy
(London: Curzon Press, 1999), Chapters 1–4.
3 The rational basis of metaphysics
1 Wilhelm Halbfass, On Being and What There Is: Classical Vaisesika and the
History of Indian Ontology (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992),
esp. p. 54.
2 Gilbert Ryle, The Concept of Mind (London: Hutchinson & Co., 1949), Chapter 1.
3 An excellent review of the details of Vaisesika ontology is Karl Potter ed., Indian
Metaphysics and Epistemology – The Tradition of Nyaya-Vaisesika up to Gangesa,
Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Vol. 2 (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1977),
Introduction.
4 Kiranavali, p. 160.
5 Numbering of the verses in the Laksanavali follows Musashi Tachikawa, The
Structure of the World in Udayana’s Realism: A Study of the Laksanavali and the
Kiranavali (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1981).
6 Vaisesikasutra 1.1.14: ‘The characteristic of a substance is to possess motions,
qualities and to be [their] inherence cause.’
7 In what follows, bold roman letters denote nodes in the graph, and italic letters
denote the entities those nodes represent.
8 Vaisesikasutra 1.1.15–6. Padarthadharmasamgraha 18. Section numbering in
the Padarthadharmasamgraha follows Karl Potter ed., Indian Metaphysics and
Epistemology – The Tradition of Nyaya-Vaisesika up to Gangesa, Encyclopedia
of Indian Philosophies, Vol. 2 (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1977), pp. 282–303.
9 Padarthadharmasamgraha 50–51.
10 Nyayabhusana, p. 158.
11 Vaisesikasutra 1.1.16.
12 For later comment on Bhasarvajña’s revision: Karl Potter and Sibajiban
Bhattacharyya eds., Indian Philosophical Analysis – Nyaya-Vaisesika from
Gangesa to Raghunatha Siromani, Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Vol. 6
(Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1993), pp. 323, 525–528.
13 Padarthatattvanirupana, p. 43.
14 Musashi Yachikawa, The Structure of the World in Udayana’s Realism: A Study
of the Laksanavali and the Kiranavali (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company,
1981), p. 41.
15 Kiranavali, p. 161.
16 In favour: Richard Thomason, ‘Species, Determinates, and Natural Kinds,’ Noûs
3 (1969), pp. 95–101; Ian Hacking, ‘Working in a New World: The Taxonomic
Notes 175
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
Solution,’ in Paul Horwich ed., World Changes: Thomas Kuhn and the Nature of
Science (Cambridge, Mass., MIT Press, 1993), pp. 275–310; Peter Gärdenfors,
‘Induction, Conceptual Spaces, and AI,’ in Douglas Stalker ed., Grue! The New
Riddle of Induction (Chicago: Open Court, 1994), pp. 117–134. Against: Ronald
de Sousa, ‘The Natural Shiftiness of Natural Kinds,’ Canadian Journal of
Philosophy 14 (1984), pp. 561–580; Muhamad Ali Khalida, ‘Natural Kinds and
Crosscutting Categories,’ Journal of Philosophy 95 (1998), pp. 33–50.
Vaisesikasutra 1.2.4. Wilhelm Halbfass, On Being and What There Is: Classical
Vaisesika and the History of Indian Ontology (Albany: State University of New
York Press, 1992), Chapter 7.
Ian Hacking, ‘Working in a New World: The Taxonomic Solution,’ in Paul Horwich
ed., World Changes: Thomas Kuhn and the Nature of Science (Cambridge, Mass.,
MIT Press, 1993), pp. 286–289.
Bimal Krishna Matilal, Perception: An Essay on Classical Indian Theory of
Knowledge (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), Chapter 12.
Apararkadeva, a follower of Bhasarvajña. Nyayamuktavali, S. S. Sastri and V. S.
Sastri ed., (Madras: Madras Government Oriental Series 167, 1961), pp. 120–
126; précis by S. S. Sastri in Karl Potter ed., Indian Epistemology and Metaphysics,
Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Vol. 2 (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1977), pp. 604–612.
Raghunatha. Kiranavaliprakasadidhiti (Badrinath Sastri ed., Princess of Wales
Saraswati Bhavana Texts 38, Benares: Vidya Vilas Press 1932), p. 15. For comment:
Karl Potter, The Padarthatattvanirupanam of Raghunatha Siromani (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, Harvard Yenching Institute Studies, Vol. 17,
1957), pp. 65–66.
Muhamad Ali Khalida, ‘Natural Khan and Crosscutting Categories,’ Journal of
Philosophy 95 (1998), pp. 33–50.
Daniel Ingalls, Materials for the Study of Navya-Nyaya Logic (Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press, 1951), p. 67.
What about the distinction between absential and antinodes? The traditional way
of making the distinction is to say that simple absence is the denial of inherence (or
some other non-identity relation) and difference is the denial of identity. Graphtheoretically, the distinctive feature of an antinode x* is that it absentially qualifies
every node other than x, while an absential node x′ does not. Does this difference
fail when x is something which inheres in nothing (an atom, an individuator)? No,
because such things do not inhere in themselves – so x′, unlike x*, absentially
qualifies x. Indeed, this second contrast is itself sufficient to discriminate absential
nodes and antinodes.
Raghunatha, Padarthatattvanirupana, p. 55. Daniel Ingalls, Materials for the
Study of Navya-Nyaya Logic (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1951),
p. 68. Bimal K. Matilal, Logic, Language and Reality (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass,
1985), p. 149. Roy W. Perrett, ‘Is Whatever Exists Knowable and Nameable?’
Philosophy East and West 49.4 (1999), pp. 410–414, esp. 408–9. I disagree here
with the idea of Matilal and Perrett that there is only an intensional difference
between an object and the absence of its absence. For me, a type difference in the
graph means a type difference in categories of thing.
Padarthatattvanirupana, pp. 67–69. Daniel Ingalls, Materials, pp. 68–69; Bimal
K. Matilal, Logic, Language and Reality, pp. 149–150.
Daniel Ingalls draws a comparison between Navya-Nyaya and intuitionist logic
(Materials, p. 68, n. 135), claiming that it is the Elimination rule for double
negation that is rejected. However we are able, in Navya-Nyaya logic, to infer
from the absence of the absence of an entity to the presence of that entity; conversely,
we are not able to infer from the presence of an entity to the absence of its absence
– the non-pervasive node is a counter-example.
176 Philosophy in classical India
28 Daniel Ingalls, Materials for the Study of Navya-Nyaya Logic (Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press, 1951), pp. 73–4; Bimal Matilal, The Navya-Nyaya Doctrine
of Negation (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1968), pp. 53, 72, 85;
Logic, Language and Reality (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1985), pp. 119–122.
29 Frege’s notion of ‘divisibility’ is formally rather analogous. Gottlob Frege, The
Foundations of Arithmetic, translated by J. L. Austin (Oxford: Basil Blackwell,
1950), p. 66: ‘The syllables “letters in the word three” pick out the word as a
whole, and as indivisible in the sense that no part of it falls any longer under the
same concept. Not all concepts possess this quality. We can, for example, divide
up something falling under the concept “red” into parts in a variety of ways,
without the parts thereby ceasing to fall under the same concept “red.”’
30 Karl Potter ed., Indian Metaphysics and Epistemology – The Tradition of NyayaVaisesika up to Gangesa, Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Vol. 2 (Delhi:
Motilal Banarsidass, 1977), pp. 114–119.
31 Raghunatha, Padarthatattvanirupana, pp. 44–46.
32 Dharmakirti, Pramanavarttika II, 85–86; Kamalasila, Pañjika under
Tattvasamgraha 592–598.
33 Udayana, Atmatattvaviveka, pp. 586–617. Prabal Kumar Sen, ‘The NyayaVaisesika Theory of Variegated Colour (citrarupa): Some Vexed Problems,’ Studies
in Humanities and Social Sciences 3.2 (1996), pp. 151–172.
34 Daniel Ingalls, Materials, pp. 73–4; Bimal Matilal, The Navya-Nyaya Doctrine of
Negation (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1968), pp. 71–73.
35 Matilal’s property-location language, in which properties have both a ‘presence
range’ and an ‘absence range’ and the two ranges are permitted to overlap, is a
different way to capture the same idea; B. K. Matilal, Logic, Language and Reality,
pp. 112–127.
36 Gangesa, Tattvacintamani, I, pramalaksana, p. 401.
37 For modern discussions of dialetheism: Graham Priest, In Contradiction: A Study
of the Transconsistent (Dordrecht: Martin Nijhoff Publishers, 1987), Part Two;
Mark Sainsbury, Paradoxes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995, 2nd
edn.), Chapter 6.
38 Gangesa, Tattvacintamani, II, vyaptipañcaka, pp. 27–31.
39 Gangesa, Tattvacintamani, II, siddhanta-laksana p. 100.
40 I follow here the explanation of Raghunatha. Vyaptipañcakadidhiti text 3–4
(Ingalls, Materials, p. 154).
41 Vaisesikasutra 1.1.9, 7.2.1–8.
42 Nyayabhusana, p. 159.
43 For the generalisation to numbers greater than 2: Jonardon Ganeri, ‘Objectivity
and Proof in a Classical Indian Theory of Number,’ Synthese (forthcoming).
44 Saktivada with Krsna Bhatta’s Mañjusa, Madhava Bhattacarya’s Vivrtti and Sahitya
Darsanacarya’s Vinodini, G. D. Sastri ed. (Benares: Kashi Sanskrit Series no. 57,
1927), p. 189.
45 Padarthatattvanirupana, pp. 86–87.
46 Avacchedakatvanirukti with Jagadisa’s Jagadisi, Dharmananda Mahabhaga ed.,
(Varanasi: Kashi Sanskrit Series 203), p. 38. Translation: Yuko Miyasaka, The
Concept of Avacchedakatva in Navya-Nyaya (containing the text of Raghunatha
Siromani’s Avacchedakatvanirukti and its Commentary Jagadisi with an English
Translation, Explanatory Notes and a Detailed Introduction) (Poona: Centre of
Advanced Study in Sanskrit, Ph.D. Thesis, 1980).
4 Reduction, exclusion and rational reconstruction
1 For this contrast: Huw Price, ‘Metaphysical Pluralism,’ Journal of Philosophy 89
(1992), pp. 387–410. Price prefers ‘additive monism’ where I have chosen ‘additive
Notes 177
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
realism,’ on the reasonable grounds that reductionism and pluralism too are
varieties of realism. But ‘monism’ is a loaded term in Indian philosophical theory,
frequently attaching to specific doctrines in the school of Advaita Vedanta, and so
I avoid it here.
G. F. Stout, ‘The Nature of Universals and Propositions,’ Proceedings of the
British Academy 10 (1921), pp. 157–172.
D. C. Williams, ‘On the Elements of Being,’ Review of Metaphysics 7 (1953), pp.
171–192.
Pramanasamuccaya. The Sanskrit original is lost. Translations from the Tibetan
are taken from (Chapter I) Masaaki Hattori, Dignaga, On Perception, being the
Pratyaksapariccheda of Dignaga’s Pramanasamuccaya from the Sanskrit
fragments and the Tibetan versions (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,
1968), and (Chapters II and V) Richard Hayes, Dignaga on the Interpretation of
Signs (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1988), revised following Shoryu
Katsura, ‘Dignaga and Dharmakirti on apoha,’ in E. Steinkellner ed., Studies in
the Buddhist Epistemological Tradition (Vienna: Österreichische Akademie der
Wissenschaften, 1991), pp. 129–146. In what follows, these are referred to by
chapter number, I, II or V.
Theodore Stcherbatsky, The Central Conception of Buddhism and the Meaning of
the Word ‘Dharma,’ (London: Royal Asiatic Society, 1922); Fumimaro Watanabe,
Philosophy and its Development in the Nikayas and Abhidharma (Delhi: Motilal
Banarsidass, 1983); Karl Potter et al. ed., Abhidharma Buddhism to 150 AD,
Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Vol. 7 (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1996).
Vasubandhu, Abhidharmakosa VI 14cd.
Dignaga on the Interpretation of Signs (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers,
1988); ‘Dinnaga,’ in E. Craig ed., Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1998),
Vol. 3, pp. 74–76: ‘The first method of securing new knowledge is described as
pure sensation (pratyaksa), a form of cognition that is free from all judgment
(kalpana). The subject of this type of cognition is particular instances (svalaksana)
of colour, sound and other sensible properties’ (p. 75).
‘Dinnaga’s Theory of Perception,’ in Epistemology, Logic and Grammar in Indian
Philosophical Analysis (Mouton: The Hague, 1971), pp. 34–39; ‘Imagination,
Perception and Language,’ in Perception (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), pp.
309–356; ‘Buddhist Logic and Epistemology,’ in B. K. Matilal and R. D. Evans
eds., Buddhist Logic and Epistemology: Studies in the Buddhist Analysis of
Inference and Language (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1982), pp. 1–
30; reprinted in his The Character of Logic in India (Albany: State University of
New York Press, 1998), Chapter 4.
Masaaki Hattori, Dignaga, On Perception, being the Pratyaksapariccheda of
Dignaga’s Pramanasamuccaya from the Sanskrit fragments and the Tibetan
versions (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1968); ‘Apoha and
Pratibha,’ in M. Nagatomi et al. eds. Sanskrit and Indian Studies: Essays in
Honour of Daniel H. H. Ingalls (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1980),
pp. 61–74; ‘The Sautrantika Background of the Apoha Theory,’ in Leslie S.
Kawamura and Keith Scott eds., Buddhist Thought and Civilization: Essays in
Honour of Herbert V. Guenther on his Sixtieth Birthday (Emeryville: Dharma
Press, 1977), pp. 47–58.
Shoryu Katsura, ‘Dignaga and Dharmakirti on apoha,’ in E. Steinkellner ed.,
Studies in the Buddhist Epistemological Tradition (Vienna: Österreichische
Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1991), pp. 129–146.
B. K. Matilal, Epistemology, Logic and Grammar in Indian Philosophical Analysis
(The Hague: Mouton, 1971), pp. 34–36.
Jonardon Ganeri, Semantic Powers (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999), Chapter
6.2.
178 Philosophy in classical India
13 E. Frauwallner, ‘Dignaga, sein Werk und seine Entwicklung,’ Wiener Zeitschrift
für die Kunde Süd- und Ost-Asiens 3 (1959), pp. 83–164. Radhika Herzberger,
Bhartrhari and the Buddhists (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1986).
