To appear: Proc. Eighth Intl. Conf. on Risk and Gambling, London, July 1990
Could Gambling Save Science
Encouraging an Honest Consensus
Visiting Researcher, The Foresight Institute
P.O. Box 61058, Palo Alto, CA 94306 USA
[email protected] 415-651-7483
The pace of scientific progress may be hindered by the tendency of our
academic institutions to reward being popular, rather than being right. A
market-based alternative, where scientists more formally "stake their
reputation", is presented here. It offers clear incentives to be careful
and honest while contributing to a visible, self-consistent consensus on
controversial (or routine) scientific questions. In addition, it allows
funders to choose questions to be researched without choosing people or
methods. The bulk of this paper is spent examining potential problems with
the proposed approach. After this examination, the idea still seems
plausible and worth further study.
Introduction
After reviewing the discrepancy between what we want from academic
institutions and what we get from current institutions, a market-based
alternative called "idea futures" is suggested. It is described through
both a set of specific scenarios and a set of detailed procedures. Over
thirty possible problems and objections are examined in detail. Finally, a
development strategy is outlined and the possible advantages are
summarized.
The Problem
THE SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTION Four centuries ago, some Europeans complained
that the existing academic institutions were biased against them.
Insiders, it was said, were "inflated by letters" and shunned anyone who
dared "speculate on anything out of the common way" [De]. Outsiders --
astrologers, chemists, and people like Bacon and Galileo -- argued that
they and their theories should be judged only by how well they agreed with
observations, and not by how they agreed with the authorities of the day
[Gal]. This was the age of utopias [Wh], as these rebels debated possible
academic reforms and imagined whole new social institutions, for both
academia in particular and society in general.
Within a century or so, the intellectual descendants of these outsiders
became the new insiders in a process now called the "Scientific
Revolution". They introduced a new respect for observations along with new
social institutions, such as the Royal Society of England, inspired by
those utopian ideals. Since then science has made impressive progress.
Most controversial issues of four centuries ago seem long settled by now,
and continued research may well settle most of the today's controversies.
Academia can claim some credit for this, and academic institutions have
continued to evolve in response to perceived problems, formalizing
publication in journals, credit in citations, and evaluation in anonymous
peer review.
PROBLEMS WITH ACADEMIA Yet little has really changed. Academia is still
largely a medieval guild, with a few powerful elites, many slave-like
apprentices, and members who hold a monopoly on the research patronage of
princes and the teaching of their sons. Outsiders still complain about
bias, saying their evidence is ignored, and many observers [Gh,Re,Syk,Tu]
have noted some long-standing problems with the research component of
academia. (Teaching is not considered here.)
Peer review is just another popularity contest, inducing familiar political
games; savvy players criticize outsiders, praise insiders, follow the
fashions insiders indicate, and avoid subjects between or outside the
familiar subjects. It can take surprisingly long for outright lying by
insiders to be exposed [Re]. There are too few incentives to correct for
cognitive [Kah] and social [My] biases, such as wishful thinking,
overconfidence, anchoring [He], and preferring people with a background
similar to your own.
Publication quantity is often the major measure of success. This
encourages redundant publication of "smallest publishable units" by many
co-authors. The need to have one's research appear original gives too
little incentive to see if it has already been done elsewhere, as is often
the case, and neglects efforts to integrate previous research.
Perhaps the core problem is that academics are rewarded mainly for telling
a good story, rather than for being right. (By "right" I include not only
being literally correct, but also being on the right track, or enabling
work on the right track.) Publications, grants, and tenure are based what
other insiders think today, independent of whether one's ideas and results
are proved correct or valuable later. Even for researchers with a good
track record, grant proposals must usually describe in some detail exactly
what will be discovered and how; true exploratory work is done on the sly.
This emphasis on story-telling rewards the eloquent, who know how to
persuade by ignoring evidence that goes against their view, and by other
standard tricks [Ci].
Admittedly, someone who has published an unusual idea that has proven right
is thought of more highly, all else being equal. But all else is usually
not equal. Outsiders find it hard to get an unusual idea published, and
being able to say "I told you so" is of little help to academics who have
failed to gain tenure. The powerful often get credit for the successes of
those under them [Re]. Only in the most experimental fields, where
feedback is direct and frequent, can we expect people who are disliked --
but usually right -- to be rewarded through informal reputations.
Perhaps our biggest problem is the distortion evident when a science
question becomes relevant for public policy, as in the recent debates over
"Star Wars" or the greenhouse effect. The popular media tend to focus on
those scientists prone to hyperbole. Any honest consensus of relevant
experts is usually lost from public view, as advocates on each side accuse
the other of bias and self-interest. Public policy can suffer dramatically
as a result, a consequence that becomes more serious as the pace of
technological change quickens.
On the whole, current academic institutions seem less than ideal [Ki], with
incentives that reward being popular, fashionable, and eloquent, instead of
being right.
INCENTIVES MATTER Are these complaints just sour grapes? Those who do
well by an existing system tend to believe problems are minor. But even if
the best ideas eventually win, we should worry if the people who advocate
those ideas don't win. The social organization of any human effort can
have a tremendous effect on its efficiency. For example, the heated debate
over national health care is mostly about which way to fund and organize
health care provides the best incentives to promote the general health.
And different past cultures with different ways of organizing have had very
different rates of scientific progress; compare Europe with China over the
last five centuries. Our rate of progress may be less than 2% of what it
could be [Be].
Are we wasting precious resources? Imagine what would happen if we used
academic peer review to decide what products to manufacture. Proposals for
new products would be reviewed anonymously by powerful people who produce
similar products. These reviewers would pass judgement without taking any
personal risk, and those judged favorably would win regardless of how
useful their product turned out to be.
I much prefer our current business system, with all of its problems, where
investors must take a personal risk when they endorse a product.
Institutions like the stock market are comparatively egalitarian and
flexible, allowing most anyone to participate in the ongoing debate about
the profit potential of any public business or the relative potential of
various industries, management styles, etc. Why can't we have academic
research institutions like these?
ACADEMIC REFORMS Most efforts to improve academic institutions focus on
incremental reform. Should reviewers be anonymous? Should submissions be
anonymous? Occasionally someone proposes a more radical reform within the
current framework, such as abolishing tenure or government funding [Fe], or
scrapping the whole thing in favor of some existing alternative like
patents. And once in a while a whole new social institution is proposed.
For example, science courts [Kan] (also called "scientific adversary
procedures") were invented to blunt hyperbole on science controversies by
using court-like proceedings to encourage cross-examination and to document
areas of agreement. Hypertext publishing [Dr,Han88] imagines an advanced
electronic publishing media where any critic could directly link a
criticism to any published item, and where readers could combine the direct
evaluations of previous readers they respect to decide what is worth
reading. A recent suggestion [Ts] imagines governments paying private labs
for each citation of one of their employee's papers, allowing a
decentralized market to set research priorities. And prizes are often
suggested as a way to fund specific verifiable achievements like sequencing
the human genome.
In this paper, I propose a new academic institution, tentatively called
"idea futures". Also market-based, it is intended to counter many existing
problems. It is utopian in the sense of describing a coherent vision of
how things might be rather different, but hopefully practical in the sense
of considering what could go wrong and how to start small.
WHAT WE WANT Before considering specific mechanisms, let us reflect a
moment on what we want from academic incentives. We want to encourage
honesty and fair play; the game should be open to anyone to prove
him/herself. Funders of research, either private foundations or
governments, presumably want research to be directed toward the academic
subjects and questions of interest to those funders. (Funders also include
the researchers themselves, to the extent that reduced salaries are
understood to be in exchange for some research autonomy.) On controversial
questions, we want a clear measure of the current opinion of relevant
experts, a measure which political advocates could not easily distort. And
those who contribute to such a measure should have clear incentives to be
careful and honest.
Presumably we want as much progress as possible per effort invested, at
least in situations where the following notion of "progress" makes sense.
Consider a well-posed question, such as "Is the Earth basically
spherical?", with a handful of possible answers (such as "No, its flat").