14 Later Buddhist theory makes a clear distinction between ‘synchronic’ and ‘diachronic’
modes of grouping; for the Jaina origins of the distinction: Piotr Balcerowicz, ‘How
Could a Cow be Both Synchronically and Diachronically Homogenous, or On the
Jaina Notions of tiryak-samanya and urdhvata-samanya,’ in N. K. Wagle and Olle
Qvarnström eds., Approaches to Jaina Studies: Philosophy, Logic, Rituals and
Symbols (Toronto: University of Toronto, 1999), pp. 211–235.
15 Nicholas Rescher, ‘The Roots of Objectivity,’ in Scientific Realism (Dordrecht:
Reidel Publishing Company, 1987), pp. 111–125. The quotation below is at p.
118.
16 Later Yogacara philosophers introduce the idea that the meaning of a general
term is a mental image (pratibimba) which is ‘qualified’ by an exclusion of others.
Santaraksita, Tattvasamgraha 1005–1010; see also Gopikamohan Bhattacharya,
‘Ratnakirti on Apoha,’ in B. K. Matilal and R. D. Evans eds., Buddhist Logic and
Epistemology: Studies in the Buddhist Analysis of Inference and Language
(Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1982), pp. 291–298. I do not believe
that Dinnaga himself endorses this view. In any case, the role of the mental image
is at best within explanations of the psychology of understanding; it is the exclusion
that does the semantic work.
17 Gennaro Chierchia and Sally McConnell-Ginet, Meaning and Grammar
(Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 1990). Dinnaga’s semantics analyses terms as
generalised quantifiers. Compare D. Westertähl, ‘Quantifiers,’ in D. Gabbay and
F. Guenther eds., The Handbook of Philosophical Logic, vol. 4: Topics in the
Philosophy of Language (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1988).
18 The class-theoretic formula is that, for any classes x and y, x ⊆ y iff x ∩ non-y = Ø.
19 Shoryu Katsura, ‘The apoha Theory of Dignaga,’ Indogaku Bukkyogaku Kenkyu
28 (1979), pp. (16)–(20). Katsura thinks that Dinnaga defines exclusion with
reference to a presupposed hierarchy. For me, the hierarchy is a consequence of
his exclusion theory of meaning.
20 Bimal K. Matilal, Epistemology, Logic and Grammar in Indian Philosophical
Analysis (The Hague: Mouton, 1971), Chapter 1.6. Jonardon Ganeri, Semantic
Powers (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999), Chapter 4.2.
21 Bimal Krishna Matilal, The Word and the World (Delhi: Oxford University Press,
1990), p. 97. Masaaki Hattori, ‘Apoha and Pratibha,’ in M. Nagatomi et al. eds.,
Sanskrit and Indian Studies: Essays in Honour of Daniel H. H. Ingalls (Dordrecht:
Reidel Publishing Company, 1980), pp. 61–74.
22 Vakyapadiyam, II 143.
23 Gottlob Frege, The Foundations of Arithmetic, translated by J. L. Austin. (Oxford:
Basil Blackwell, 1950), Introduction; see also Michael Dummett, Frege: Philosophy
of Mathematics (London, Duckworth, 1991), Chapter 16.
24 Masaaki Hattori, ‘Apoha and Pratibha,’ in M. Nagatomi et al. eds. Sanskrit and
Indian Studies: Essays in Honour of Daniel H. H. Ingalls (Dordrecht: Reidel
Publishing Company, 1980), p. 66.
25 Brendan S. Gillon and Richard Hayes, ‘The Role of the Particle eva in (Logical)
Quantification in Sanskrit,’ Wiener Zeitschrift für die Kunde Süd- und Ost-Asiens
26 (1982), pp. 195–203. Jonardon Ganeri, ‘Dharmakirti’s Semantics for the
Particle eva,’ in Shoryu Katsura ed., Dharmakirti’s Thought and Its Impact on
Indian and Tibetan Philosophy (Vienna: Österreichische Akademie der
Wissenschaften, 1999), pp. 101–116. Brendan Gillon, ‘Another Look at the
Sanskrit Particle eva,’ in Shoryu Katsura ed., Dharmakirti’s Thought and Its
Impact on Indian and Tibetan Philosophy (Vienna: Österreichische Akademie
der Wissenschaften, 1999), pp. 117–130.
Notes 179
26 Shoryu Katsura, ‘Dignaga on trairupya,’ Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies
32 (1983), pp. (15)–(21).
27 I discuss the behaviour of only without this assumption in Jonardon Ganeri,
‘Dharmakirti’s Semantics for the Particle eva (only),’ pp. 101–116.
28 Jinendrabuddhi; see M. Hattori, ‘Apoha and Pratibha,’ in M. Nagatomi et al.
eds., Sanskrit and Indian Studies: Essays in Honour of Daniel H. H. Ingalls
(Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1980), pp. 64–65.
29 Tom F. Tillemans, ‘On sapaksa,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 18 (1990), pp. 53–80.
30 Hans H. Herzberger, ‘Three Systems of Buddhist Logic,’ in B. K. Matilal and R. D.
Evans eds., Buddhist Logic and Epistemology: Studies in the Buddhist Analysis of
Inference and Language (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1982), pp. 59–76.
31 Bimal Matilal, ‘Buddhist Logic and Epistemology,’ in B. K. Matilal and R. D. Evans
eds., Buddhist Logic and Epistemology: Studies in the Buddhist Analysis of
Inference and Language (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1982), pp. 1–
30; reprinted in his The Character of Logic in India (Albany: State University of
New York Press, 1998), Chapter 4.
32 Collection on Knowing ad II 6. The various possibilities are represented in a
different way in Dinnaga’s brief Chart of Reasons (HC). There a 3 × 3 grid
represents the nine ways for the reason property to be distributed across the
likeness and unlikeness classes. Interesting is the proposal of Vijay Bharadwaja to
interpret the three conditions as requirements that the reason: (i) be ‘relevant’ to
the thesis; (ii) ‘support’ the thesis; and (iii) not ‘support’ the antithesis, with a
correlative reading of the chart of reasons and the fallacies of reason. Vijay
Bharadwaja, Form and Validity in Indian Logic (Shimla: Indian Institute of
Advanced Study, 1990), Chapters 1–3.
33 Motoi Ono, ‘Dharmakirti on asasarananaikantika,’ in Shoryu Katsura ed.,
Dharmakirti’s Thought and its Impact on Indian and Tibetan Philosophy (Vienna:
Österreichische Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1999), pp. 301–316. Bimal Krishna
Matilal, ‘Dharmakirti and the Universally Negative Inference,’ in E. Steinkellner ed.,
Studies in the Buddhist Epistemological Tradition (Vienna: Österreichische Akademie
der Wissenschaften, 1991), pp. 161–168. Reprinted in The Character of Logic in
India (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1998), pp. 118–126.
34 Dharmakirti, Nyayabindu II 11–12.
35 See Moksakaragupta’s eleventh-century Tarkabhasa or Language of Reason.
Yuichi Kajiyama, An Introduction to Buddhist Philosophy: An Annotated
Translation of the Tarkabhasa or Moksakaragupta, Memoirs of the Faculty of
Letters (Kyoto) 10 (1966), pp. 74–76.
36 Pramanavarttika I, 39–42.
37 Douglas Walton, Arguments from Ignorance (Penn.: The Pennsylvania State
University Press, 1996).
38 Shoryu Katsura, ‘Dharmakirti’s Concept of Truth,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy
12 (1984), pp. 213–235. Georges B. J. Dreyfus, Recognizing Reality: Dharmakirti’s
Philosophy and its Tibetan Interpretations (Albany: State University of New York
Press, 1997), Chapter 17.
39 Alambanapariksa (AP).
40 There is an analogy in the Epicurean account of what it is for a perceptual state to
have informational content. Richard Sorabji, Animal Minds and Human Morals
(London: Duckworth, 1993), p. 47. For modern defences of the matching
condition: David Lewis, ‘Veridical Hallucination and Prosthetic Vision,’ in
Philosophical Papers II (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986), pp. 273–290;
F. Dretske, Knowledge and the Flow of Information (Oxford: Basil Blackwell,
1981).
41 Pramanavarttika, III, 68–69. Shoryu Katsura, ‘On Perceptual Judgement,’ in N. K.
Wagle and F. Watanabe eds., Studies in Buddhism in Honour of Professor A. K.
180 Philosophy in classical India
Warder (Toronto: University of Toronto Centre for South Asian Studies, 1993),
pp. 66–75; see also his ‘Dignaga and Dharmakirti on apoha,’ in E. Steinkellner ed.,
Studies in the Buddhist Epistemological Tradition (Vienna: Österreichische Akademie
der Wissenschaften, 1991), p. 138, n. 40. Georges B. J. Dreyfus, Recognizing Reality.
Dharmakirti’s Philosophy and its Tibetan Interpretations (Albany: State University
of New York Press, 1997), pp. 359–361.
42 Collection on Knowing I 2c–3b.
5 Rationality, harmony and perspective
1 Haribhadra, Anekantajayapataka, H. R. Kapadia ed. (Baroda: Oriental Institute,
1940), esp. p. ix. B. K. Matilal, The Central Philosophy of Jainism (Ahmedabad:
L. D. Institute of Indology, 1981), p. 25.
2 Richard Fynes, Hemacandra: The Lives of the Jaina Elders (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1998).
3 Hemacandra, Pramanamimamsa. Paragraph numbering follows the edition of
Mookerjee and Tatia.
4 Y. J. Padmarajiah, Jaina Theories of Reality and Knowledge (Bombay: Jain Sahitya
Vikas Mandal, 1963), pp. 126–127.
5 Sanmatitarkaprakarana 3.49.
6 Brahmasutrabhasya 2.2.33.
7 Tattvasamgraha, verse 1722.
8 Bhagavatisutra 2.1.90. Bansidhar Bhatt, The Canonical Niksepa: Studies in Jaina
Dialectics (Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1978), pp. xiv and 68.
9 Jonardon Ganeri, Semantic Powers: Meaning and the Means of Knowing in
Classical Indian Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999), Chapters 3, 6.
10 P. F. Strawson, ‘On Referring,’ Mind 59 (1950), pp. 320–344. David Kaplan,
‘Demonstratives: An Essay on the Semantics, Logic, Metaphysics and Epistemology
of Demonstratives and Other Indexicals,’ in J. Almog, J. Perry, and H. Wettstein
eds., Themes From Kaplan (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989).
11 Stephen Schiffer, ‘Descriptions, Indexicals and Belief Reports: Some Dilemmas,’
Mind 104 (1995), pp. 107–131.
12 Siddhasena, Nyayavatara 29.
13 Vidyananda, Tattvarthaslokavarttika 1.6.21, 1.6.25.
14 Paul Dundas, The Jains (London: Routledge, 1992), p. 198.
15 Jaina Tarkabhasa p. 24; see also Sukhlalji Sanghvi, ‘Anekantavada: The Principal
Jaina Contribution to Logic,’ in his Advanced Studies in Indian Logic and
Metaphysics (Calcutta: Indian Studies Past and Present, 1961), pp. 24–26.
16 Huw Price, ‘Metaphysical Pluralism,’ Journal of Philosophy 89 (1992), pp.
387–410.
17 Pramananayatattvalokalamkara 4.13.
18 Pramanasamuccaya 5.1.
19 R. C. Pandeya, ‘The Conception of Syadvada,’ in R. A. Kumar, T. M. Dak and A.
D. Mishra eds., Anekantavada and Syadvada (Landun: Jain Visva Bharati, 1996),
pp. 314–322. Quotation: p. 321.
20 Syadvadamañjari below verse 23.
21 Pradeep P. Gokhale, ‘The Logical Structure of Syadvada,’ Journal of Indian Council
of Philosophical Research 8 (1991), pp. 73–81.
22 Graham Priest, Richard Routley and Jean Norman eds., Paraconsistent Logic:
Essays on the Inconsistent (Munchen: Philosophia Verlag, 1989), pp. 16–17.
23 Stanislaw Jaskowski, ‘Propositional Calculus for Contradictory Deductive
Systems,’ Studia Logica 24 (1969), pp. 143–157. Quotation: p. 149.
24 B. K. Matilal, ‘Anekanta: both yes and no?’ Journal of Indian Council of
Philosophical Research 8 (1991), pp. 1–12. Reprinted as ‘The Jaina Contribution
Notes 181
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
to Logic,’ in The Character of Logic in India (Albany: State University of New
York Press, 1998), pp. 127–139. Quotation: p. 137.
D. H. H. Ingalls, Materials for the Study of Navya-Nyaya Logic (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1951), p. 63.
It may accord slightly better with some Jaina formulations to parameterise over
properties or states, and treat ‘exists’ and ‘does not exist’ as assigning truthvalues to points (x, F) in the parameter space.
This interpretation of the value ‘unassertible’ resembles a standard interpretation
of the third value in Kleene’s three-valued system. Nicholas Rescher, Many-Valued
Logic (New York: McGraw Hill, 1963), p. 34.
Jaina Tarkabhasa, pp. 19–20.
Syadvadamañjari below verse 23.
A. L. Basham, History and Doctrines of the Ajivikas (London: Luzac & Co.,
1951). Translation, p. 274, slightly revised.
Laghiyastraya, verse 12.
On Akalanka on Dharmakirti: Nagin J. Shah, Akalanka’s Criticism of
Dharmakirti’s Philosophy (Ahmedabad: L. D. Institute, 1967), pp. 267–270.
Nyayakumudacandra, pp. 421–425.
Pravacanapravesa, verse 62 and autocommentary.
B. K. Matilal, The Central Philosophy of Jainism (Ahmedabad: L. D. Institute of
Indology, 1981).
Uttaradhyayanasutra 28.24; cited by K. N. Jayatilleke, Early Buddhist Theory of
Knowledge (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1963), p. 164.