Experience indicates that, with enough study and evidence, one of the
answers will eventually stand out as best to most anyone who considers the
question carefully. At least this seems to happen for most questions that
have been traditionally labeled "scientific"; questions about the morality
of abortion or the nature of God may not fare as well. Where there is such
a limiting "right" answer, "progress" can mean the rate at which general
scientific opinion converges to that answer. This definition of progress
hopefully avoids debates about whether more knowledge is good, or whether
there is really an ultimate truth.
Translating these goals to an individual level, we want our institutions to
reward academics for pushing scientific opinion toward the "right" answer,
presumably by somehow increasing their reputation, influence, or resources.
Let us imagine an academic who, after some reflection or observation, comes
to a tentative conclusion which he/she would like others to consider. If
most everyone already agrees with this conclusion, even without seeing the
new supporting evidence or analysis, the academic should receive little
credit for just making an "obvious" claim. However, credit should be
possible if the claim is surprising, i.e., if people who have not yet seen
the evidence are not yet willing to agree. If, upon reviewing the
evidence, most everyone now agrees with the surprising claim, then the
academic should certainly receive some credit. And, in fact, peer review
can handle this case. But what if there is not uniform agreement? It
still seems that the academic should be rewarded, if the claim is
eventually born out. And others who supported the claim in the face of
disagreement should also gain credit [Led], since they helped push the
general opinion in the right direction.
Why shouldn't savvy academics now win credit by supporting as many claims
as possible, or by multiplying controversies? Clearly they should risk
losing credit when they are wrong, so that credit is in some ways
conserved. The ratio of possible loss to gain should depend on how unusual
one's position is. Siding with the majority and being right should gain
one less than siding with a minority and being right. The total amount
gained or lost should depend on how much of their reputation each academic
has chosen to stake on this issue, as well as on how interesting the issue
is to the ultimate research funders.
In summary, part of what we want from academic incentives is a fair game
for staking our reputation, so that on questions of interest to funders, we
converge as fast as possible to the "right" answer.
THE PROPOSAL
Surprising as it may seem, such a social institution exists. It is
relatively simple, cheap, decentralized, and egalitarian. It could create
a consensus on disputed science questions that would be clear, expert,
honest, and self-consistent across a wide range of issues. This consensus
should respond quickly to new information, and predict at least as well as
any other co-existing consensus mechanism. It is well-grounded in our best
theories of decision and incentives.
And it is ancient. We need only revive and embellish a suggestion made
back during the utopian scientific revolution. Chemical physicians,
excluded by the standard physicians from teaching in the British schools,
repeatedly offered challenges like the following (circa 1651):
Oh ye Schooles. ... Let us take out of the hospitals, out of the
Camps, or from elsewhere, 200, or 500 poor People, that have Fevers,
Pleurisies, etc. Let us divide them into halfes, let us cast lots,
that one halfe of them may fall to my share, and the other to yours;
... we shall see how many Funerals both of us shall have: But let the
reward of the contention or wager, be 300 Florens, deposited on both
sides: Here your business is decided. [De]
They proposed to bet on the question, apparently believing bets to be a
useful augmentation of the existing academic incentives! Bets are a long-
established and robust reputation mechanism, widely seen as a cure for
excessive verbal wrangling; you "put your money where your mouth is". In
science and elsewhere, phrases like "you bet" are standard ways to express
confidence. Offers to make token bets are particularly compelling, and
scientists of equal stature often make and publicize such bets, with recent
bets on resource depletion, computer chess, black holes [Hal], solar
neutrinos, and cold fusion [Gar,Lew,WSJ].
Consider the example of Piers Corbyn, a London astrophysicist who has been
unable to get academic metrologists interested in his unusual theory of
long-term weather cycles [NS]. Since June 1988 he has been making bets to
gain publicity, betting against the bookmaker William Hill, who uses odds
posted by the British Metrological Service. Over the last six months
alone, he has won 80% of his 25 bets a month, gaining an over 90% average
rate of return per bet. (There is a one in 200 to 10^20 chance, depending
on what independence you assume, of this happening randomly.) Yet the
Service still refuses to take Piers seriously, or make even token bets
against him. Which doesn't seem quite fair; hasn't Pier earned the right
to be considered? William Hill has taken on the bets for the publicity,
but is tired of losing, and has adjusted their odds accordingly. Why
shouldn't these be the odds used for official British agricultural policy,
instead of the Service's predictions?
If the primary way that academics are now rewarded for being right, rather
than popular, is an informal process for staking their reputation, which
has various biases because of its informality, and if we want a better
reputation game, why not literally make bets and formalize the process?
Imagine a betting pool or market on most disputed science questions , with
the going odds available to the popular media, and treated socially as the
current academic consensus. Imagine that academics are expected to "put up
or shut up" and accompany claims with at least token bets, and that
statistics are collected on how well people do. Imagine that funding
agencies subsidize pools on questions of interest to them, and that
research labs pay for much of their research with winnings from previous
pools. And imagine that anyone could play, either to take a stand on an
important issue, or to insure against technological risk.
This would be an "idea futures" market, which I offer as an alternative to
existing academic social institutions. Somewhat like a corn futures
market, where one can bet on the future price of corn, here one bets on the
future settlement of a present scientific controversy. This is admittedly
an unusual suggestion. But consider what might happen.
Scenarios
CONTINENTAL DRIFT In 1915 German meteorologist Alfred Wegener published
his theory of continental drift, which he had collected extensive evidence
in support of. But contemporaries considered his theory to be
"impossible", and Wegener died an intellectual outcast in 1930 [Mar]. Yet
in the 1960's his theory began to be taken seriously, and is now the
established view. Wegener eventually gained fame, but overall academia
seems to discourage activity like his. Some of Wegener's peers, for
example, probably found his thesis plausible, but decided that to say so
publicly would be a poor career move.
With idea futures, Wegener could have opened a market for people to bet on
his theory, perhaps to be judged by some official body of geologists in a
century. He could have then offered to bet a token amount at, say, 1-4
odds, in effect saying there was at least at 20% chance his claim would be
vindicated. His opponents would have had to either accept this estimate,
and its implications about the importance of Wegener's research, or bet
enough to drive the market odds down to something a little closer to
"impossible". They could not suppress Wegener merely by silence or
ridicule.
As Wegener increased his stake, buying more bets to move the price back up,
his opponents would hopefully think just a little more carefully before
betting even more to move the price back down. Others might find it in
their interest to support Wegener; anyone who thought the consensus odds
were wrong would expect to make money by betting, and would thereby move
the consensus toward what they believe. Everyone would have a clear
incentive to be careful and honest!
The market would encourage more research related to continental drift, as
one could make money by being the first to trade on new relevant
information. Eventually the evidence would more clearly tip in Wegener's
favor, and the price of his bets would rise. Wegener, or his children,
could then sell those bets and reap some rewards. While those rewards
would not make up for years of neglect, at least he would get something.
As the controversy became settled, and opinions converged, people would
gradually sell and leave the market. Few people, if any, need be left for
the final judging, which could usually be avoided (using mechanisms to be
described below).
COLD FUSION A more recent controversy began in March 1989, when Pons and
Fleishman announced "fusion in a jar" at a dramatic press conference. In
the months that followed, media aftershocks of confirmation attempts were
tracked by thousands of scientists and others, who argued with each other
about the chances of cold fusion being real. Proposals to bet came up
often, even in the public debates. Critics, uncomfortable with airing
scientific disputes in public, complained that Pons and Fleishman broke the
rules by going to the popular media instead of through normal peer review
channels, unfairly gaining extra attention and funding. Supporters
countered that popular media spread information quickly to other
scientists; cold fusion, if right, was too important to wait for normal
channels.
In the journal Science , Robert Pool speculated that a market in cold fusion
might have gone something like Figure 1 [Poo]. If there really had been a
betting market, then there would have been a market price that journalists
like Pool could publish as news. A table of going prices might appear on
the science page in the newspaper, much like the stock page in the business
section, conveying current scientific opinion better than the current
"balanced" interviews with extremists on all sides. It's been suggested
[Ze] that the added information in betting market prices might have helped
resolve the debate more quickly
Figure 1 A Hypothetical Market in Cold Fusion
There needn't be a conflict between going through slow proper channels and
getting the word out, if a fast market were a proper channel. The effect
of staged media events might be reduced as it might not be news if the
price didn't change; advocates would have to convince, not the average
listener, but those people willing to make bets. Remaining biases, such as
the overconfidence evident in figure 1, would be reduced by technical and
other trading specialists.
Cold fusion businesses would have been less risky to start. As it was, a
new fusion business had to bet both that cold fusion was real, and that
they were the best group to develop and market it in that case. With idea
futures they could, by both starting a business and betting against cold
fusion (essentially taking out insurance), really only be betting on their
ability to develop cold fusion if it were real.
Insights from a great many people whose opinions on the cold fusion
controversy were ignored, such as inarticulate people and those without
Ph.Ds, could have been integrated in a decentralized manner. Popular play
would end up subsidizing professional efforts on questions of popular
interest, offering more "direct democracy" in setting research priorities.
NEUTRINO MASS Betting markets could also function in the absence of overt
controversy, as in the following (hypothetical) story.
Once upon a time the Great Science Foundation decided it would be a "good
thing" to know the mass of the electron neutrino. Instead of trying to
figure out who would be a good person to work on this, or what a good
research strategy would be, they decided to just subsidize betting markets
on the neutrino mass. They spent millions.
Soon the market odds were about 5% that the mass was above 0.1eV, and Gung
Ho Labs became intrigued by the profits to be made. They estimated that
for about $300K spent on two researchers over 3 years, they could make a
high confidence measurement of whether the mass was above 0.1eV. So they
went ahead with the project, and later got their result, which they kept
very secret. While the market now estimated the chance of a mass over
0.1eV at 4%, their experiment said the chance was at most 0.1%.
So they quietly bought bets against a high mass, moving the price down to
2.5% in the process. They then revealed their results to the world, and
tried their best to convince people that their experiment was solid. After
a few months they mostly succeeded, and when the price had dropped to 0.7%
they began to sell they bets they had made. They made $400K off of the
information they had created, which more than covered their expenses to get
that information.
Or course if Gung Ho Labs had failed to convince the world of their
results, they would have faced the difficult choice of quitting at a loss,
or holding out for the long-term. No doubt a careful internal review would
be conducted before making such a decision.
Gung Ho would be free to use peer review, tenure, and fixed salaries
internally, if they are effective ways to organize workers. The two
researchers need not risk their life savings to be paid for their efforts.
But the discipline of the external market should keep these internal
institutions from degenerating into mere popularity contests.
KILLER PEANUT BUTTER Once upon another time, Munchem Biolabs found
compelling evidence that peanut butter was more deadly than most
pesticides, a conclusion that Lunch Industries Exclusive (LIE) wanted
desperately to suppress. LIE's usual procedure was to fund a bunch of
competing studies to come to opposite conclusions, which usually kept the
waters muddy enough that legislators and customers would ignore it all.
But this time they had to deal with an idea futures market on the question,
and the public was beginning to take the odds in such markets seriously.
Munchem had moved the market odds of deadly peanut butter up rather high.
LIE now had two choices; either they could use overwhelming cash to move
the odds back down, or use competing studies, advertising, etc. to persuade
others to bet on their side.
If they bet alone, they would know they were throwing their money away with
no obvious limit on future spending. Not only might Munchem find allies,
but LIE employees who knew they were bluffing might be tempted to pick up a
little free money with some anonymous bets. If word of Lunch's bluff got
out, as insider information often does, investors would flock in and wipe
out the effect of LIE's bets.
If LIE tried to throw away other people's money through a persuasion
campaign, they would face a market dominated, as most liquid markets are,
by battle-hardened speculators. These investors, not easily persuaded by
clever jingles, would quickly hook up with research insiders, who generally
know which labs tend to find whatever results their funders want.
So in the end, Lunch Industries accepted the market odds, and began
research on non-toxic peanut butter.
Procedures
Rather than just present an abstract utopian vision of market-based
academic incentives, this paper aims to consider in some detail what
problems might arise and possible approaches for dealing with them. The
following is a core set of procedures tentatively selected to best deal
with known problems, a core that will be expanded upon later in the paper.
No doubt, experience with real idea futures markets will show many of these
suggestions to have been naive. I offer them primarily to make plausible
the idea that betting markets could be applied to a much wider range of
scientific questions than is presently considered feasible. (This section
is somewhat dense, and may be profitably skimmed on a first reading.)
ASSETS Imagine that John bets Mary $5, at even odds, that it will rain
next Monday. Since they don't entirely trust each other, John and Mary put
the bet in writing and each give $5 to Frank, a trusted third party. John
has essentially paid $5 for an I.O.U. that says "Worth $10 If Rain Monday",
since if he wins he gets $5 from Mary and his own $5 back. Mary's I.O.U.
says "Worth $10 If Not Rain Monday". On Tuesday one of them can cash in
their I.O.U. for $10 from Frank.
This standard betting scenario can be improved by breaking it into
different transactions; first create the I.O.U.s and then sell them.
Replace Frank with a stable financial institution, let's call it a "bank",
which will sell a pair of "$10 if rain", "$10 if not rain" coupons to
anyone for a price of $10. The bank takes no risk, since exactly one of
the coupons will be worth $10 in the end. And since the bank holds the $10
in the meantime, it can afford to offer interest on the $10, and perhaps
pay a local meteorologist to be an impartial judge. Now Mary can first buy
a coupon pair from the bank for $10 and then offer to sell her "$10 if
rain" coupon to John or anyone for $5, retaining the "$10 if not rain" for
herself.
A central clearinghouse for such offers, which matched compatible offers
and insured that people made good on their offers, would always hold a best
current offer to sell and to buy. If the transaction costs of processing
an offer through the clearinghouse were small, as current technology
allows, then the "spread" between these offers could be quite small,
leaving a going "market price". A going price of $3.20 for "$10 if rain
Monday" would represent a temporary consensus of a 32% chance of rain
Monday.
In general, these markets trade assets of the form "X if A" (called
"contingent assets"), where X is some pre-existing "base" asset and A is
one of a set of mutually exclusive claims that some judging organization
agrees to eventually choose from. The base X can be any stock, bond,
currency, commodity, or even another compatible contingent asset. The set
of claims is a "question", and each claim is one possible answer to the
question. To trade on a question, we need an agreement between several
parties - an author, a judge, and one or more banks, registries,
clearinghouses, and randomness checkers.
An author carefully words a set of claims, and a judging organization
agrees to, if necessary, offer a verdict in favor of one of these claims at
some, perhaps indirectly specified, date. Registries hold records of
public, i.e. not anonymous, trades made at clearinghouses. (Clearinghouses
may be required to hold additional private records of all trades, to be
subpoenaed by criminal investigators if necessary.)
Consider a question with possible answers {A,B,...}. Any bank authorized
in the agreement on that question can "split" any allowed base X (usually
anything) into the assets {"X if A", "X if B", ...}, or "join" those assets
back into X. In the example above, $10 was split into "$10 if rain" and
"$10 if not rain". The bank is trusted to report the net effect of these
transactions to a central agent, who keeps track of the net "market
capital" that has been split along this question.
On the specified date, and after a short warning period, the judges are
given an agreed-upon judging-fee in order to study the question and render
their verdict. Verdicts assign a percentage of validity to each of the
possible question answers. If the verdict is 98% in favor of A, then banks
are authorized to let people exchange their "X if A" assets for 98% of X.
The judging-fee is obtained from the banks, who devalue the current assets
contingent on that question by some percentage, a percentage which can be
no more than a pre-specified max-judging-percentage. This devaluation
creates an incentive for traders to "settle out of court" and sell before
the judging date.
What if there is too little capital in the market to support the required
judging fee? John and Mary's market only has $10 in it, and with a 10%
max-juding-fee, only $1 is available for judging, short of the $5 the
meteorologist judge requires. In this case we can hold an "audit lottery"
[Pol]. The current market capital, $10, is gambled with whomever offers
the best price, among those approved by the randomness checker. If the
gamble is won, every asset contingent on this question increases in value,
resulting in enough market capital for judging to proceed, in this case
$50. If the gamble is lost, all such assets become worthless and judging
is not needed. Investors can insure against the added risk audit lotteries
impose by putting money into an pot to be gambled in the same lottery, but
on the other side.
Judges can be given more flexibility to deal better with uncertainties
regarding when a question will be judgeable and how much that will cost.