6 Reason in equilibrium
1 Jayarasi (c. AD 800) is a principal source for the sceptical argument:
Tattvopaplasimha, pp. 64–65. Jayarasi is taken on by at least two Naiyayikas –
Bhasarvajña and Vyomasiva – in the centuries immediately subsequent to him;
see Eli Franco, Perception, Knowledge and Disbelief: A Study of Jayarasi’s
Scepticism, 2nd edn. (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1994), pp. 13–14, 554. A
second radical critic, Sriharsa (twelfth century AD) presses the sceptical position
with great vigour – his critique is at least a part of what drives the so-called New
Epistemology (Navya-Nyaya) of Gangesa and his followers towards a reform
of the earlier theory; see Stephen Phillips, Classical Indian Metaphysics (La Salle:
Open Court, 1995). On both: Esther Solomon, Indian Dialectics, 2 volumes
(Ahmedabad: B. J. Institute of Learning and Research, 1976), Chapter 13.
2 For a survey of the literature on this theory, see Karl Potter ed., Indian Epistemology
and Metaphysics, Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Vol. 2 (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1977), pp. 203–206; Karl Potter and Sibajiban
Bhattacharyya eds., Indian Analytical Philosophy: Gangesa to Raghunatha,
Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Vol. 6 (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1993), pp. 187–192.
3 Ernest Sosa, Knowledge in Perspective (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1991), pp. 225–244, esp. p. 240.
4 See also Bimal K. Matilal, Perception: An Essay on Classical Indian Theories of
Knowledge (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1986), pp. 153 167; Eli Franco,
‘Bhasarvajña and Jayarasi: The Refutation of Scepticism in the Nyayabhusana,’
Berliner Indologische Studien 3 (1987), pp. 23–49.
5 Nandita Bandyopadhyay, ‘The Concept of Contradiction in Indian Logic and
Epistemology,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 16.3 (1988), pp. 225–246, n. 1.
6 Nyayavarttikatatparyatika, p. 261 (below 1.1.40).
7 Tattvacintamani, 1892 (Vol. 2), pp. 210–212. The relevant passage is quoted in
full in Chapter 6.6.
182 Philosophy in classical India
8 Atmatattvaviveka, p. 863.
9 Douglas Walton, Arguments from Ignorance (Penn.: The Pennsylvania State
University Press, 1996).
10 On Sriharsa: Phyllis Granoff, Philosophy and Argument in Late Vedanta: Sriharsa’s
Khandanakhandakhadya (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1978);
Stephen Phillips, Classical Indian Metaphysics (La Salle: Open Court, 1995),
Chapter 3.
11 Khandanakhandakhadya IV, 19 (aprasangatmakatarkanirupana, pp. 777–788,
1979 edition; section numbering follows this edition). Sriharsa the negative
dialectician wants to criticise even the varieties of suppositional reasoning, although
his own method depends upon it. So he says: ‘By us indeed were suppositional
reasonings installed in place, and so we do not reject them with [such] counterarguments. As it is said – “it is wrong to cut down even a poisonous tree, having
cultivated it oneself”’ (p. 787).
12 Atmatattvaviveka, p. 533.
13 Khandanakhandakhadya II, 2 (pratibandilaksanakhandana, pp. 571–572). The
full quotation is given by Samkara Misra in his commentary.
14 Stanislaw Schayer, ‘Studies on Indian Logic, Part II: Ancient Indian Anticipations
of Propositional Logic’ [1933], translated into English by Joerg Tuske in Jonardon
Ganeri ed., Indian Logic: A Reader (London: Curzon Press, 2000).
15 Morris R. Cohen and Ernest Nagel, An Introduction to Logic and Scientific
Method (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1934), p. 384.
16 Bhimacarya Jhalakikar, Nyayakosa or Dictionary of Technical Terms of Indian
Philosophy (Poona: Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute, 1928), under
laghutvam.
17 A useful chart is in S. Bagchi, Inductive Reasoning, interleaved between p. 182
and p. 183.
18 Udayana, Parisuddhi, p. 304 (under NS 1.1.40).
19 Nyayakosa, under aharyam.
20 Visvesvara Pandit. Alankarakaustubham, M. P. Sivadatta and K. P. Parab eds.
(Bombay: Nirnaya-sagara Press, 1898; Kavyamala no. 66), pp. 207–208.
21 Mukund Lath, ‘The Concept of Aharya-jñana: Some Queries,’ Journal of the
Indian Council of Philosophical Research 13.1 (1995), pp. 175–181.
22 N. S. Dravid, ‘Aharya Cognition in Navya-Nyaya,’ Journal of the Indian Council
of Philosophical Research 14.2 (1996), pp. 164–168.
23 Vijay Bharadwaja, Form and Validity in Indian Logic (Shimla: Indian Institute of
Advanced Study, 1990), Chapter 5.
24 S. Bagchi, Inductive Reasoning, p. 59.
25 Bimal K. Matilal, Perception: An Essay on Classical Indian Theories of Knowledge
(Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1986), Chapter 6, esp. 6.6; Jonardon Ganeri, Semantic
Powers: Meaning and the Means of Knowing in Classical Indian Philosophy
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999), pp. 138–154.
26 Especially Thomas Nagel’s reflections on the possibility of what he calls a ‘general
concept of truth’ in The View from Nowhere (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1987), pp. 93–99. Also: David Lewis, ‘Elusive Knowledge,’ Australasian Journal
of Philosophy 74 (1996), pp. 549–567.
27 Nyayakusumañjali 3.7.
28 Khandanakhandakhadya I, 29 (vyaptilaksanatadgrahopayakhandana; pp. 395–
396). Translation: Stephen Phillips, Classical Indian Metaphysics (La Salle: Open
Court, 1995), pp. 154–156, and for the wider context Mrinalkanti Gangopadhyay,
Indian Logic in its Sources (Delhi: Munshiram, 1987), pp. 67–118.
29 Tattvacintamani, II, tarkaprakarana (1892, pp. 232–233); translation Stephen
Phillips, Classical Indian Metaphysics, pp. 162–4, and for the wider context
Mrinalkanti Gangopadhyay, ‘Gangesa on vyaptigraha: The Means for the
Notes 183
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
Ascertainment of Invariable Concomitance,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 3
(1975), pp. 167–208.
Tattvacintamani, II, vyaptilaksanatadgrahopayasiddhanta (1892, pp. 210–212).
Nelson Goodman, Fact, Fiction and Forecast (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965),
pp. 66–67.
The phrase is due to John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1972), pp. 20–1, 48–51.
Norman Daniels, ‘On Some Methods of Ethics and Linguistics,’ Philosophical
Studies 37 (1980), pp. 21–36.
Stephen Stich and R. Nisbett, ‘Justification and the Psychology of Human
Reasoning,’ Philosophy of Science 47 (1980), pp. 188–202; Stephen Stich,
‘Reflective Equilibrium, Analytic Epistemology and the Problem of Cognitive
Diversity,’ Synthese 74 (1988), pp. 391–413.
On the distinction: John Rawls, ‘The Independence of Moral Theory,’ Proceedings
and Addresses of the American Philosophical Society 48 (1974), pp. 4–22;
Norman Daniels, ‘Wide Reflective Equilibrium and Theory Acceptance in Ethics,’
Journal of Philosophy 76 (1979), pp. 256–282; Ernest Sosa, ‘Equilibrium in
Coherence?’ in his Knowledge in Perspective (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1991), Chapter 15.
The domain of principles meets an ‘independence constraint’ analogous to the
one Norman Daniels finds in the domain of particular judgments.
J. N. Mohanty, Reason and Tradition in Indian Thought (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1992). The quotation is at p. 271.
Roderick Chisholm, Theory of Knowledge (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall,
1966), pp. 56–69; see also his ‘The Problem of the Criterion,’ The 1973 Aquinas
Lecture (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1973).
Rohinton Mistry, A Fine Balance (London: Faber & Faber, 1995). Gangesa’s
epistemology is related in important ways to the bi-level virtue epistemology of
Ernest Sosa. Ernest Sosa, ‘Reflective Knowledge in the Best Circles,’ The Journal
of Philosophy 94 (1997), pp. 410–430. See also: Richard Foley, ‘Skepticism and
Rationality,’ in M. D. Roth and G. Ross (eds.), Doubting (Dordrecht: Kluwer
Academic Publishers, 1990), pp. 69–81.
Texts
For the newest editions and translations of the texts, consult Karl Potter’s
excellent and regularly updated online bibliography on the philosophical
literature of India – https://faculty.washington.edu/kpotter/
Anekantajayapataka, by 184184Haribhadra; ed. with Vrtti and
Municandra Suri’s Vivarana, H. R. Kapadia (Baroda: Gaewkwad
Oriental Series 88, 1940), 2 volumes.
AM
Aptamimamsa, by Samantabhadra; ed. Gajadharalal Jain (Benares:
Sanantana Jaina Granthamala, 1914).
AP
Alambanapariksa (Examination of Supports), by Dinnaga; ‘restored’
N. Aiyaswami Shastri, Alambanapariksa and vitti by Dinnaga with
the Commentary of Dharmapala, restored into Sanskrit from the
Tibetan and Chinese Versions and Edited with an English Translation
and Notes (Madras: The Adyar Library, 1942).
—— ed. with Vinitadeva’s and Dharmapala’s commentaries, N.
Aiyaswami Shastri, Bulletin of Tibetology (1980), pp. 1–170.
TRANSLATIONS Fernando Tola and Carmen Dragonetti, ‘Dignaga’s
Alambanapariksavrtti,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 10 (1982), pp.
105–134. See also Shastri, 1942, 1980.
AS
Arthasastra, by Kautilya; critical ed. R. P. Kangle, The Kautilya
Arthasastra (2nd edn., Bombay: Bombay University Press, 1972),
Part I.
TRANSLATION R. P. Kangle, The Kautilya Arthasastra (2nd edn.,
Bombay: Bombay University Press, 1972), Part II.
ATV
Atmatattvaviveka, by Udayana; ed. V. P. Dvivedin and L. S. Dravida
(Calcutta: Asiatic Society, 1986).
TRANSLATIONS Kisor Kumar Chakrabarti, Classical Indian
Philosophy of Mind: The Nyaya Dualist Tradition (Albany: State
University of New York Press, 1999), pp. 219–276.
—— N. S. Dravid, Atmatattvaviveka of Udayanacarya (Shimla:
Indian Institute of Advanced Study, 1995).
AYVD Anyayogavyavacchedadvatrimsika, by Hemacandra. See SM.
AJP
Texts 185
HC
JTB
KA
KhKh
LA
LT
MK
Hetucakradamaru (Chart of Reasons), by Dinnaga; ‘reconstructed’
from Tibetan by Durgacharan Chatterji, ‘Hetucakranirnaya – A
Translation,’ Indian Historical Quarterly 9 (1933), pp. 266–272,
511–514.
—— Richard S. Y. Chi, Buddhist Formal Logic: A Study of Dignaga’s
Hetucakra and K’uei-chi’s Great Commentary on the Nyayapravesa
(London: Royal Asiatic Society, 1969).
TRANSLATIONS D. Chatterji, R. S. Y. Chi.
Jaina Tarkabhasa, by Yasovijaya; ed. D. Bhargava (Delhi: Motilal
Banarsidass, 1973).
TRANSLATION D. Bhargava.
Kiranavali, by Udayana; ed. with Vardhamana’s Prakasa, Siva
Candra Sarvvabhouma (fasc. 1–3, 1911) and Narendra Chandra
Vedantatirtha (fasc. 4, 1956) (Calcutta: The Asiatic Society, Bibliotheca
Indica No. 200).
TRANSLATIONS B. K. Matilal (précis), in Karl Potter ed., Indian
Metaphysics and Epistemology – The Tradition of Nyaya-Vaisesika
up to Gangesa, Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Vol. 2 (Delhi:
Motilal Banarsidass, 1977), pp. 589–603.
—— Musashi Tachikawa [sections on earth, fire, water], The
Structure of the World in Udayana’s Realism: A Study of the
Laksanavali and the Kiranavali (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing
Company, 1981), pp. 109–147.
Khandanakhandakhadya, by Sriharsa; ed. Swami Yogindrananda
Nyayacarya (Varanasi: Udasina Sanskrit Press, 1979).
—— ed. with selections from the commentaries by Samkara Misra
and Raghunatha Siromani, S. N. Sukla (Varanasi: Chowkhamba
Oriental Series 82, 1904–1914).
TRANSLATIONS Ganganath Jha, The Khandanakhandakhadya of
Sri Harsa (Delhi: Sri Satguru, 1986), 2 volumes.
—— Phyllis Granoff [Book I, Introduction], Philosophy and Argument
in Late Vedanta: Sriharsa’s Khandanakhandakhadya (Dordrecht:
Reidel Publishing Company, 1978), pp. 71–208.
—— Mrinalkanti Gangopadhyay [Book I, Inference], Indian Logic
in its Sources (Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal, 1984), pp. 67–118.
Laksanavali, by Udayana; ed. Musashi Tachikawa, The Structure of
the World in Udayana’s Realism: A Study of the Laksanavali and the
Kiranavali (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1981).
TRANSLATION Musachi Tachikawa.
Laghiyastraya, by Akalanka; ed. with Akalanka’s Nyayaviniscaya
and Pramanasamgraha in Akalanka Granthatrayam, Mahendra
Kumar Sastri (Calcutta: Sanchalaka Singhi Jaina Granthamala, 1939).
Mulamadhyamakakarika (The Middle Stanzas), by Nagarjuna; ed.
with Candrakirti’s Prasannapada, Dwarikadas Shastri (Varanasi:
Bauddha Bharati, 1989, 2nd edn.).
186 Philosophy in classical India
NA
NB
NBh
NBhu
NK
NKA
TRANSLATIONS Jay L. Garfield, The Fundamental Wisdom of the
Middle Way (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995).
—— David Kalupahana, Nagarjuna: The Philosophy of the Middle
Way (Albany: SUNY Press 1986).
—— Kenneth Inada, Nagarjuna: A Translation of his
Mulamadhyamakakarika (Tokyo: Hokuseido Press, 1970).
—— Frederick Streng, Emptiness: A Study in Religious Meaning
(Nashville: Abingdon Press, 1967), pp. 183–220.
Nyayavatara, by Siddhasena Divakara; ed. A. N. Upadhye (Bombay:
Jaina Sahitya Vikasa Mandala, 1971).
TRANSLATIONS Piotr Balcerowicz, Epistemology in Historical and
Comparative Perspective. Critical Edition and English Translation
of
Logical-Epistemological
Treatises:
Nyayavatara,
Nyayavataravirti and Nyayavatara-vippana with Introduction and
Notes (Hamburg: Franz Steiner Verlag, 2000).
—— Satkari Mookerjee, ‘A Critical and Comparative Study of Jaina
Logic and Epistemology on the Basis of the Nyayavatara of
Siddhasena Divakara,’ Vaishali Institute Research Bulletin I (1971),
pp. 1–144.
Nyayabindu, by Dharmakirti; ed. with Dharmottara’s Tika and an
anonymous Tippani, Dwarikadas Sastri (Varanasi: Baudhha Bharati,
1985).
TRANSLATIONS Mrinalkanti Gangopadhyaya, Vinitadeva’s
Nyayabindutika (Calcutta: Indian Studies Past and Present, 1971).
—— Theodore Stcherbatsky, ‘A Short Treatise of Logic by
Dharmakirti with its Commentary by Dharmottara,’ in his Buddhist
Logic, Vol. 2 (New York: Dover Publications, 1962), pp. 1–253.
—— G. C. Pande, Nyayabindu (Sarnath, 1996).
Nyayabhasya, by Vatsyayana Paksilasvamin, see NS.
TRANSLATION See NS.
Nyayabhusana, by Bhasarvajña; ed. S. Yogindrananda (Varanasi:
Saddarsan Prakasan Pratisthanam, 1968).
TRANSLATION B. K. Matilal (précis), in Karl Potter ed., Indian
Metaphysics and Epistemology – The Tradition of Nyaya-Vaisesika
up to Gangesa, Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Vol. 2 (Delhi:
Motilal Banarsidass, 1977), pp. 410–424.
Nyayakandali, by Sridhara; ed. Durgadhara Jha (Varanasi:
Sampurnanand Sanskrit Vishvavidyalaya, Ganganatha Jha
Granthamala, Vol. 1, 1977).
TRANSLATION See PDS.
Nyayakusumañjali, by Udayana; ed. Padmaprasada Upadhyaya and
Dhundhiraja Sastri (Benares: Chowkhamba Sanskrit Series Office,
Kash Sanskrit Series 30, 1957).
TRANSLATION N. S. Dravid, Nyayakusumañjali of Udayanacarya
(Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1996).
Texts 187
Nyayakumudacandra, by Prabhacandra (a commentary on
Akankara’s Laghiyastraya); ed. Mahendra Kumar Nyayacharya
(Bombay: Manik Chandra Dgambara Jain Series, 1938; reprinted in
2 volumes, Sri Satguru, 1991).
NM
Jayanta. Nyayamañjari; ed. S. N. Shukla (Benares: Chowkhamba
Sanskrit Series 106, 1936).
TRANSLATION J. V. Bhattacharyya, Nyayamañjari: The
Compendium of Indian Speculative Logic (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass,
1978).
NS
Nyayasutra, by Gautama Aksapada; Gautamiyanyayadarsana with
Bhasya of Vatsyayana, critical ed. Anantalal Thakur (Delhi: Indian
Council of Philosophical Research, 1997).
TRANSLATION Gautama’s Nyayasutra with Vatsyayana’s
Commentary, translated by Mrinalkanti Gangopadhyaya, with an
introduction by Debiprasad Chattopadhyaya (Calcutta: Indian Studies
Past and Present, 1982).
NV
Nyayavarttika by Bharadvaja Uddyotakara; critical ed. Anantalal
Thakur (Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1997).
TRANSLATION Ganganatha Jha, The Nyayasutras of Gautama
with the Bhasya of Vatsyayana and the Varttika of Uddyotakara
(Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1984), Vols. 1–4.
NVTP Nyayavarttikatatparyaparisuddhi, by Udayana, critical ed.
Anantalal Thakur (Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research,
1996).
NVTT Nyayavarttikatatparyatika, by Vacaspati; critical ed. Anantalal
Thakur (Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1996).
TRANSLATIONS B. K. Matilal (précis), in Karl Potter ed., Indian
Metaphysics and Epistemology – The Tradition of Nyaya-Vaisesika
up to Gangesa, Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Vol. 2 (Delhi:
Motilal Banarsidass, 1977), pp. 455–483.
—— Theodore Stcherbatsky, sections translated in his Buddhist Logic,
Vol. 2 (New York: Dover Publications, 1962), pp. 287–298, 303–
308, 405–432.
P
Prasannapada, by Candrakirti; see MK.
TRANSLATION Mervyn Sprung, Lucid Exposition of the Middle
Way: The Essential Chapters from the Prasannapada of Candrakirti
(Boulder, Colorado: Prajña Press, 1979).
PDS
Padarthadarmasamgraha aka PrasastapadaBhasya, by Prasastapada;
ed. with Sankara Misra’s Upaskara, Dundhiraja Sastri (Varanasi:
Chaukhamba Sanskrit Series Office, Kashi Sanskrit Series 3, 1923).
TRANSLATION Ganganatha Jha, Padarthadharmasamgraha with
Sridhara’s Nyayakandali, The Pandit, n.s. Vols. 25–37 (1903–15).
PKM Prameyakamalamartanda, by Prabhacandra; ed. Mahendra Kumar
Shastri (Bombay: Nirnayasagar Press, 1941; reprinted Sri Satguru
1990).
NKC
188 Philosophy in classical India
Pramanamimamsa, by Hemacandra; ed. Sukhlalji Sanghvi (Calcutta:
Shri Bahadur Singh Singhi Jaina Series 9, 1939).
TRANSLATION Satkari Mookerjee and N. Tatia, Hemacandra’s
Pramanamimamsa, Text and Translation with Critical Notes
(Varanasi: Tara Publications, 1970).
PNTA Pramananayatattvalokalamkara, by Vadideva Suri, ed. Hari Satya
Bhattacharya (Bombay: Jaina Sahitya Vikas Mandala, 1967).
TRANSLATION H. S. Bhattacharya.
PS
Pramanasamuccaya (Collection on Knowing), by Dinnaga; for
editions of the Tibetan translations, see Richard Hayes, Dignaga on
the Interpretation of Signs (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers,
1988), p. 338.
—— partly ‘reconstructed’ into Sanskrit by Muni Sri Jambuvijaya in
Vaisesikasutra of Kanada, with the Commentary of Candrananda,
Appendix 7 (Baroda: Oriental Institute, Gaekwad’s Oriental Series
136, 1961).
—— H. N. Randle, Fragments from Dignaga (London, 1926).
—— Shoryu Katsura, ‘New Sanskrit Fragments of the
Pramanasamuccaya,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 3 (1975), pp. 67–
78.
TRANSLATIONS Chapter I. Masaaki Hattori, Dignaga, On
Perception, being the Pratyaksapariccheda of Dignaga’s
Pramanasamuccaya from the Sanskrit fragments and the Tibetan
versions (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1968), pp.
21–70.
—— Chapters II, V. Richard P. Hayes, Dignaga on the Interpretation
of Signs (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1988), pp. 231–
248, 252–299.
PTN
Padarthatattvanirupana, by Raghunatha; ed. Karl H. Potter, The
Padarthatattvanirupanam of Raghunatha Siromani (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, Harvard Yenching Institute Studies,
Vol. 17, 1957).
TRANSLATION K. H. Potter.
PV
Pramanavarttika (Commentary on Knowing), by Dharmakirti; ed.
with Manorathanandin’s Vrtti, Dwarikadas Shastri (Varanasi:
Baudhha Bharati, 1968).
—— ed. Raniero Gnoli, The Pramanavarttikam of Dharmakirti: The
First Chapter with the Autocommentary (Rome: Istituto Italiano per
I1 Medio ed Estremo Oriente, 1960).
TRANSLATIONS (ongoing)
—— Chapter I (svarthanumana, ‘inference for oneself’). [1–10]
Richard P. Hayes and Brendan S. Gillon, ‘Introduction to Dharmakirti’s
Theory of Inference as Presented in Pramanavarttika SvopajñaVrtti
1–10,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 19 (1991), pp. 1–74.
—— Chapter II (pramanasiddhi, ‘establishment of knowing’). [1–6]
PM
Texts 189
SM
ST
STP
TA
TC
Shoryu Katsura, ‘Dharmakirti’s Theory of Truth,’ Journal of Indian
Philosophy 12 (1984), pp. 215–235. [34–72] Eli Franco, Dharmakirti
on Compassion and Rebirth (Vienna: Arbeitskreis für Tibetische und
Buddhistische Studien Universität Wien, 1997).
—— Chapter III (pratyaksa, ‘perception’). [1–51] Satkari Mookerjee
and Hojun Nagasaki, The Pramanavarttika of Dharmakirti – An
English Translation of the First Chapter with the Autocommentary
(Nalanda: Nava-Nalanda Mahavira Research Publication, 1964).
—— Chapter IV (pararthanumana, ‘inference for others’). [ 1–148]
Tom J. F. Tillemans, Dharmakirtis Pramanavarttika – An Annotated
Translation of the Fourth Chapter (pararthanumana) Vol. 1 (Vienna:
Österreichische Akademie der Wissenschaften, 2000). [202–206]
Shoryu Katsura, ‘Pramanavarttika IV 202–206– Towards the Correct
Understanding of svabhavapratibandha,’ Journal of Indian and
Buddhist Studies 40 (1992), pp. 35–40.
Syadvadamañjari, by Mallisena; ed. with Hemacandra’s
Anyayogavyavacchedadvatrimsika, A. B. Dhruva (Bombay: Bombay
Sanskrit and Prakrit Series 83, 1933).
TRANSLATIONS S. K. Saksena and C. A. Moore, in S.
Radhakrishnan and C. A. Moore eds., A Sourcebook in Indian
Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1957), pp. 260–
268.
—— F. W. Thomas, The Flower-Spray of the Quodammodo Doctrine
(Berlin: Akademia Verlag, 1960).
Saptabhangitarangini, by Vimaladasa; ed. T. P. Sharma (Bombay:
Rayacandra Jaina Sastra Mala, 1905, 1916, 1977).
Sanmatitarkaprakarana, by Siddhasena Divakara; ed. with
Abhayadevasuri’s Tattvabodhavidhayani by S. Sanghvi and B. Doshi
(Ahmedabad: Gujarat Puratattva Mandira Granthavali, 1924–31).
Tattvarthasutra, by Umasvati; ed. J. L. Jain (Arah: Bibliotheca
Jainica, 1920).
TRANSLATION K. K. Dixit, Sukhlalji Sanghvi’s Commentary on
Tattvarthasutra of Vacaka Umasvati (Ahmedabad: L. D. Institute of
Indology, 1974).
Tattvacintamani, by Gangesa; ed. with Mathuranatha’s Rahasya and
Jayadeva Misra’s Aloka, Kamakhyanatha Tarkavagisa, 6 volumes
(Calcutta: Asiatic Society, 1884–1901).
TRANSLATIONS Thorough précis in Karl Potter and Sibajiban
Bhattacharyya eds., Indian Philosophical Analysis – NyayaVaisesika from Gangesa to Raghunatha Siromani Encyclopedia of
Indian Philosophies, Vol. 6 (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1993), pp.
85–311.
—— Chapter I (pratyaksa, ‘perception’). Stephen Phillips, Gangesa’s
‘Jewel of Reflection on Reality,’ the Perception Chapter (New York:
Oxford University Press, 2000). Also: (2 pramanyavada) J. N.
190 Philosophy in classical India
TS
TUS
U
V
Mohanty, Gangesa’s Theory of Truth (Santiniketan, 1966), pp. 73–
210. (8 abhavavada) Bimal K. Matilal, The Navya-Nyaya Doctrine
of Negation (Harvard: Harvard University Press, 1968), pp. 173–
188. (14 nirvikalpakavada) Sibajiban Bhattacharyya, Gangesa’s
Theory of Indeterminate Perception (Delhi: Indian Council of
Philosophical Research, 1993), Part Two.
—— Chapter II (anumana, ‘inference’). (1 anumitinirupana and 2–8
vyaptipañcaka to visesavyapti) Cornelius Goekoop, The Logic of
Invariable Concomitance in the Tattvacintamani (Dordrecht: Reidel
Publishing Co., 1967), pp. 55–154. (2 vyaptipañcaka) Daniel H. H.
Ingalls, Materials for the Study of Navya-Nyaya Logic (Harvard:
Harvard University Press, 1951), p. 86. (9 vyaptigrahopayaprakarana)
Mrinalkanti Gangopadhyay, ‘Gangesa on vyaptigraha: The Means
for the Ascertainment of Invariable Concomitance,’ Journal of Indian
Philosophy 3 (1975), pp. 167–208. (10 tarkaprakarana) Stephen
Phillips, Classical Indian Metaphysics (La Salle: Open Court, 1995),
pp. 158–164. (14 Paksata) A. K. Rai, ‘Paksata in Navya-Nyaya,’
Journal of Indian Philosophy 23 (1995), pp. 3–4. (21 isvaranumana)
John Vattanky, Gangesa’s Philosophy of God (Madras, 1984).
—— Chapter IV (sabda, ‘language’). (1 sabdapramanyavada) Pradyot
Kumar Mukhopadhyay, The Nyaya Theory of Linguistic
Performance: A New Interpretation of Tattvacintamani (Calcutta:
K.P. Bagchee & Co., 1992). (8 vidhivada) V. N. Jha, The Philosophy
of Injunctions (Delhi: Sri Satguru Publications, 1988). (11 apurvavada)
V. N. Jha, The Philosophy of the Intermediate Causal Link (Delhi:
Sri Satguru Publications, 1986).
Tarkasamgraha, Annambhatta; ed. with author’s Dipika, Satkari
Sarma Vangiya (Varanasi, 1969).
TRANSLATION Gopinath Bhattacharya, Tarkasamgrahadipika on
Tarkasamgraha by Annambhatta (Calcutta: Progressive Publishers,
1983; reprinted 1994).
Tattvopaplasimha, by Jayarasi; ed. Sukhlalji Sanghavi and Rasiklal
C. Parikh (Varanasi: Bauddha Bharati, 1987).
TRANSLATIONS Chapter 1 (Perception). Eli Franco, Perception,
Knowledge and Disbelief: A Study of Jayarasi’s Scepticism (2nd
Edition, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1994).
—— Chapter 2 (Inference). S. N. Shastri and S. N. Saksena, in Sarvepalli
Radhakrishnan and Charles Moore eds., A Sourcebook in Indian
Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1957), pp. 236–246.
Upaskara, by Sankara Misra; see PDS.
TRANSLATION See: VS.
Vigrahavyavartani (Reply to Critics), by Nagarjuna; critical ed. E.