The max-judging-percentage can be spent in discrete units, each specified
by a percentage-unit and a fee-unit. After spending each percentage-unit,
the judges could choose to postpone judging to a later date and/or raise
the next fee-unit. If necessary, an audit lottery would be held before
each new unit.
If desired, judges can also be given a direct financial incentive to be
careful and honest. "Appeals" markets can be created on the same question,
but judged by an independent group much later and/or with a much higher
judging-fee. For a limited period after a verdict is announced, an amount,
up to a fixed fraction of the original judging-fee, would be spent trying
to move the price in the appeals market toward the verdict specified.
Judges would end up with some contingent assets saying their verdict would
be upheld in the appeals market, assets they could sell immediately, at a
loss, if they so chose.
Idea futures markets need no central management. Anyone could author a
claim on any subject of interest to them, contract with different judging
groups to judge that claim on different dates, and allow different banks to
deal in each question. And anyone should be able to open a clearinghouse
to sell any asset. All of these groups could compete openly for the
attention and respect of investors.
INVESTORS Investors could be as diverse as they are in current markets,
each focusing on some specialty while avoiding risk from other areas. For
example, if the market odds are "incoherent", i.e., deviate from the
standard axioms of probability, a trader who corrects that deviation can
make better than the average rate of return without significant risk.
Therefore coherence specialists should keep the market consensus roughly
consistent over a wide range of subjects. Similarly, technical traders
would keep the pattern of price changes close to the ideal random walk
[Mal]. The market odds should also quickly reflect information contained
in any co-existing consensus measures, such as opinion polls or reports of
elite committees, as traders could make easy money if alternative measures
were reliably better predictors than the market.
A contingent asset, like "X if F", that is split again creates conjunctive
contingent assets like "X if F and A". Conjuncts which combine a great
many claims should be popular, since they offer investors the greatest
expected return. Conjunctive assets also allow one to bet the conditional
probability of A given F and remain insensitive to the verdict on F. In
this way diverse traders, each of whom has only local knowledge, could
manage a large network of dependencies such as the currently popular "Bayes
net" models [Pe].
SOCIAL ATTITUDES Some new social attitudes toward these new markets are
important elements of the envisioned approach. As with current financial
markets, the market odds should be treated as the current social consensus
on a question by popular media and policy makers. While one may of course
disagree with this consensus in conversation, it is not impolite for others
to inquire whether one who so disagrees has made investments commensurate
with their wealth and the fuss they are making. People who do so invest
should receive the same sort of social credit now granted to "do-gooder"
advocates who devote personal resources to changing current opinion on some
important issue. Like Pheleas Fogg, the hero of Verne's Around the World
in Eighty Days , "a man who rather laid wagers for honor's sake than for the
stake proposed" [Ve], these investors should not be treated as mere risk-
loving gamblers.
Social credit should also go to philanthropists who choose to subsidize a
market on some important question. By funding an automatic inventory-based
[St] market-maker, which always offers to buy or sell at prices determined
solely by its current inventory, one gives away money only to those who
move the market price in the direction of its final verdict.
Reputation scores can be computed from each person's public trades,
recorded at registries. A trade is considered "public" if the trader
committed at trading time to a date at which the trade would be publicly
revealed, and that date has passed. One simple reputation score would be
the ratio of the current market value of assets held to their value when
purchased, corrected for a few distortions. People with high reputation
scores should be respected for having been right against the crowd, and
such scores might even compete with G.P.A.s or number of papers published
as an evaluation measure.
Objections
The main difference between "blue sky" fantasies and serious but radical
suggestions is in how well they handle the details. If you are like most
readers, you will by now have thought of one or more problems with or
objections to idea futures. If so, you are encouraged to scan this section
and go directly to the issues of concern to you. (Most of these issues
have been raised by at least three independent commentators in previous
discussions.)
ISN'T GAMBLING ILLEGAL? Yes, betting markets on science questions appear
to be only legal in Great Britain, where they are highly regulated. Even
Nevada, which allows sports betting, prohibits general betting to avoid
scandals that might "taint" the gambling industry. Which is a shame because
most of the arguments against betting, discussed below, do not apply well
to science betting. We allow scattered markets that give us rather good
consensus estimates on horse races and football teams, yet not on important
science and technology questions! In the long term perhaps we can persuade
legislators to allow science bets because of their extra benefits and
reduced problems. Science betting certainly seems easier to justify than
the currently popular regressive taxation through state lotteries.
ISN'T BETTING A USELESS ZERO-SUM GAME? A standard argument for making
betting illegal is to keep people from wasting their energies in
unproductive activities. The only obvious value in betting on dice throws
is entertainment, but laws to prohibit this usually also prohibit much
more. Life insurance and commodity futures markets [Ro] were both
prohibited by anti-gambling laws until advocates managed to obtain
exemptions.
Being monetarily zero sum does not make betting useless. Betting markets
allow traders to reduce risk, and create informative prices. In liquid
markets most of the trading, liquidity, and price rationalization comes
from speculators, for whom the market is basically a betting game. Buying
any particular stock in the stock market, for example, is basically a bet
in a zero-sum game when compared to investing in the standard "market"
combination of all assets in the same tax and risk category. (While, if
the prices are irrational, such bets may help the economy as a whole, this
"externality" also benefits people not betting on that question.)
In fact, a standard way to analyze financial portfolios is to break them
into contingent assets, each of which has value in only one possible world
[ShW]. A "complete" market, where one can bet on anything, is best,
allowing investors to minimize risk and maximize expected return [La].
Science bets would not only allow corporations to more easily insure
against technological risk, but they would create prices embodying the sort
of valuable information that governments now fund research to obtain. When
the betting stakes are invested in stocks, the money is hopefully being put
into productive use by those companies. Therefore, ignoring transaction
costs and judging fees, the average rate of return of contingent assets
split from stocks would be the same as the return on those stocks.
DOES ANYBODY EVER BET THIS WAY? Liquid markets in contingent assets are a
somewhat different betting mechanism from the usual bookies or pari-
mutuels. But they are not untried. Such markets are widely used to teach
MBA students about how markets work [Fo], and are usually done on
elections. Some financial traders have used them to bet on basketball
tournaments [Pow]. And I have developed a board game where players use
such a market to bet on a murder mystery as it unfolds. Most players learn
the mechanism very quickly, and have lots of fun!
WHAT ABOUT COMPULSIVE GAMBLING? About 2% of the population seems unable to
resist the temptation to risk more than they can afford to lose [APA] in
casinos, racetracks, and high risk financial markets. Lost in the thrill
of "action" and the hope that all of their financial worries will soon be
over, they often regret their excess later, and resort to desperate
measures, like theft, to pay debts.
Compulsive gambling is encouraged by advertising and easy access to games
with a quick and possibly large payoff. British law reduces this problem
by requiring casino players to apply 48 hours in advance, by allowing them
to sign up on lists of people to be excluded from all casinos, and by
forbidding youth and on-site alcohol, entertainment, and credit [Ke].
Margin limits in financial markets serve some similar functions.
Governments may impose similar rules to discourage compulsive gambling in
idea futures, though it is important that any advertising restrictions not
prevent the wide dissemination of current market prices. More importantly,
unless options (or investments on margin) are offered, science questions
are generally too long term to be a problem, offering no more "action" than
long-term stock investments. Traders who regret their purchase a few days
later can sell and get most of their money back. And, given that many
other options markets exist, it is not clear that allowing science options
would increase opportunities for compulsive risky investing.
IS THERE ENOUGH INTEREST IN SCIENCE QUESTIONS? A recent science fiction
[Br] novel imagined wide-spread betting on science and technology
questions, supplanting horse racing in popularity. And it is possible that
having a direct, if small, influence and personal stake in science would
heighten the public's interest. At present, though, fewer people probably
follow science than football.
We don't need to interest everyone, however, just enough to pay for the
modest overheads involved. Few people have interest and opinions about the
future price of corn, yet corn futures markets thrive. A great many people
are now involved in scientific research, many more follow scientific
journals, and even more follow science in the popular media. Many of these
people have strong opinions on various science controversies and feel they
have insufficient opportunity to express them. Idea futures would thrive
if it tapped only a small fraction of current interest and effort.