H. Johnston and A. Kunst in The Dialectical Method of Nagarjuna:
Vigrahavyavartani (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1986).
TRANSLATION Kamaleswar Bhattacharya, in critical ed.
Texts 191
VN
VS
Vadanyaya, by Dharmakirti; ed. Pradeep P. Gokhale, Vadanyaya of
Dharmakirti: The Logic of Debate (Delhi: Sri Satguru Publications,
1993).
TRANSLATION P. P. Gokhale.
Vaisesikasutra, by Kanada; critical ed. with Candrananda’s Vrtti,
Muni Sri Jambuvijayaji (Baroda: Oriental Institute, Gaekwad’s
Oriental Series 136, 1961).
TRANSLATION Nandalal Sinha, The Vaisesikasutras of Kanada,
with the commentary of Sankara Misra (Allahabad: The Panini Office,
Bhuvaneswari Asrama, 1911).
Bibliography
Alsdorf, Luwig, ‘Niksepa – A Jaina Contribution to Scholastic Methodology,’
Journal of The Oriental Institute, Baroda 22 (1973), pp. 455–463.
Bagchi, Sitansusekhar, Inductive Reasoning: A Study of Tarka and its Role in Indian
Logic (Calcutta: Munishchandra Sinha, 1953).
Balcerowicz, Piotr, ‘How Could a Cow be Both Synchronically and Diachronically
Homogenous, or On the Jaina Notions of tiryak-samanya and urdhvatasamanya,’ in N. K. Wagle and Olle Qvarnström eds., Approaches to Jaina Studies:
Philosophy, Logic, Rituals and Symbols (Toronto: University of Toronto, 1999),
pp. 211–235.
Bandyopadhyay, Nandita, ‘The Concept of Contradiction in Indian Logic and
Epistemology,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 16.3 (1988), pp. 225–246.
Barnes, Jonathan ed., The Complete Works of Aristotle (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1985).
Basham, A. L., History, and Doctrines of the Ajivikas (London: Luzac & Co., 1951).
Bhaduri, S., Studies in Nyaya-Vaisesika Metaphysics (Poona: Bhandarkar Oriental
Research Institute, 1947).
Bharadwaja, Vijay, ‘Rationality, Argumentation and Philosophical Embarrassment:
A Study of Four Logical Alternatives (catuskoti) in Buddhist Logic,’ Philosophy
East and West 34 (1984), pp. 303–319; reprinted in his Form and Validity in
Indian Logic, Chapter 4.
—— Form and Validity in Indian Logic (Shimla: Indian Institute of Advanced Study, 1990).
Bhatt, Bansidhar, The Canonical Niksepa: Studies in Jaina Dialectics (Leiden: E. J.
Brill, 1978).
Bhattacharya, Gopikamohan, ‘Ratnakirti on Apoha,’ in B. K. Matilal and R. D. Evans
eds., Buddhist Logic and Epistemology: Studies in the Buddhist Analysis of
Inference and Language (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1982), pp.
291–298.
Bhattacharya, Kalidas, ‘An Idea of Comparative Indian Philosophy,’ All India
Oriental Conference (Santiniketan, 1980).
Bhattacharya, Kamaleswar, ‘On the Relationship Between Nagarjuna’s
Vigrahavyavartani and the Nyayasutras,’ Journal of Indo-European Studies
(USA) 5 (1977), pp. 265–273.
—— ‘Nagarjuna’s Arguments against Motion: Their Grammatical Basis,’ in G.
Bhattacharya et al. eds., A Corpus of Indian Studies: Essays in Honour of
Professor Gaurinath Sastri (Calcutta: Sanskrit Pustak Bhandar, 1980), pp. 85–
95.
—— ‘The Grammatical Basis of Nagarjuna’s Arguments: Some Further
Considerations,’ Indologica Taurinensia 8–9 (1980–1), pp. 35–43.
Bibliography 193
—— ‘Nagarjuna’s Arguments Against Motion,’ Journal of the International
Association of Buddhist Studies 8 (1985), pp. 7–16.
—— ‘Back to Nagarjuna and Grammar,’ The Adyar Library Bulletin 59 (1995), pp.
178–189.
Bhattacharyya, Sibajiban, ‘The Navya-Nyaya Theory of Universals,’ in his
Gadadhara’s Theory of Objectivity, Part 1: General Introduction to NavyaNyaya Concepts (New Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1990),
Chapter 3.
Bronkhorst, J., ‘Nagarjuna and The Naiyayikas,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 13
(1985), pp. 107–132.
Burton, David, Emptiness Appraised: A Critical Study of Nagarjuna’s Philosophy
(London: Curzon Press, 1999).
Cardona, George, ‘Anvaya and Vyatireka in Indian Grammar,’ Adyar Library
Bulletin 31 (1967–8), pp. 313–352.
—— ‘On Reasoning from Anvaya and Vyatireka in Early Advaita,’ in his Studies in
Indian Philosophy (Ahmedabad: L.D. Series, 1981), pp. 79–104.
—— ‘A Path Still Taken: Some Early Indian Arguments Concerning Time,’ Journal of
the American Oriental Society 111.3 (1991), pp. 445–464.
Chakrabarti, Arindam, ‘I Touch What I Saw,’ Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research 52 (1992), pp. 103–117.
—— ‘Rationality in Indian Philosophy,’ in Eliot Deutsch and Ron Bontekoe eds., A
Companion to World Philosophies (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1997), pp.
259–278.
—— Denying Existence (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1997).
Chakrabarti, Kishor, Indian Philosophy of Mind: The Nyaya Dualist Tradition
(Albany: State University of New York Press, 1999).
Chakrabarti, Kishor and Chandana Chakrabarti, ‘Towards Dualism: The NyayaVaisesika Way,’ Philosophy East and West 41 (1991), pp. 477–491.
Chierchia, Gennaro and Sally McConnell-Ginet, Meaning and Grammar
(Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1990).
Chisholm, Roderick, Theory of Knowledge (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall,
1966).
—— ‘The Problem of the Criterion,’ The 1973 Aquinas Lecture (Milwaukee:
Marquette University Press, 1973).
Cohen, Morris R. and Ernest Nagel, An Introduction to Logic and Scientific Method
(London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1934).
Coward, Harold, Derrida and Indian Philosophy (Albany: State University of New
York Press, 1990).
Daniels, Norman, ‘Wide Reflective Equilibrium and Theory Acceptance in Ethics,’
Journal of Philosophy 76 (1979), pp. 256–282.
—— ‘Reflective Equilibrium and Archimedean Points,’ Canadian Journal of
Philosophy 10 (1980), pp. 83–103.
—— ‘On Some Methods of Ethics and Linguistics,’ Philosophical Studies 37 (1980),
pp. 21–36.
Davidson, Donald, ‘Paradoxes of Irrationality,’ in R. Wollheim and J. Hopkins eds.,
Philosophical Essays on Freud (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1982),
pp. 289–305.
Dravid, N. S., ‘Aharya Cognition in Navya-Nyaya,’ Journal of the Indian Council of
Philosophical Research 14.2 (1996), pp. 164–168.
Dretske, Fred, Knowledge and the Flow of Information (Oxford: Basil Blackwell,
1981).
Dreyfus, Georges B. J., Recognizing Reality: Dharmakirti’s Philosophy and its
Tibetan Interpretations (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997).
194 Philosophy in classical India
Dummett, Michael, Frege: Philosophy of Mathematics (London, Duckworth, 1991).
Dundas, Paul, The Jains (London: Routledge, 1992).
Edgerton, Franklin, ‘The Meaning of Samkhya and yoga,’ American Journal of
Philology 45 (1924), pp. 1–47.
Franco, Eli, ‘Bhasarvajña and Jayarasi: The Refutation of Scepticism in the
Nyayabhusana,’ Berliner Indologische Studien 3 (1987), pp. 23–49; reprinted as
an Appendix in his Perception, Knowledge and Disbelief
—— Perception, Knowledge and Disbelief: A Study of Jayarasi’s Scepticism, 2nd
edition (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1994).
Frauwallner, E., ‘Die Erkenntnislehre des Klassischen Samkhya-Systems,’ Wiener
Zeitschrift für die Kunde Süd- und Ost-Asiens 2 (1958), pp. 84–139.
—— ‘Dignaga, sein Werk und seine Entwicklung,’ Wiener Zeitschrift für die Kunde
Südund Ostasiens 3 (1959), pp. 83–164.
Frege, Gottlob, The Foundations of Arithmetic, translated by J. L. Austin (Oxford:
Basil Blackwell, 1950).
Fricker, Elizabeth, ‘Against Gullibility’ in B. K. Matilal and A. Chakrabarti eds.,
Knowing from Words (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1994), pp. 125–161.
Fynes, Richard, Hemacandra: The Lives of the Jaina Elders (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1998).
Galloway, Brian, ‘Notes on Nagarjuna and Zeno on Motion,’ The Journal of the
International Association of Buddhist Studies 10 (1987), pp. 80–87.
—— ‘Some Logical Issues in Madhyamaka Thought,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy
17 (1989), pp. 1–35.
Ganeri, Jonardon, ‘Numbers as Properties of Objects: Frege and the Nyaya,’ Studies
in Humanities and Social Sciences (3) – Epistemology, Logic and Ontology After
Matilal (Shimla: Indian Institute of Advanced Studies, 1996), pp. 111–121.
—— Semantic Powers: Meaning and the Means of Knowing in Classical Indian
Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999).
—— ‘Dharmakirti’s Semantics for the Particle eva (only)’ in Shoryu Katsura ed.,
Dharmakirti’s Thought and Its Impact on Indian and Tibetan Philosophy
(Vienna: Österreichische Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1999), pp. 101–116.
—— ‘Objectivity and Proof in an Indian Theory of Number,’ in Synthese
(forthcoming).
—— ‘Cross-modality and the Self,’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61
(2000).
—— ‘Indian Logic and the Colonization of Reason,’ in Jonardon Ganeri ed., Indian
Logic: A Reader (London: Curzon Press, 2001).
Gangopadhyay, Mrinalkanti, ‘Gangesa on Vyaptigraha: The Means for the
Ascertainment of Invariable Concomitance,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 3
(1975), pp. 167–208.
—— Indian Logic in its Sources (Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal, 1984).
Gärdenfors, Peter, ‘Induction, Conceptual Spaces, and AI,’ in Douglas Stalker ed.,
Grue! The New Riddle of Induction (Chicago: Open Court, 1994), pp. 117–134.
Gillon Brendan S. and Richard Hayes, ‘The Role of the Particle eva in (Logical)
Quantification in Sanskrit,’ Wiener Zeitschrift für die Kunde Süd- und OstAsiens 26 (1982), pp. 195–203.
Gillon Brendan, ‘Another Look at the Sanskrit Particle eva,’ in Shoryu Katsura ed.,
Dharmakirti’s Thought and Its Impact on Indian and Tibetan Philosophy
(Vienna: Österreichische Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1999), pp. 117–130.
Gokhale, Pradeep P., ‘The Logical Structure of Syadvada,’ Journal of Indian Council
of Philosophical Research 8 (1991), pp. 73–81.
—— Inference and Fallacies Discussed in Ancient Indian Logic (Delhi: Sri Satguru
Publications, 1992).
Bibliography 195
Goodman, Nelson, Fact, Fiction and Forecast (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965).
Goody, Jack, ‘East and West: Rationality in Review,’ Ethnos (1992), pp. 6–36.
Granoff, Phyllis, Philosophy and Argument in Late Vedanta: Sriharsa’s
Khandanakhandakhadya (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1978).
Gutting, Gary, Michel Foucault’s Archaeology of Scientific Reason (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1989).
Hacker, Paul, ‘Anviksiki,’ Wiener Zeitschrift für die Kunde Süd-und Ostasiens 2
(1958), pp. 54–83.
Hacking, Ian, ‘Working in a New World: The Taxonomic Solution,’ in Paul
Horwich ed., World Changes: Thomas Kuhn and the Nature of Science
(Cambridge, Mass., MIT Press, 1993), pp. 275–310.
Halbfass, Wilhelm, ‘Darsana, Anviksiki, Philosophy,’ in his India and Europe: an
Essay in Understanding (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1988),
pp. 263–286.
—— On Being and What There Is: Classical Vaisesika and the History of Indian
Ontology (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992).
Haslanger, Sally, Change, Persistence and Possibility (Ph.D. dissertation,
University of California, 1985).
Hattori Masaaki, Dignaga, On Perception, being the Pratyaksapariccheda of
Dignaga’s Pramanasamuccaya from the Sanskrit fragments and the Tibetan
Versions (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1968).
—— ‘The Sautrantika Background of the apoha Theory,’ in Leslie S. Kawamura
and Keith Scott eds., Buddhist Thought and Civilization: Essays in Honour of
Herbert V. Guenther on his Sixtieth Birthday (Emeryville: Dharma Press,
1977), pp. 47–58.
—— ‘Apoha and Pratibha,’ in M. Nagatomi et al. eds. Sanskrit and Indian
Studies: Essays in Honour of Daniel H. H. Ingalls (Dordrecht: Reidel
Publishing Company, 1980), pp. 61–74.
Hayes, Richard P., ‘On the Reinterpretation of Dharmakirti’s svabhavahetu,’
Journal of Indian Philosophy 15 (1987), pp. 319–332.
—— Dignaga on the Interpretation of Signs (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic
Publishers, 1988).
—— ‘Nagarjuna’s Appeal,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 22 (1994), pp. 309–410.
Herzberger, Hans H., ‘Three Systems of Buddhist Logic,’ in B. K. Matilal and R. D.
Evans eds., Buddhist Logic and Epistemology: Studies in the Buddhist
Analysis of Inference and Language (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company,
1982), pp. 59–76.
Herzberger, Radhika, Bhartrhari and the Buddhists (Dordrecht: Reidel
Publishing Company, 1986).
Hiriyanna, M., Outlines of Indian Philosophy (London: G. Allen & Unwin,
1932).
Hoffman, Frank J., ‘Rationality in Early Buddhist Four-Fold Logic,’ Journal of
Indian Philosophy 10 (1982), pp. 309–337.
—— Rationality and Mind in Early Buddhism (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1992;
first published 1987).
Hume, David, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (London: Routledge,
1991).
Huntington, C. W., The Emptiness of Emptiness: An Introduction to Early
Indian Madhyamaka (Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 1989).