Having a fraction of science funding channeled through betting markets
would certainly accomplish this. So might basic attitude changes toward
seeing markets as a legitimate place to "take a stand" on important issues,
trading scores as indicators of who is right more often, and the market
price as a valid consensus measure. Idea futures does not need large sums
of money to be successful; even when there is only $100 bet on a question,
the market still offers the social benefit of a visible consensus and
incentives for honesty.
WILL THESE MARKETS BE TOO THIN? In a market with low "liquidity", there
are so few traders that you have to wait a while to find someone willing to
trade with you. Automated market-makers [Hak], always ready to trade at
prices determined by their current inventory, can increase liquidity and
maintain a small "spread" between their buy and sell price offers. And
they can be very cheap if the basic transaction costs are low, which they
could be if thousands of markets shared the same computerized market place.
But the market might remain "thin" in the sense that prices could change
quickly against a trader in response to each small amount traded, so they
would have to wait to get a "reasonable" price. A lack of expected market
thickness can be a self-fulfilling prophecy, since traders prefer thick
markets [Ec]. This is a standard explanation for the limited number of
futures and options markets currently available. On the other hand, thin
markets are known for being good places to find overlooked bargains, and
are less prone to speculative bubbles (a single rational person can squash
one).
A thin idea futures market may actually seem better to some people, as the
cost to change the current market consensus would be less. But a thicker
market seems preferable over all. Funding channeled through market-makers
would of course thicken the markets, as would consistency arbitrage and
conditional offers that connect questions. Two people making a bet is a
very thin market, but it happens all the time.
DOESN'T BETTING ONLY WORK FOR CLEAR CUT QUESTIONS LIKE HORSE RACES?
Most organized betting focuses on questions which, like sporting events, will
become very clearly resolved in a fixed time. This minimizes disputed
verdicts and judging costs, and so it makes sense for risk and
entertainment seeking bettors to focus on such subjects. But this does not
imply that, given a specific subject area, betting markets are not a
reasonable alternative to other consensus, reputation, and incentive
mechanisms. Any incentive mechanism must pick some arbiter of quality, and
subjects that are difficult for bets are also difficult for other
approaches. For example, peer review, which uses averages of anonymous
expert reviews as a quality measure, is widely believed to work better in
the "hard sciences" than elsewhere.
Most scientific controversies seem to eventually get resolved enough to
settle a bet. This resolvability is in fact central to popular notions of
what defines science. Scientific claims are often defined as claims of
"fact" which future evidence could possibly disprove [Pop], or at least
alter our degree of confidence in. And science is widely believed to be
"progressive", so that as evidence accumulates and relevant studies
continue, opinions gradually converge. Beautiful theories killed by ugly
facts are left behind.
Actually most people believe that opinions on most questions of fact
usually converge with time, evidence, and sincere study. We hope that
history will prove us right. We debate and discuss, essentially saying
"I'll bet if we talked it out, you'd see I'm right". We take the advice of
experts, indicating that we think we would come to believe what the experts
believe, if only we were to study what the experts have studied.
Even if we aren't sure whether opinions will converge, we think there is a
good chance they would converge if only a knowledgeable and detached enough
group would spend enough effort to study and debate the question. And if
that group is diverse and independent enough, we believe we would probably
agree with them. If so, we should accept their verdict to settle a bet.
HOW OFTEN DO BELIEFS REALLY CONVERGE? Just because people believe their
opinions converge, doesn't mean that they do. After all, there are strong
social reasons to want to believe in convergence. Even if most questions
that are settled today were once controversial, this doesn't mean that most
old controversies are now settled. Perhaps yesterday's questions referred
to concepts that are not even considered to make sense today. Historical
studies, examining random scientific questions and claims of several
centuries ago, should be done to shed light on these doubts.
But there are reasons to be optimistic. Standard decision theory, though
it does not adequately account for the computational costs of deducing the
implications of theories and evidence, is instructive and indicates that
rational agents should come to agree [Se]. Consider an ideal decision
theory agent who has a degree of belief in some particular claim A and
continues to observe new evidence. Asymptotically, either all new evidence
will be irrelevant and have no bearing on A, or the agent will become
certain about whether A is true or false. Now imagine that the claim A
specifies a detailed possible world, i.e. says that the real world is one
particular world out of the many possible worlds. If two ideal agents
start out with wildly different beliefs, but neither of them is completely
certain about A, and if they both observe the same not asymptotically-
irrelevant evidence, then they will asymptotically come to agree about A.
Studies indicate that people also have strong tendencies to conform and
agree when exposed to each others opinions [Li] and arguments [My]. In
fact, the rate at which they come to agree often seems faster that can be
rationally justified by decision theory. Randomly selected legal juries
usually come to a unanimous verdict on complex legal questions.
WHAT IF BELIEFS NEVER CONVERGE? Even if beliefs usually converged, idea
futures might be unworkable if it dealt badly enough with situations where
beliefs don't converge. One approach is to have mutually exclusive claim
sets include a "this question too vague to judge" claim which the judges
could choose if it seemed clear that no amount of study or time would ever
allow a choice between the rest. Most people could then bet on the
question conditional on it being resolved. This solution fails, however,
if sincere beliefs never converge and yet it never becomes clear whether or
not beliefs will converge. A deadline by which a question must be resolved
could deal with this, but has other disadvantages.
If investors can reasonably estimate the chances that a question will be
unresolvable in this manner, then the problem is manageable. High-risk
questions will only be traded if there is enough disagreement [Ja] or
subsidies to justify it, and for low-risk questions the problem can be
ignored. And, it seems, resolvability can be estimated. Questions about
religion and morals are more difficult, as are certain long-standing
riddles like the nature of consciousness. On the other hand, a question
about a physical property of a substance, like a bond angle of some new
molecule, seems quite resolvable. As a rule, one should prefer questions
closer to direct observations. And general claims for which relevant
evidence will always be available should do better than claims like what
someone had for breakfast ten years ago.
WHAT DO CONVERGENT BELIEFS HAVE TO DO WITH TRUTH? The philosopher Peirce
claimed that "The opinion which is fated to be ultimately agreed to by all
who investigate, is what we mean by the truth" [Th]. However, the question
of whether the convergent opinion we might all come to with unlimited
evidence, study, and debate is the way the world "really" is, is beyond the
scope of the paper. Even if it isn't "truth", we are all interested in it,
and it's hard to think of a better truth-estimate on which to base academic
incentives.
WHAT ABOUT BADLY WORDED CLAIMS? Even if an issue becomes settled, a
poorly worded claim on that issue may be unresolvable. To avoid this, we need
techniques for avoiding ambiguity and incentives for players to use them.
Wording a claim so it is both relevant to some important issue and
minimally ambiguous is a skill that is routinely learned in many
professions. Lawyers and philosophers obtain clarity through standardized
words and language, and scientists are adept at finding connections between
abstract theories and specific observations. Claims should avoid slippery
concepts and phrasing which allows many interpretations. Verbose
annotations can also help by discussing motivations, examples, intended
word meanings, judging criteria, etc.
If copyright laws are interpreted as applying to claim wordings, then claim
authors may be able to charge an extra royalty fee for each join. Claim
authors would then compete with each other for royalties from investors,
who would prefer authors with reputations for writing clear and interesting
claims. Added incentives come if authors bet against their claim being
judged too vague.
To avoid excessive costs in forming a claim, a question could hold a
"clarification lottery". After a certain time, or when the market capital
reached a certain amount, judges could be funded in the usual manner to
replace a hastily worded claim with a more considered one.
Even when one cannot really word a good claim to bet on directly, markets
offer other ways to bet on a subject. For example, if one believed that
when physicists disagree with chemists, the chemists are usually right,
one could invest in a "basket" or mutual fund which bets on the side of
chemists in as many controversies as possible.
CAN'T WRONG IDEAS STILL BE USEFUL? Absolutely. If you think an idea is
probably wrong, but is probably more like the right answer than anything
else around, then bet on that. If you just think that work on the idea is
likely to inspire something interesting, then bet on that. These questions
will be harder to judge though.
WHAT IF THE FINE PRINT DIFFERS FROM THE SUMMARY? Verbose claims would
probably be described by short summary sentences or phrases in price lists,
offers, etc. As with contracts and political ballot initiatives, there are
problems when a deceptive title differs from the fine print. In extreme
cases people might sue for misrepresentation, but usually we can only
encourage the buyer to beware.