Ingalls, Daniel H. H., Materials for the Study of Navya-Nyaya Logic (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1951).
Jacobi, Hermann J., ‘A Contribution Towards the Early History of Indian
Philosophy,’ translated by V. A. Sukthankar, The Indian Antiquary XLVII
(1918), pp. 101–109.
196 Philosophy in classical India
Jaskowski, Stanislaw, ‘Propositional Calculus for Contradictory Deductive
Systems,’ Studia Logica 24 (1969), pp. 143–157.
Jayatilleke, K. N., Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge (London: George Allen
and Unwin, 1963).
Jhalakikar, Bhimacarya, Nyayakosa, or Dictionary of Technical Terms of Indian
Philosophy (Poona: Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute, 1928).
Jinpa, Thupten, ‘Delineating Reason’s Scope for Negation,’ Journal of Indian
Philosophy 26 (1998), pp. 275–308.
Johnston, Mark, ‘Is There a Problem About Persistence?’ Aristotelian Society
Supplementary Volume 61 (1987), pp. 107–135.
Kajiyama Yuichi, An Introduction to Buddhist Philosophy: An Annotated
Translation of the Tarkabhasa or Moksakaragupta, Memoirs of the Faculty of
Letters (Kyoto) 10 (1966).
Kaplan, David, ‘Demonstratives: An Essay on the Semantics, Logic, Metaphysics and
Epistemology of Demonstratives and Other Indexicals,’ in J. Almog, J. Perry, and
H. Wettstein eds., Themes from Kaplan (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989).
Katsura Shoryu, ‘The apoha Theory of Dignaga,’ Indogaku Bukkyogaku Kenkyu 28
(1979), pp. (16)–(20).
—— ‘Dignaga on trairupya,’ Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies 32 (1983), pp.
(15)–(21).
—— ‘Dharmakirti’s Concept of Truth,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 12 (1984), pp.
213–235.
—— ‘On trairupya Formulae,’ in Buddhism and Its Relation to Other Religions:
Essays in Honour of Dr. Shozen Kumoi on His Seventieth Birthday (1986), pp.
161–172.
—— ‘Dignaga and Dharmakirti on apoha,’ in E. Steinkellner ed., Studies in the
Buddhist Epistemological Tradition (Vienna: Österreichische Akademie der
Wissenschaften, 1991), pp. 129–146.
—— ‘On Perceptual Judgement,’ in N. K. Wagle and F. Watanabe eds., Studies in
Buddhism in Honour of Professor A. K. Warder (Toronto: University of Toronto
Centre for South Asian Studies, 1993), pp. 66–75.
Kellner, Birgit, ‘Levels of (Im)Perceptibility: Dharmottara’s Views on The Drsya and
Drsanupalabdhi,’ in Shoryu Katsura ed., Dharmakirti’s Thought and Its Impact
on Indian and Tibetan Philosophy (Vienna: Österreichische Akademie der
Wissenschaften, 1999), pp. 193–208.
Khalida, Muhamad Ali, ‘Natural Kinds and Crosscutting Categories,’ Journal of
Philosophy 95 (1998), pp. 33–50.
King, Richard, Indian Philosophy: An Introduction to Hindu and Buddhist
Thought (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1999).
Kumar, R. A., Dak, T. M. and Mishra A. D. eds., Anekantavada and Syadvada
(Landun: Jain Visva Bharati, 1996).
Larson, Gerald James and Ram Shankar Bhattacharya eds., ‘Samkhya: A Dualist
Tradition in Indian Philosophy,’ Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Vol. IV
(Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1987).
Lath, Mukund, ‘The Concept of Aharya-jñana: Some Queries,’ Journal of the Indian
Council of Philosophical Research 13.1 (1995), pp. 175–181.
Lear, Jonathan, ‘A Note on Zeno’s Arrow,’ Phronesis 26 (1981), pp. 91–104.
Lewis, David, ‘Veridical Hallucination and Prosthetic Vision,’ in Philosophical Papers
II (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986), pp. 273–290.
—— The Plurality of Worlds (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986).
—— ‘Rearrangement of Particles: Reply to Lowe,’ Analysis 48 (1988), pp. 65–72.
Loy, David, ‘The Clôture of Deconstruction: A Mahayana Critique of Derrida,’
International Philosophical Quarterly 27 (1987), pp. 59–80.
Bibliography 197
Lowe, E. J., ‘Lewis on Persistence versus Endurance,’ Analysis 47 (1987), pp. 152–154.
Liberman, Kenneth, ‘The Grammatology of Emptiness,’ International Philosophical
Quarterly 31.4 (1991), pp. 435–448.
McEvilley, Thomas, ‘Pyrrhonism and Madhyamika,’ Philosophy East and West 32
(1982), pp. 3–35.
Mates, Benson, The Skeptic Way: Sextus Empiricus’s Outlines of Pyrrhonism (New
York: Oxford University Press, 1996).
Matilal, Bimal Krishna, The Navya-Nyaya Doctrine of Negation (Harvard: Harvard
University Press, 1968).
—— ‘Gangesa on the Concept of Universal Property (Kevalanvayin),’ Philosophy
East and West 18 (1968), pp. 151–161. Reprinted in Logic, Language and
Reality, pp. 128–139.
—— Epistemology, Logic and Grammar in Indian Philosophical Analysis (The
Hague: Mouton, 1971).
—— The Logical Illumination of Indian Mysticism (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1977).
—— ‘Double Negation in Navya-Nyaya,’ in M. Nagatomi et al. eds., Sanskrit and
Indian Studies: Essays in Honour of Daniel H. H. Ingalls (Dordrecht: Kluwer,
1980), pp. 1–10. Reprinted in Logic, Language and Reality, pp. 145–154.
—— ‘A Note on the Difference of Difference,’ in G. Bhattacharya et al. eds., A Corpus
of Indian Studies: Essays in Honour of Gaurinath Sastri (Calcutta, Sanskrit
Pustak Bhandar, 1980), pp. 69–78. Reprinted in Logic, Language and Reality,
pp. 155–163.
—— The Central Philosophy of Jainism (Ahmedabad: L. D. Institute of Indology,
1981).
—— Logic, Language and Reality: An Introduction to Indian Philosophical Studies
(Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1985).
—— Perception: An Essay on Classical Indian Theories of Knowledge (Clarendon
Press, Oxford, 1986).
—— The Word and the World (Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1990).
—— ‘Anekanta: both yes and no?’ Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical
Research 8 (1991), pp. 1–12. Reprinted as ‘The Jaina Contribution to Logic,’ in
The Character of Logic in India, pp. 127–139.
—— ‘Dharmakirti and the Universally Negative Inference,’ in E. Steinkellner ed.,
Studies in the Buddhist Epistemological Tradition (Vienna: Österreichische
Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1991), pp. 161–168. Reprinted in The Character
of Logic in India, pp. 118–126.
—— ‘Is Prasanga a Form of Deconstruction?’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 20
(1992), pp. 345–362.
—— ‘A Realist View of Perception,’ in P. K. Sen and R. R. Verma eds., The Philosophy
of P.F. Strawson (New Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1995),
pp. 305–326. Reprinted in his Philosophy, Religion, Culture: Collected Essays
(Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2001).
—— The Character of Logic in India, Jonardon Ganeri and Heeraman Tiwari eds.,
(Albany: State University of New York Press, 1998).
—— ‘On the Concept of Philosophy in India,’ in Philosophy, Religion, Culture:
Collected Essays (Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2001).
—— Philosophy, Religion and Culture: Collected Essays, Jonardon Ganeri ed.,
(Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2001); Vol. 1: Mind, Language and World, Vol.
2: Ethics and Epics.
Matilal, Bimal Krishna and R. D. G. Evans eds., Buddhist Logic and Epistemology:
Studies in the Buddhist Analysis of Inference and Language (Dordrecht: Reidel
Publishing Company, 1982).
198 Philosophy in classical India
Matilal, Bimal Krishna and Arindam Chakrabarti eds., Knowing from Words
(Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1994).
Meltzoff, Andrew, ‘Molyneux’s Babies: Cross-Modal Perception, Imitation, and the Mind of
the Preverbal Infant,’ in N. Eilan, R. McCarthy and M. W. Brewer eds., Spatial
Representation: Problems in Philosophy and Psychology (Oxford: Basil Blackwell,
1993).
Miyasaka Yuko, The Concept of Avacchedakatva in Navya-Nyaya (containing the
text of Raghunatha Siromani’s Avacchedakatvanirukti and its Commentary
Jagadisi with an English Translation, Explanatory Notes and a Detailed
Introduction) (Poona: Centre of Advanced Study in Sanskrit, PhD. Thesis,
1980).
Mohanty, J. N., Gangesa’s Theory of Truth (Santiniketan, 1966).
—— Reason and Tradition in Indian Thought (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992).
—— Essays on Indian Philosophy, edited by Purushottama Bilimoria (Delhi: Oxford
University Press, 1993).
Mondal, Pradyot, ‘Some Aspects of Perception in Old Nyaya,’ Journal of Indian
Philosophy 10 (1982), pp. 357–376.
Müller, Max, The Six Systems of Indian Philosophy (Oxford, 1899).
Nagel, Thomas, The View From Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press,
1986).
Nenninger, Claudius, ‘Analogical Reasoning in Early Nyaya-Vaisesika’ Asiatische
Studien 48 (1994), pp. 819–832.
Nozawa, M., ‘Inferential Marks in the Vaisesikasutras,’ Sambhasa: Nagoya Studies in
Indian Culture and Buddhism 12 (1991), pp. 25–38.
Nozick, Robert, The Nature of Rationality (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1993), pp. 163–174.
Oberhammer, Gerhard R. F., ‘Paksilasvamin’s Introduction to his Nyayabhasyam,’
Asian Studies (Philippines) 2 (1964), pp. 302–322.
Oetke, Claus, ‘Ich’ und das Ich (Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag Wiesbaden Gmbh,
1988).
—— Studies on the Doctrine of Trairupya (Vienna: Wiener Studien für Tibetologie
und Buddhismuskunde, 1993).
—— ‘Ancient Indian Logic as a Theory of Non-Monotonic Reasoning,’ Journal of
Indian Philosophy 24 (1996), pp. 447–539.
Oliver, Curtis, ‘Perception in Early Nyaya,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 6 (1978),
pp. 243–266.
Ono Motoi, ‘Dharmakirti on asasarananaikantika,’ in Shoryu Katsura ed.,
Dharmakirti’s Thought and its Impact on Indian and Tibetan Philosophy
(Vienna: Österreichische Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1999), pp. 301–316.
Padmarajiah, Y. J., Jaina Theories of Reality and Knowledge (Bombay: Jain Sahitya
Vikas Mandal, 1963).
Pandeya, R. C., ‘The Conception of Syadvada,’ in R. A. Kumar, T. M. Dak and A. D.
Mishra eds., Anekantavada and Syadvada (Landun: Jain Visva Bharati, 1996),
pp. 314–322.
Parasher, Aloka, Mlecchas in Early India: A Study in Attitudes Towards Outsiders up
to AD 600 (New Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal, 1991).
Perrett, Roy W. ‘A Note on the Navya-Nyaya Account of Number,’ Journal of Indian
Philosophy 13 (1985), pp. 227–234.
—— ‘Is Whatever Exists Knowable and Nameable?’ Philosophy East and West 49.4
(1999), pp. 410–414.
Phillips, Stephen H., Classical Indian Metaphysics: Refutations of Realism and the
Emergence of ‘New Logic’ (La Salle: Open Court, 1995).
Potter, Karl, ‘Astitva Jñeyatva Abhidheyatva,’ Wiener Zeitschrift für die Kunde Süd-
Bibliography 199
und Ost-Asiens und Archiv für Indische Philosophic 12–13 (1968), pp. 275–
280.
Potter, Karl ed., Indian Metaphysics and Epistemology – The Tradition of NyayaVaisesika up to Gangesa, Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Vol. 2 (Delhi:
Motilal Banarsidass, 1977).
Potter, Karl and Sibajiban Bhattacharyya eds., Indian Philosophical Analysis –
Nyaya-Vaisesika from Gangesa to Raghunatha Siromani, Encyclopedia of Indian
Philosophies, Vol. 6 (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1993).
Potter, Karl, with Robert Buswell, Padmanabh Jaini and Noble Ross Keat eds.,
Abhidharma Buddhism to 150 AD, Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Vol. 7
(Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1996).
Preisendanz, Karin, Studien zu Nyayasutra III.1 Mit dem Nyayatattvaloka Vacaspati
Misras II, Tiel 1 und 2 (Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, 1994).
Price, Huw, ‘Metaphysical Pluralism,’ Journal of Philosophy 89 (1992), pp. 387–410.
Priest, Graham, ‘Can Contradictions Be True?’ Supplementary Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society 67 (1993), pp. 35–54.
—— ‘The Structure of the Paradoxes of Self-Reference,’ Mind 103 (1994), pp. 25–34.
—— Beyond the Limits of Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995).
Priest, Graham, Richard Routley and Jean Norman eds., Paraconsistent Logic:
Essays on the Inconsistent (Munchen: Philosophia Verlag, 1989).
Radhakrishnan, Sarvepalli, Indian Philosophy (London: George Allen and Unwin,
1923).
Radhakrishnan, Sarvepalli and Charles Moore eds., A Sourcebook in Indian
Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1967).
Raja, K. K., ‘Apoha and Pre-Dinnaga Views on Sentence Meaning,’ in B. K. Matilal
and R. D. Evans eds., Buddhist Logic and Epistemology: Studies in the Buddhist
Analysis of Inference and Language (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company,
1982), pp. 185–192.
Ramakrishnan, Lakshmi, ‘On Talk of Modes of Thought,’ Journal of the Indian
Council of Philosophical Research 13.2 (1996), pp. 1–17.
Ramanujan, A. K., ‘Is There an Indian Way of Thinking?’ Contributions to Indian
Sociology 23 (1989), pp. 41–58.
Ram-Prasad, C., ‘Immediacy and the Direct Theory of Perception: Problems from
Sriharsa,’ Studies in Humanities and Social Sciences 3.2 (1996) – Epistemology,
Logic and Ontology After Matilal (Shimla: Indian Institute of Advanced Studies),
pp. 33–56.
—— Knowledge and the Highest Good: Liberation and Philosophical Inquiry in
Classical Indian Thought (Basingstoke: Macmillan, 2000).