WHAT ABOUT SUCKER BETS? If a stranger offers to bet you on an oddball
subject, there is a good chance they are trying to trick you with a
deceptive claim. Even if it looks like you couldn't lose, you are well-
advised to decline; the fact that they are making an offer gives you
information.
In markets on pre-existing controversies where many traders have already
examined the claims, this is less likely, though still possible. In
general, traders should look claims over carefully and not bet unless they
honestly think they know better than than the other traders.
DON'T SCIENCE QUESTIONS RESOLVE TOO SLOWLY? The fundamental questions that
get people interested in science, such as whether the universe is infinite,
can take decades or even centuries to resolve. But this does not prevent
markets in such questions. Most any newspaper will show that people
regularly buy bonds scheduled to mature in forty years. Fifty year-olds
who buy such bonds are not counting on living to be ninety; they know they
can sell the bonds in the market at any time.
At present, you usually can't get a Ph.D. on whether the universe is
infinite; you focus instead on a smaller question that is hopefully
relevant for the bigger ones. Idea futures investors will similarly prefer
shorter-term questions. A question that takes ten years to resolve (say
starting at 50/50 and ending more than 90% certain 90% of the time) should
have the same sort of daily price fluctuations (around 1.5%) as stocks do,
and so support a similar mix of short-term speculators, and long-term
fundamentals-oriented investors.
But for longer-term questions, investing in fundamentals is less
attractive. Less information comes out per unit time in a long-term
market, so there is less money to be made for a given market thickness. And
if you must hold out for decades until other investors come to their
senses, the extra rate of return above the market average that you get for
your information may be very small, and so you may prefer to quit now if
you have better opportunities elsewhere. To make things worse, this
creates an opportunity for strategic behavior. Someone might move the
price in some direction and try to hold it there in the hope that other
traders will not be willing to hold out as long and therefore quit at a
loss.
Finally, you may not trust the underlying financial institutions to remain
stable over a century or more. Few people would probably bet that "Nuclear
war will destroy most of civilization", even though many people would like
to for insurance reasons. Even if the banks don't go bankrupt,
uncertainties about the relative long-term value of different base assets
the betting stakes could be invested in may completely swamp any added
return from winning a bet. This problem might be minimized if the "market
asset" [ShW], a maximally diversified world mutual fund, became the
standard base asset.
Even with all these problems, there will probably be rather thick and well
subsidized markets on a few very basic science questions, as funding
agencies and amateurs seeking to influence important issues would focus on
them. Such questions could be connected, through a network of conditional
offers, to related shorter-term questions which research could more
directly resolve, allowing researchers of simpler questions to obtain some
of the subsidies on the basic questions.
In financial markets, the conventional wisdom is that longer-term price
movements are less rational, as there is less incentive to correct
irrational deviations. But there is still some incentive, and so idea
futures may still offer an improvement over the existing situation.
WHY SHOULD I TRUST THE JUDGES? Even when sincere opinions would converge,
investors may worry about judges being biased by bribes or various shared
interests and associations. Fortunately, investors get to pick the assets
they buy, and therefore the judges they bet on. So they can prefer long-
lived judging organizations with reputations for fairness and avoiding
scandals, and which use various available means to discourage foul play.
Incentives for traders to settle out of court and avoid judging altogether
certainly help avoid judging foul play. So do clear-cut claims and judging
criteria that leave little room for judging discretion. If we wait so long
that the right verdict becomes "obvious" it would also be hard for judges
to cheat. Also more trustworthy are juries of people who have never had a
stake in the question, randomly selected from a large population,
deliberating openly and offering to consider any relevant evidence.
The question of whether some proposed evidence is relevant for some
deliberation could have its own betting market. If so, then juries could
offer to consider any evidence for which the market odds of relevance were
above some threshold.
Incentives to detect foul play could come from both the ability to sue
cheating judges, and possibly from large bonds which judges might post
payable to anyone who uncovers such corruption. Also, any persistent
difference in the market odds on the same claim with different judges would
constitute consensus about judging bias, flagging those judges for closer
scrutiny. Judge rating agencies might form. Finally, "appeals" markets
can give judges a direct incentive to be careful and honest, since judges
must then bet that their verdict will be upheld on appeal.
WON'T JUDGING COST TOO MUCH? Through audit lotteries, one can keep the
percentage taken by judges below any given threshold, and still afford to
pay for very detailed judging, even going so far as to choose many jurors
from widely different cultures and train them in one or more specialties
before having them adjudicate some specific issue! This approach is mainly
limited by risk aversion, which limits the attractiveness of large wins.
Most people will not want to bet so much on any one question that the
amount they might win would be much more than their total wealth. A one in
a billion chance of winning a billion dollars is not worth as much to most
people as a one in a thousand chance of winning a thousand dollars. If the
amount one would need to bet to avoid this effect is too small, it is not
worth the bother and people will bet nothing on the question.
WON'T WEALTHY PEOPLE HAVE TOO MUCH INFLUENCE? Markets are not opinion
polls where the rich get more votes; to use market influence one must risk
losing it. As in existing financial markets, rich investors who are not
specialists in some particular area will prefer to get investment advice
from someone who is a specialist, or avoid investing in that area entirely.
This is similar to the way that powerful people defer to academic
specialists now. Rich people who carelessly throw their weight around will
lose their riches.
Even so, the wealthier social classes will have more influence, as they do
now in most areas of life, including academia. If this is a problem which
you are willing to invoke the force of government to solve (I am reluctant
to do so), then the natural solution is general wealth redistribution.
This is economically much more efficient than trying to crudely keep the
rich out of any particular walk of life.
If you worry that markets would create large inequalities in academia,
don't. Influence in academia, as measured for example by number of papers
published [Pr], is far more concentrated than in most walks of life. It
seems unlikely that markets would make things worse, and could well make
things much better, as people would not need degrees or the blessing of the
academic elites to play as equals.
WON'T THE MARKET BE DOMINATED BY FOOLS? Again, markets are not opinion
polls. Anyone can invest in any open market, but they only choose to
invest where they think they have special insight or insurance needs. Even
if they are mistaken about their special insights into, say, the gold
market, they are fairly quickly taught otherwise. Most people who play
commodity markets, for example, lose their stake and quit within a year.
Such markets are dominated by the minority who have managed to play and not
go broke. If you believe otherwise, and know of some market where the
prices are obviously wrong, I suggest that you "put your money where
your mouth is" and take some of that free money you believe is sitting
there. It's easy to bad-mouth the stupid public before you have tried to
beat them.
WON'T ADVERTISING MANIPULATE OPINION? Advertising, in the sense of
campaigns to persuade through evidence and arguments, exists now in
academia and would certainly persist. Advertising, in the sense of clever
jingles and sex appeal to grab the subconscious of the impulse buyer,
should not be a problem, except perhaps if idea futures assets became a
popular fashion accessory. People do not try to affect the price of corn
futures with clever jingles; it would be like trying to sell cars by
offering free balloons to Consumer Reports technicians. The savvy
investors who dominate markets are smarter than that.
AREN'T MARKETS FULL OF CHEATS AND THIEVES? Yes, but this does not
usually distort the incentives or the consensus price much. Most cheating
is not "manipulating the price", which is rather hard to do in a liquid market,
but conflicts of interest where someone who supposedly represents someone
else uses information gained to act in their own interest.
Insider trading is mentioned below. But brokers and investment advisors
are the worst case. In markets you win whenever you can get others to do
what you just did, or when you predict what they will do and do it first.
Brokers and investment advisors often tell you to buy whatever they would
like to sell, and charge you large commissions for the "advice". Brokers
often trade for themselves just before they execute trades for you; stop
orders and margin calls are especially lucrative.
To avoid being cheated, be careful who you trust. Avoid brokers who trade
for themselves, and advisors who do not take the same risk they advise for
you.
As bets, idea futures markets cannot be cornered or monopolized. No matter
how many bets have been made, other people are always free to bet more.
WHAT ABOUT INSIDER TRADING? When an employee of a company makes money by
trading on inside information they have about that company, or by telling
someone else so they can trade, that employee is considered to be going
against the interest of the other stockholders who own the company.
Employment contracts and laws can forbid this conflict of interest, though
price movements just before major announcements show that a substantial
amount of such trading happens anyway.
Fortunately nature has no insiders or employees. The only similar problem
in idea futures is when a research lab is trying to keep a result
temporarily secret before trading on it, and an employee sneaks out and
trades first. This can be dealt with exactly as if it were stock insider
trading, through private trading records accessible to criminal
investigators.
WHAT ABOUT "MORAL HAZARD"? One of the advantages of a market is that it
offers incentives to anyone to come and contribute their knowledge about
the world. A disadvantage is that, since changing the world can give one
special knowledge about it, people may have an incentive to cause harm. If
we allow anyone to bet on your lifespan, then someone may decide to kill
you just to win a bet. And this murder may be much harder to solve than
most since, with anonymous trading, most anyone might be a potential
suspect. (Though criminal investigators should be able to learn who really
made what "anonymous" trades.) For this reason, there are usually
restrictions on who may buy how much life insurance on you.
Moral hazard should be less of a problem for basic questions about nature
that people cannot change, though it could conceivably be a problem for
short-term trading and options that bet on when information will come out.
We wouldn't want someone to blow up the latest accelerator to prevent
information from coming out, or to kill some patients to slant a medical
study.
Yet we shouldn't prevent open markets if the chance of foul play seems
small. Anyone is allowed to trade stock, even though there is a
possibility that someone will sell short the stock of the makers of
Tylenol, and then poison some packages to depress Tylenol sales. Only for
the rare claim where the risk of harm seemed particularly high might one
justify a prior restraint limiting who could have how much stake on the
different sides of a question.
WHAT ABOUT INCENTIVES TO START FALSE RUMORS? A "rumor" is just
information, perhaps false, passed informally through a social network.
Maliciously false rumors occur whenever people both have an interest in
what other socially connected people think about a question, and when there
is inadequate feedback for learning what rumors were false, so that people
can discount unreliable sources.
In current academia, there is often enough feedback to discourage false
rumors about what results are about to be published. Word of mouth which
discredits a person, however, can keep him or her out without others ever
really finding out if the rumor was right.
Markets both encourage and discourage false rumors. Markets give more
people an interest in fooling other people, but also improve the feedback
about what rumors were right. And the market price offers an alternative
to informal information channels. Again, don't believe everything you
hear; trust advisors with a good track record who take the same risk they
advise you to.
WHAT ABOUT INCENTIVES TO KEEP INFORMATION SECRET? If you acquired a
piece of information where it was clear which side of what questions the
information favored, then your best strategy would be to buy on those
sides, reveal and publicize the information (perhaps after selling it to
other traders), wait for the price to rise, and then sell at a profit. If,
however, the implications of the information are not clear, you might be
tempted to sit tight and wait for further revelations, even though you risk
other people stumbling on to your insight in the meantime. It is similar
with incentives to publish. Unless you can connect your insight to
currently popular issues, and package enough of them together to make a
paper, you cannot get published and so you keep the idea to yourself.
One approach might be to formulate a question more closely related to your
information, and then try to convince some funding agency that your
question is interesting, even if its implications are not clear. Or you
could subsidize your question, in the hope that this would encourage others
to figure out its implications and create conditional offers connecting it
to other questions. Either approach might induce enough market thickness
to make your information pay off.
WON'T AN APPARENT CONSENSUS CREATE A CROWD MENTALITY? People might
think they agreed more than they actually did, defer to a consensus that had
little thought behind it, and so create the social analogues of anchoring
and overconfidence [Kah]. Would creativity be suppressed?
Markets with less thought behind them should give themselves away by being
thinner. If not, and some of us catch wind of this trend, we could make
money by correcting for it. And, for what it's worth, the market odds at
horse races actually tend to be underconfident, being biased toward long-
shots. Markets encourage people to be contrarian in the sense that by
making any trade one is saying the consensus is probably wrong.
WILL THE NEW INCENTIVES SLOW OR STOP CONVERGENCE? This is the opposite
of the above problem. People with a stake on a certain side will become
mentally biased toward that side, resisting the rational implications of
mounting evidence. This is of course not a new phenomenon in academia, and
so it's hard to see why the problem would be worse. Except for issues
closely connected to basic "ideologies" about which most everyone has an
opinion, we can expect to find impartial jurors to bring people back to
reality.
WON'T DIFFERENT CLAIM WORDINGS, JUDGES, AND BASE ASSETS CONFUSE THE
CONSENSUS? Unless the performance of a base asset correlates with a
claim, the price should be independent of base, and arbitrageurs can easily
enforce this. If the prices on the same claim judged by different judges
were persistently different, this would constitute consensus about judging
bias, a situation that judges would want to avoid. If different claim
wordings on an issue have very different prices, this represents consensus
that there are really several different issues to be distinguished. For
each distinguishable issue, traders seeking liquidity will probably
congregate around one or a handful of base asset/wording/judge
combinations, preventing things from getting too confusing.
WON'T THE CONSENSUS REFLECT RISK PREFERENCES AS WELL AS BELIEFS? Yes,
the amount one should bet depends on one's beliefs, attitude toward risk, and
the stake one already has in a question [Kad]. Risk-avoiders bet less than
risk-takers, and bet less on the side that they already have a stake in.
Price distortions from this should be minor, unless beliefs correlate
significantly with risk attitudes and non-betting stakes, and if the stakes
held approach each person's total wealth. One exception is that few people
would bet for "Technology will soon make us all too rich to care about
money", even if they believed it.
It might seem that questions with extremely lop-sided odds would also be a
problem. Too few people might bet that "energy is conserved" (EC) if they
very confidently expected to win very little. But by splitting EC assets
along other questions, people could jointly support EC, debate other
questions, and get a higher average return.
Some people have worried that opinionated yet extremely risk averse people,
unwilling to bet on anything, would be unfairly labeled "insincere"
debaters. But it is hard for me to imagine that they could not afford to
risk even $10 a year so that we could develop a reputation score for them.
If it is the risk of a low reputation score that scares them, perhaps they
should not act so opinionated.
WON'T BETTING CHALLENGES DISCOURAGE CREATIVITY? If people were expected
to bet on every idea that comes out of their mouth, they would be more
reluctant to think up wild ideas, most of which are going to be bad.
Hopefully we can maintain a distinction between saying "Here is an
interesting idea to think about" and "This is the way it is, why won't you
agree?", only expecting people to put up or shut up in the second case.
WHAT'S THE POINT OF A "CONSENSUS" THAT PEOPLE DISAGREE WITH? Regardless
of the name used, people often want to pool their differing individual
estimates on some issue into a composite estimate. This is most clearly
needed in the "public choice" problem, where citizen estimates must be
combined into government policy. But there is also a more general need for
social institutions where experts combine their estimates on some subject
into composite estimates that non-experts can use to make individual
choices. Several such institutions may compete for attention, but the need
remains.
Most work on consensus measures [Ge,Gr,Syn] focuses on various explicit
functions to combine individual beliefs, and some simple variations of
these [Man] are now used as academic consensus mechanisms. Compared to
these, betting markets not only offer superior incentives [Ei] for people
to bother to make their beliefs explicit and honest, but betting markets
have the following unique claim to the word "consensus".
It is in the personal interest of an ideal decision theory agent to make
all external actions as if they agreed with the market consensus [Kad],
without any coercion. Agents should buy contingent assets up to the point
where their marginal rates of substitution are the same, i.e. where they
all agree on the relative value of getting one more dollar for sure vs.
even more dollars in some contingency. An external observer, who can offer
agents trades or choices but cannot tell how much each agent has already
bet, cannot tell that the agents internally disagree.
Insurance-based proposals [Fa] are similar in spirit to the betting markets
proposed here, as is the following proposal for dealing with the public
choice problem [Mu]. If a government threatens to make a change, sells
insurance on the change either way, and then makes the choice that is
cheapest for them, they produce the most efficient "parteo optimal" result.
ISN'T IT BETTER FOR PEOPLE TO ARGUE OUT THEIR OWN DISPUTES? Yes, which
is why we want incentives, such as with audit lotteries, to settle out of
court and avoid judging. Idea futures is only intended to discourage
insincere debaters.