Randle, H. N., Indian Logic in the Early Schools (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1930).
Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972).
—— ‘The Independence of Moral Theory,’ Proceedings and Addresses of the
American Philosophical Society 48 (1974), pp. 4–22.
Rescher, Nicholas, Many-Valued Logic (New York: McGraw Hill, 1963).
—— ‘The Roots of Objectivity,’ in Scientific Realism (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing
Company, 1987), pp. 111–125.
Robinson, Richard H., ‘Some Logical Aspects of Nagarjuna’s System,’ Philosophy
East and West 6 (1957), pp. 291–308.
—— Early Madhyamika in India and China (Madison, Milwaukee and London:
University of Winsconsin Press, 1967).
—— ‘Did Nagarjuna Really Refute All Philosophical Views?’ Philosophy East and
West 22 (1972), pp. 325–331.
Ruegg, David Seyfort, ‘The Uses of the Four Positions of the Catuskoti and the
200 Philosophy in classical India
Problem of the Description of Reality in Mahayana Buddhism,’ Journal of Indian
Philosophy 5 (1977), pp. 1–71.
—— The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India (Wiesbaden:
Otto Harrassowitz, 1981).
—— ‘Does the Madhyamika Have a Thesis and Philosophical Position?’ in B. K.
Matilal and R. D. G. Evans eds., Buddhist Logic and Epistemology. Studies in the
Buddhist Analysis of Inference and Language (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing
Company, 1982), pp. 229–238.
Russell, Bertrand, Human Society in Ethics and Politics (London: Allen and Unwin,
1954).
Ryle, Gilbert, The Concept of Mind (London: Hutchinson & Co., 1949).
Sagal, Paul, ‘Nagarjuna’s Paradox,’ American Philosophical Quarterly 29.1 (1992),
pp. 79–85.
Sainsbury, Mark, Paradoxes, 2nd edn (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press,
1995).
Sanghvi, Sukhlalji, Advanced Studies in Indian Logic and Metaphysics (Calcutta:
Indian Studies Past and Present, 1961).
Sartre, J-P., Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology,
translated by H. E. Barnes (London: Methuen & Co., 1966).
Schayer, Stanislaw, ‘Studies on Indian Logic, Part II: Ancient Indian Anticipations of
Propositional Logic’ (1933), translated by Joerg Tuske in Jonardon Ganeri ed.,
Indian Logic: A Reader (London: Curzon Press, 2001).
—— ‘Über die Methode der Nyaya-Forschung,’ in O. Stein and W. Gambert eds.,
Festschrift für Moritz Winternitz (Leipzig, 1933, pp. 247–257), translated by
Joerg Tuske in Jonardon Ganeri ed., Indian Logic: A Reader (London: Curzon
Press, 2001).
Schiffer, Stephen, ‘Descriptions, Indexicals and Belief Reports: Some Dilemmas,’ Mind
104 (1995), pp. 107–131.
Schuster, Nancy, ‘Inference in the Vaisesikasutras,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 1
(1972), pp. 341–395.
Sen, Prabal Kumar, ‘The Nyaya-Vaisesika Theory of Variegated Colour (citrarupa):
Some Vexed Problems,’ Studies in Humanities and Social Sciences 3.2 (1996) –
Epistemology, Logic and Ontology After Matilal (Shimla: Indian Institute of
Advanced Studies), pp. 151–172.
Shah, Nagin J., Akalanka’s Criticism of Dharmakirti’s Philosophy (Ahmedabad: L.
D. Institute, 1967).
Shaw, J. L., ‘The Nyaya on Existence, Knowability and Nameability,’ Journal of
Indian Philosophy 5 (1978), pp. 255–266.
—— ‘Number: From the Nyaya to Frege-Russell,’ Studia Logica 41 (1982), pp. 283–
291.
Siderits, Mark, ‘Nagarjuna as Anti-Realist,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 16 (1988),
pp. 311–326.
—— ‘Thinking on Empty: Madhyamaka Anti-Realism and Canons of Rationality,’ in
S. Biderman and B-A. Scharfstein eds., Rationality in Question (Leiden: E. J. Brill,
1989), pp. 231–250.
—— Indian Philosophy of Language (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers,
1991).
—— ‘Matilal on Nagarjuna,’ in P. Bilimoria and J. N. Mohanty eds., Relativism,
Suffering and Beyond: Essays in Memory of B. K. Matilal (Delhi: Oxford
University Press, 1997), pp. 69–92.
Siderits, Mark and J. Dervin O’Brien, ‘Zeno and Nagarjuna on Motion,’ Philosophy
East and West 26 (1976), pp. 281–299.
Simon, Herbert and Allen Newell, Human Problem Solving (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.:
Prentice-Hall, 1972).
Bibliography 201
Solomon, Esther, ‘Scepticism or Faith and Mysticism – A Comparative Study of the
Tattvopaplasimha and the Khandanakhandakhadya,’ Journal of the Oriental
Institute (Baroda) 8 (1959), pp. 219–233, 349–368.
—— Indian Dialectics, 2 volumes (Ahmedabad: B. J. Institute of Learning and
Research, 1976).
Solomon, Robert, ‘Existentialism, Emotions, and the Cultural Limits of
Rationality,’ Philosophy East and West 42 (1992), pp. 597–621.
Soni, Jayandra, ‘Dravya, Guna and Paryaya in Jaina Thought,’ Journal of
Indian Philosophy 19.1 (1991), pp. 75–88.
Sorabji, Richard, Animal Minds and Human Morals (London: Duckworth,
1993).
Sosa, Ernest, Knowledge in Perspective (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1991).
Sousa, Ronald de, ‘The Natural Shiftiness of Natural Kinds,’ Canadian Journal
of Philosophy 14 (1984), pp. 561–580.
Spelke, E. S. and G. A. Van De Walle, ‘Perceiving and Reasoning about Objects:
Insights from Infants,’ in Naomi Eilan, Rosaleen McCarthy and Bill Brewer
eds., Spatial Representation (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993).
Stcherbatsky, Theodore, The Central Conception of Buddhism and the
Meaning of the Word ‘Dharma’ (London: Royal Asiatic Society, 1922).
Steinkellner, Eric Von, ‘On the Interpretation of the svabhavahetuh,’ Wiener
Zeitschrift für die Kunde Süd- und Ost-Asiens 18 (1973), pp. 117–129.
Stich, Stephen, ‘Reflective Equilibrium, Analytic Epistemology and the Problem
of Cognitive Diversity,’ Synthese 74 (1988), pp. 391–413.
Stich, Stephen and R. Nisbett, ‘Justification and the Psychology of Human
Reasoning,’ Philosophy of Science 47 (1980), pp. 188–202.
Stout, G. F., ‘The Nature of Universals and Propositions,’ Proceedings of the
British Academy 10 (1921), pp. 157–172.
Strawson, P. F., ‘On Referring,’ Mind 59 (1950), pp. 320–344.
—— Introduction to Logical Theory (London: Methuen, 1952).
Tachikawa Musashi, The Structure of the World in Udayana’s Realism: A Study
of the Laksanavali and the Kiranavali (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing
Company, 1981).
Taylor, Charles, ‘Rationality,’ in his Philosophy and the Human Sciences:
Philosophical Papers 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), pp.
134–151.
Thomason, Richard, ‘Species, Determinates, and Natural Kinds,’ Noûs 3
(1969), pp. 95–101.
Tillemans, Tom F., ‘On sapaksa,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 18 (1990), pp.
53–80.
Tucci, G., Pre-Dinnaga Buddhist Texts on Logic from Chinese Sources (Baroda:
Oriental Institute, Gaekwad’s Oriental Series 49, 1929).
Tuske, Joerg, ‘Being in Two Minds: The Divided Mind in the Nyayasutra,’ Asian
Philosophy 9.3 (1999), pp. 229–238.
Uno Atishi, ‘Vyapti in Jainism,’ in N. K. Wagle and F. Watanabe eds., Studies on
Buddhism in Honour of Professor A. K. Warder (Toronto: University of
Toronto, 1993), pp. 160–167.
Van Den Bossche, Frank, ‘Jain Relativism: an Attempt at Understanding,’ in R.
Smet and K. Watanabe eds. Jain Studies in Honour of Jozef Deleu (Tokyo:
Hon-No-Tomosha, 1993), pp. 457–474.
—— ‘Existence and Non-Existence in Haribhadra Suri’s Anekantajayapataka,’
Journal of Indian Philosophy 23 (1995), pp. 429–468.
Wada, Toshihiro, Invariable Concomitance in Navya-Nyaya (Delhi: Sri Satguru,
1990).
202 Philosophy in classical India
Walton, Douglas, Arguments from Ignorance (Penn.: Pennsylvania State
University Press, 1996).
Watanabe Fumimaro, Philosophy and its Development in the Nikayas and
Abhidharma (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1983).
Westertähl, D., ‘Quantifiers,’ in D. Gabbay and F. Guenther eds., The Handbook
of Philosophical Logic, Vol. 4: Topics in the Philosophy of Language
(Dordrecht: Reidel, 1988).
Williams, Bernard, Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry (Harmondsworth:
Penguin, 1978).
Williams, D. C., ‘On the Elements of Being,’ Review of Metaphysics 7 (1953), pp. 171–
192.
Zong-qi, Cai, ‘Derrida and Madhyamika Buddhism,’ International Philosophical
Quarterly 33.2 (1993), pp. 183–195.
Index
Abhidharma 100–3, 124–5, 171, 177
absence (abhava) 12, 21, 72, 74, 82–
91, 95, 98, 175–6; versus nonexistence 82, 144–7
absolute conception see objective
conception
Advaita Vedanta see Vedanta
Ajivikas, the 143–4, 180
Akalanka 144, 147–8, 181, 185
Annambhatta 86, 190
Apararkadeva 175
Aristotle 65, 97; Aristotelian syllogism 31
Arthasastra (Treatise on Gains) 8–10,
184
associate condition (upadhi) 79, 145,
152, 154, 162
association and dissociation, method of
(anvaya-vyatireka) 109–10, 118
ataraxia or equipoise 39, 55
atoms 10, 34, 72–5, 77–8, 124–5, 175
attention, faculty of 22–5
authority 2, 10–11, 37, 166; see also
testimony
Bagchi, Sitansusekhar 167, 182
Balcerowicz, Piotr 5, 177
Bandyopadhyay, Nandita 181
Basham, A. L. 180
Bhaduri, S. 95
Bharadwaja, Vijay 69, 167, 179, 182
Bhartrhari 58, 109, 111–12
Bhasarvajña 71, 76–8, 91–2, 95, 174–
5, 181, 186, 194
Bhatt, Bansidhar 180
Bhattacharya, Gopikamohan 178
Bhattacharya, Kalidas 17, 170
Bhattacharya, Kamaleswar 63, 69, 173
Bhattacharya, Ram Shankar
Bhattacharyya, Sibajiban 95, 174, 181
Bhavaviveka 49
Bilimoria, Purushottama 169, 173
bogus reason (hetvabhasa) 32–3, 37–9,
119; the ‘unproven’ (sadhyasama)
33, 39, 59
Borges, Jorges Luis 66, 174
Buddha, the 42, 48, 51, 67, 132
Buddhapalita 49
Buddhism see Abhidharma,
Madhyamaka, Yogacara
burden of proof 59, 151, 153–7, 160,
163
Burton, David 69, 173–4
Candrakirti 49, 68, 185, 187
Canguilhem, G. 4
Caraka 26, 171
Cardona, George 69, 173
Carvaka 135, 160
catuskoti ‘ four-limbed’ refutation 48–51,
52–6
causation 44, 46, 50–8, 62, 77
Chakrabarti, Arindam 5, 40–1, 171–2
Chakrabarti, Kisor 41, 95, 184
change 53–4, 72–3, 125–6, 128–30
Chisholm, Roderick 21, 166, 170, 183
Cohen, M. R. 157, 182
Colebrooke, Henry 29
collecting relation (paryapti) 92
colour, problem of mixed 81, 88, 131–2
common-sense 27–8, 40, 131–2; scheme
43–7, 50, 57, 67–8, 97–8, 100
concepts, Dinnaga’s theory of 99–100,
106, 137
conceptual construction (kalpana) 100–
6, 177
connectedness of the world 81–2; see
also unity
consciousness 23–5, 166
contact (sanyoga) 26, 47, 76–7, 82, 88;
sensory 17 22, 125
204 Philosophy in classical India
content, Nyaya theory of 19, 158–9
contradiction 37, 129–34, 138, 141,
146, 153, 155–6, 159–61, 163, 165,
181; see also paraconsistency.
counterfactuals 36, 122, 153, 158–61,
163
Coward, Harold 172
critical inquiry (Anviksiki) 7–17; and
problem-solving 14
culture 2–3, 5
Daniels, Norman 182–3
Davidson, Donald 171
debate 2, 10, 13, 15, 17, 26, 28–35
passim, 37–9, 119, 128
deep case (karaka) 63
definition, nature of 17–8, 33, 63–5,
75–7, 130
demonstration (avayava) 13–15, 17,
28–9, 32, 37, 49, 62; see also
extrapolation, inference
Descartes, René 37–8, 72, 156
dharma, as basic ingredient 48, 101–3,
177
dharma, as proper conduct 3, 7–8, 169
Dharmakirti 21, 118, 121–4, 126–7,
145, 176–9, 181, 186, 188–9, 191
Dinnaga 2, 33–4, 40, 50, 58, 62, 68,
97–127
passim, 129, 137, 144, 146–7, 152,
170–2, 177–9, 184–5, 188
dialetheic logic see paraconsistency
doubt (samsaya) 13–4, 20, 24, 131,
151–168
passim
doxastic ascent 58–9, 159–62
Dravid, N. S. 182, 184, 186
Dretske, Fred 179
Dreyfus, Georges B. J. 179
duhkha 15–16, 22–4, 36, 44, 48, 50–2
Dummett, Michael 178
Dundas, Paul 135, 180
Edgerton, Franklin 170
emptiness (sunyata) 1, 42–70
passim, 97, 123, 172–4
epistemic closure, principles of 110
error 23, 28, 44; 58, 128, 157; Nyaya
theory of 158–9
ethics 3–4, 10, 15–17, 23, 36, 44, 98, 172
Eubulides 94
example (udaharana) 14, 28–35, 50, 62,
81, 114–22, 144–7, 152, 154–5, 162
exclusion (apoha) 100, 106–15, 137, 148,
178
extraction (apoddhara), method of 111
extrapolation 22, 25–35
passim, 38–40, 62, 99, 114–23
passim, 144–7
passim, 152–4, 158, 162–4, 167; see
also inference
five-limbed inference schema see
demonstration
Franco, Eli 181, 189–90
Frauwallner, E. 171, 177
Frege, Gottlob 4, 96, 175, 178
Freud, Sigmund 170
Fricker, Elizabeth 172
Fynes, Richard 180
Gadadhara 91–2
Galloway, Brian 69, 173
gambler’s fallacy 164–5
Ganeri, Jonardon 41, 96, 127, 169,
171–3, 176–8, 180, 182
Gangesa 89–91, 95, 154–5, 158–67,
176, 181, 189–90
Gangopadhyay, Mrinalkanti 41, 168,
182, 185–7, 190
Gautama Aksapada 10, 13, 21, 27–8,
40, 60, 187
Gillon, Brendan 5, 178, 188
Goekoop, Cornelius 96, 190
Gokhale, Pradeep 150, 171, 180, 191
Goodman, Nelson 163, 182
Goody, Jack 169
Gosala 143
Granoff, Phyllis 167, 181, 185
Gutting, Gary 175
Hacker, Paul 9, 170
Hacking, Ian 80, 174–5
Halbfass, Wilhelm 40, 71, 95, 170,
174–5
Haribhadra 129, 150, 169, 179, 184
Hattori, Masaaki 102–3, 112, 126–7,
177–8, 188
Hayes, Richard 69, 102, 126–7, 172–3,
177–8, 188
Hemacandra 129–32, 140–1, 149, 180,
184, 188–9
Herzberger, Hans H. 178
highest goal, the (nihsreyasa) see
liberation
Hoffman, Frank 69
Hume, David 5, 36, 160, 170
Huntington, C. W. 69
imagination (vikalpa) 21; see also
conceptual construction
Index 205
individuator (visesa) 72–80, 93, 175
induction, problem of 116, 118, 122,
151–2, 160, 164
inference 10–11, 14, 21–2, 24, 26–38,
49, 61–2, 89–91, 100–2, 103, 106,
110, 114–23, 125, 134, 144–7, 151–
4, 159–60, 163–5, 171, 174, 177–9;
from sampling 26, 30, 33, 35, 121,
154; of the ‘residual’ 27; from nonobservation (anupalabdhi) 21, 110,
121, 122; and the universal rule
(vyapti) 31, 33, 37, 118, 122, 145–7,
151, 160
Ingalls, Daniel 81, 95, 142, 175–6, 180,
190
inherence (samavaya) 26, 72–6, 79, 82,
84–7, 92, 97–9, 111, 174–5
Jacobi, Hermann 9, 70
Jagadisa 92, 151, 176
Jainism 2–3, 30, 40, 98, 126, 128–50
passim, 177, 179–81
Jaskowski, S. 140, 180
Jayarasi 27–8, 167, 171, 181, 190
Jayatilleke, K. N. 181
Jhalakikar, Bhimacarya 182
justification 162–3, 165–7; virtuous
circle of 163–4
Kamalasila 176
Kanada 130, 188, 191
Kaplan, David 180
karaka see deep case
karma theory of moral retribution 16,
23, 44
Katsura, Shoryu 102–3, 126–7, 177–9,
188–9
Kautilya 2, 8–12, 16, 28, 184
Khalida, Muhamad Ali 174–5
knowing, method of (pramana) 10, 12–
14, 27, 32, 35, 58–62, 77, 100, 106,
125, 129, 134, 148–9, 152–3, 157,
162, 166
Kumarila 156
language 2, 4, 58, 98, 102–5, 128, 133,
135–7, 141, 143; limits to 1, 42;
propositional 89–90
Larson, Gerald James 170
Lear, Jonathan 65, 174
Lewis, David 173, 179
liberation 9, 15–17
Liberman, Kenneth 172
likeness see similarity
Lokayata 7–9, 27
Loy, David 172
Madhyamaka Buddhism 1, 39–40,
42–70, 98, 124, 172–4, 185
Magritte, René 83
Mahabharata, the 7
Mahavira 132, 149
Mallisena 139–40, 143, 189
Manu 1, 8
many-sidedness, theory of (anekantavada)
128–30, 134, 148, 150
Masaaki, Hattori 102–3, 112, 126–7,
177–8, 188
mathematics 72–3, 94; see also number
Matilal, Bimal Krishna 3, 5, 19, 21, 28,
33, 40–1, 69–70, 81, 95–6, 102,
126–7, 147, 149–50, 167–82,
185–7, 190
maximal property see universally
present property
McEvilley, Thomas 173
meaning 4, 9, 58, 60, 104–6, 133,
135–7; as basis for application
(praVrttinimitta) 106–7; exclusion
theory of 106–14, 178; Jaina theory
of 137–43, 148; of names 91, 104–5;
of sentences 111–14
Meltzoff, Andrew 171
memory 24–5, 101
metaphysical pluralism 98, 137, 176
mind, the (manas) 1, 10, 22–5, 171
Mistry, Rohinton 183
Mohanty, J. N. 3, 41, 96, 166, 169,
173, 183, 190
Moksakaragupta 151, 179
moral theory see ethics
motion (karma) 44, 46, 51, 58, 63–6,
69, 72–8, 93, 98, 107, 126, 173
Müller, Max 2, 169
Nagarjuna 1, 26, 39, 42–70, 94, 97–8,
123, 156–7, 172–4, 185–6, 191
Nagel, Ernest 157, 182
Nagel, Thomas 172, 182
natural kinds: cross-cutting systems of
80–1; jati as 81
Navya-Nyaya 71, 81–95, 141, 151–68,
174–6, 181–3, 189–90
negation 53, 67, 82–91, 94, 107, 113,
132, 140–1, 159, ; rules of Double
Negation Elimination and
Introduction 87, 89, 175
Nenninger, Claudius 41
Niksepa 133, 180
nirvana 42
Nisbett, R. 164, 182
206 Philosophy in classical India
nominalism 2, 43, 97, 104–5
non-monotonicity 41, 62
non-observation, inference from see
inference, from non-observation
norms of reason 2–3, 15, 29, 31, 35,
119, 169
number 52, 91–4, 176
Nyaya 10–41, 46, 65, 88, 94, 99, 114,
125, 132, 137, 152, 157, 170–2; see
also Navya-Nyaya
nyaya 11, 15, 37
Nyayasutra, the 10–41, 60, 154, 171, 187
O’Brien, J. Dervin 173
objective conception 1, 43–7, 66–8, 172
objective support (alambana) see
support, objective
objectivity 22, 50, 129, 176
Oetke, Claus 41, 127, 171
‘only’ (eva), as a quantifier 112–14,
127, 139–41, 178
Ono, Motoi 127, 179
Padmarajiah, Y. J. 130, 150, 180
pain see duhkha
Pandeya, R. C. 138, 180
Panini 113, 142
paraconsistency 141, 143, 165–6; and
non-adjunctive logics of discourse
141–2; see also contradiction
paradox 54, 94, 141, 173; of origin
50–9; of motion 51, 58, 63–6; of
change 53–4
Parasher, Aloka 172
perception 10, 15, 17–25, 37–9, 45–7,
51, 61–2, 100–4, 106, 115, 122–6,
134, 148, 154, 158, 170, 176–7
Perrett, Roy W. 96, 175
persistence see change
perspective see standpoint
Phillips, Stephen 5, 168, 181–2, 189–90
Plato 10
pleasure 16, 22–4, 136
pluralism see metaphysical pluralism
Potter, Karl 95, 174–7, 181, 184–9
pramana epistemology, see knowing,
method of
Pramanasamuccaya (Collection on
Knowing) 97–121, 126, 170, 173,
177, 180, 188
prasanga 47–54, 155–7, 172
Prasastapada 22, 58, 76, 187
pretence (aharya) 158–9
Price, Huw 176, 180
Priest, Graham 54, 140, 173, 176, 180
problem of the criterion 166–7
quality (guna) 27, 72–8, 88, 91–4, 98,
100, 104, 107, 111–12, 126, 148
quibbling (cchala) 11, 60, 173
Radhakrishnan, Sarvepalli 2, 169, 189–90
Raghunatha 71, 77–8, 85–6, 91–2, 95,
175–6, 185, 188
Ramakrishnan, Lakshmi 169
Ramanujan, A. K. 3, 169
Ramayana, the 7
Ram-Prasad, C. 40, 168
Randle, H. N. 28, 171, 188
Rawls, John 182
realism 17, 58, 88, 98, 125, 176
reason property (hetu) 12, 14, 26–35,
57, 89–91, 114–23, 144–7, 151–3,
162–7
reductionism 2, 97–8, 107, 125, 171, 176
reflective equilibrium 153, 164–7
Rescher, Nicholas 105, 177, 180
resemblance see similarity
Robinson, Richard H. 70, 172–3
Ruegg, David Seyfort 4, 42, 69–70,
170, 172, 174
Russell, Bertrand 10, 91, 170
Ryle, Gilbert 72, 174
Samkhya 8–9, 26, 170–1
sadhyasama see bogus reason
Sagal, Paul 70
Samkara 130, 180
Sanghvi, Sukhlalji 148, 150, 180, 188–9
Sañjaya 94
Santaraksita 130, 180
Santideva 49, 172
Sartre, Jean Paul 170
scepticism 2, 7–8, 11, 27–8, 38–40, 42–
3, 67, 148, 152–4, 156–7, 159–61,
163, 174, 181; Pyrrhonic 55–7
Schayer, Stanislaw 31, 157, 171, 182
Schiffer, Stephen 180
scientific explanation 26, 57–8, 68, 77,
80–1
self see soul
self-marked (svalaksana) 100–4, 106
self-refutation 66–8
self-standing nature (svabhava) 44–5,
47, 66–8
semantic model 89
Sen, Prabal Kumar 95, 176
sense–reference distinction 3–4, 136
senses, the 18–9, 22–5, 38, 58, 61, 101,
105, 124–5; inner sense 22, 101
seven-fold division (saptabhangi)
137–40, 149, 189
Index 207
Sextus Empiricus 55–7, 173
Shah, Nagin J. 150, 181
Shaw, J. L. 96
Siddhasena 130, 134, 144–5, 149, 180,
186, 189
Siderits, Mark 69, 172–3
similarity 27, 29–38
passim, 75, 99–127
passim, 144, 147, 153, 179
simplicity (laghutva) 2, 97, 157
Solomon, Esther 41, 167, 169, 181
‘somehow’ (syat), as a modal operator
138–41, 147–9
Soni, Jayandra 150
sophistical resemblance-based rejoinder
(jati) 13, 31–3
Sorabji, Richard 5, 179
Sosa, Ernest 58, 152, 173, 181–2
soul, the (atman) 8–9, 11, 13, 22–5, 34,
44, 128, 143, 171; soul-mind
division 22–5
Sousa, Ronald de 174
Stout, G. F. 99, 176
Sriharsa 2, 94, 156–68
passim, 181, 185
standpoint (naya) 133–7, 143, 150
Stcherbatsky, Theodore 177, 186–7
Steinkellner, E. 126, 177, 179
Stich, Stephen 164, 182
Strawson, P. F. 40, 172, 180
substance (dravya) 27, 64, 72–9, 87–8,
91, 101, 104, 111–2, 129–33, 135–
6, 138–9, 143, 148–9, 174
substitution, property-, model of
inference 29
support, objective (alambana) 45, 48,
123–6
suppositional reasoning (tarka) 13–4,
24, 144–4, 151, 153–68, 181
syadvada see ‘somehow’
Tachikawa, Masashi 79, 174, 185
Taylor, Charles 169
testimony 10, 14, 24, 35–40, 61, 134
Thakur, Anantalal 170, 187
theory revision 3, 46, 71, 76–8, 89, 94,
132, 164–7, 174
Thomason, Richard 174
Tillemans, Tom F. 127, 178, 189
time 8, 23–6, 44, 52, 132–3; the three
times 56–7; and the now 64–6, 136
Trairasikas, the 143–3
trope 72, 99–111, 122, 125–6
truth 42, 57, 89–91, 120, 123, 128, 134,
137–41, 149, 152–3, 162, 179, 182;
‘conventional’ vs. ‘ultimate’ 45, 101
truth-aptness 50, 158
truth-value 48, 89, 114, 149, 172, 180;
links 66
Tucci, G. 171
Tuske, Joerg 171, 182
Udayana 71, 73–81, 95, 154–62, 171,
176, 182, 184–7
Uddyotakara 18, 21, 23, 38, 62, 170,
187
unity 2, 17, 81, 97, 101–2, 107, 111
universal (samanya) 10, 22, 33, 52, 72–
81, 86, 91, 98–100, 104, 107, 109,
111, 119, 135, 176
universally present property
(kevalanvayin) 90
unpervaded occurrence (avyapyaVrttitva) 82, 88–90
Upanisads, the 1, 11, 97, 169
Vacaka Umasvati 130, 189
Vacaspati 153–4, 187
Vadideva Suri 137–8, 140, 145, 149,
188
Vaisesika 2, 47, 58, 68, 71–96
passim, 98–9, 104, 111, 119, 125,
130–2, 137, 174–6
Vaisesikasutra 26, 41, 170–1, 176,
188, 191
validity 89–91
Van Den Bossche, Frank 150
Vatsyayana Paksilasvamin 10–20, 23–
4, 26–7, 32, 34–5, 37–40, 170,
186–7
Vedanta 2, 8, 135, 162, 176
Vedas, the 2, 7–8, 35
Vidhyabhusana, S. C. 29
Vigrahavyavartani (Reply to Critics)
43–4, 59–62, 66–8, 191
Vyadi 113
Vyomasiva 181
Wada, Toshihiro 96
Walton, Douglas 122, 179, 181
wholes 10, 13, 18, 21–3, 26, 72, 88,
97–9, 101, 147–9, 171, 175
William of Occam 97
Williams, Bernard 172
Williams, D. C. 99, 176
Yasovijaya 136, 141–4, 185
Yoga 8–9, 170
Yogacara Buddhism 2, 40, 178
Zeno 65, 94, 173–4