Another way to avoid judging is to hold "argue lotteries" which are like
audit lotteries except that judges are not invoked. The idea is to focus
attention on a smaller number of markets where more is at stake. This
should induce more discussion and examination of such questions, perhaps
resulting in more related questions being formed to reflect the argument
structures proposed. Hopefully, opinions would naturally converge, and
people would leave the market. Judges are really only there to discourage
self-deception and strategic bargaining, so that the market odds eventually
reflect the "obvious".
WON'T THIS HAVE THE SAME PROBLEMS AS PATENTS? No [Hir]. With patents we
must decide who owns an idea, and so a centralized legal system must make a
great many subtle decisions with insufficient evidence and expertise. We
must examine history to decide who contributed how much to the idea. We
must define some sharp legal boundaries that determine what it is to use
the idea. With present patent law, we must also decide if an idea is true,
if it is "original", if it is "obvious", if it is a "process", if it was
revealed properly, etc. Bets are much more flexible; we need only decide
if an idea is right, and we can each choose who is to judge that question.
Government intervention and international agreement is not needed.
WOULDN'T ANONYMOUS TRADING SCREW UP REPUTATION STATISTICS? Perhaps
people could make private trades to move prices out of line, and then make
public trades on the other side to bring them back, so that those trades do
better than average. This is somewhat like giving someone a wad of money by
dropping it in the park and having them wander by an hour later to pick it
up. If the park is crowded enough, someone else will have found it by
then. In the market, anyone else could make money by stopping the price
from moving out of line. The problem is more serious, however, if everyone
accepts that only one trader has any information about a question, and so
no one else wants to bet there. If possible, such markets should be
excluded from reputation scores.
IF THIS IS SO GREAT, WHY HASN'T IT HAPPENED ALREADY? If it was in
people's interest, wouldn't there be such markets by now? Well, if we always
assumed this we might never make anything new, but it's an important
question to ask. The fact that science bets have been legal only in
Britain, and then only in the last three decades is only part of an
explanation.
English bookmakers perceive little demand for science bets, and so take
them mainly to induce popular articles mentioning the going odds on unusual
subjects [ShG]. This publicity brings in new clients, who may then switch
to the "real" betting on sports. Because of this, bookies prefer small bets
on subjects "in good taste" that anyone can understand, like UFOs, Yetis,
and Moon landings. They avoid subjects that seem too esoteric for the
general public, like the recent "cold fusion" claims, and subjects that
won't very clearly resolve themselves, as a judging industry has not yet
evolved.
Bookmakers traditionally prefer to set prices and stick to them, rather
than setting up markets, letting prices fluctuate, and playing market-
maker. Because of this, they are usually unwilling to offer bets on claims
where they do not know how to estimate the odds, and few bookies have
advanced science educations. As a result, they mainly take safe bets,
siding with the scientific establishment against "crazy" outside theories,
which doesn't help the image problem betting has in many quarters.
English bookmakers do not seem to have seriously tried to sell imagine-
conscious academics on science bets, through arguments like those in this
paper. Nor, to my knowledge, has the possibility for betting markets as a
funding mechanism been pointed out. Questions of interest to academics are
now avoided and no visible influenceable consensus is formed; one cannot
even subscribe to a publication listing the going prices on science
questions. It should be possible to improve on this.
Strategy
It's a lot easier to sketch a grand utopian vision than it is to figure out
how to get there from here. An ideal development strategy would show how
to grow incrementally, with each self-supporting step leading naturally to
the next one. Most utopian visions fail because they, instead, require too
many things to change all at once.
One advantage of idea futures is that, if not legally prohibited or
socially shunned, it can co-exist with existing academic institutions and
incrementally attract investors, patrons, and controversies. Papers would
still be published and elite committees would still convene. Professors
would gradually make more side bets, and begin to challenge each other to
bets. Journalists would gradually use the market odds in news stories
more, and funding agencies would gradually try larger amounts of subsidies.
Idea futures could rise or fall on its own merits, as people studied how
well its predictions compared to other consensus measures, and how the rate
of progress in a field depends on the fraction of funding channeled through
the markets.
Unfortunately, there also seem to be some obstacles to overcome before
gradual growth is possible. Economies of scale in forming reputable
judging organization or building secure computerized marketplaces may mean
that certain levels of participation may be required before idea futures
can "take off". But the major hurdle seems to be attitudes toward the very
idea, attitudes reflected in the world-wide legal prohibitions. There are
several possible strategies here.
One approach is more discussions, like those in this paper, of the need for
alternative academic institutions, and of betting markets as a particular
alternative. Perhaps idea futures must be disassociated from ordinary
betting, as insurance and stock bets have been, though the metaphor of bets
is very useful in explaining how it works.
Also helpful is further research on markets in conditional assets, such as
recent attempts to show them superior to opinion polls at predicting
elections [Fo]. Laboratory experiments [Sm] comparing betting markets to
some mockup of existing peer review institutions would be very interesting,
though not of course decisive.
A different approach, which I am also pursuing, would be to create an
electronic mail-based reputation game, where people play for "bragging
rights" instead of money. This would avoid legal problems and the
discomfort academics have in dealing explicitly with money, and would allow
many people from around the world to participate in a less-threatening
partial test of markets as an academic consensus mechanism. However,
avoiding money makes the incentives suspect, and precludes many of the
advantages, like insurance, that idea futures offer. If enough people
played, the scores would mean something to observers, and so people would
have an incentive to play and play well. But building a game up to this
status would be hard, probably requiring some "big name" players to attract
others.
If the basic idea became plausible enough to enough British (because
that's where its legal) intellectuals in some field, it could be seriously
tried. The initial field would preferably be one where bets are easier to
settle, like number theory, though such subjects tend to be ones where
existing institutions also work better, and so have less of a perceived
need for change. A socially important question with minimal opportunities
for conflict of interest would also be nice. Idea futures will have "made
it" when it becomes known as a good place to find out the latest thinking
on certain issues, reliably predicting what will later become consensus in
other social contexts.
Advantages
If its potential problems can be overcome, and a development path charted
and followed, idea futures offers many advantages, most of which have
already been mentioned.
There would be a clear incentive to be careful, honest, and expert, when
making public statements. People could be rewarded for being right, rather
than just for being liked by academic insiders. Those who invest wisely
would accumulate capital and gain influence, which they could reinvest in
discretionary research or in influencing future consensuses.
Funding agencies would only need to pick important questions, not who would
be good to research them. Diverse approaches could be tried to research a
question, without arbitrary penalties for crossing disciplinary boundaries,
ignoring fashion and insiders, integrating pre-existing knowledge, and
using insights too small or inarticulate to make a publishable unit.
Anyone, not just Ph.D.s, could contribute directly to the world's corpus of
knowledge. Easily published science odds and amateur betting might
increase popular interest in science, subsidize professional efforts on
questions of popular interest, and perhaps even increase the general
savings rate. Clear market odds would ease science reporting.
A visible scientific consensus would be available to guide public policy, a
consensus which would be self-consistent across a wide range of issues and
harder for media campaigns to distort. Compared to competing consensus
mechanisms, idea futures should be relatively simple, cheap, decentralized,
egalitarian, responsive to new information, and at least as informative.
This consensus should correct for many current biases, such as
overconfidence.
The mere threat of betting challenges could improve incentives in
discussions and debates. If the market consensus carried social weight, it
could serve as a coordination point for thousands of independent
conversations. A rejected visionary would have a new way to get publicity
for his ideas, and a reward for being right against the establishment.
True cranks would subsidize leveler heads, and as debates became settled,
they would leave a trail of agreed-upon statements which could be used to
counter bogus claims made by those ignorant of solid expert consensus.
Businesses could make insurance hedges against technological risk, as in
the cold fusion case. While such insurance may be legal now, the
introduction of speculators would increase market thickness to a point
where it might be practical.
Reputation scores offer a new way to evaluate people's ability to separate
the wheat from the chaff in ideas and arguments, and these scores should
depend less on whether one has curried favor with the right people.
Idea futures is well-grounded in our best theories of decision and
incentives. Once legal and accepted, idea futures could grow
incrementally, and perhaps dramatically increase our rate of scientific
progress per funding spent.
Conclusion
Markets in contingent assets, more commonly known as "bets", offer a
needed alternative to existing academic institutions. Betting markets
cannot solve all current problems, or replace all current institutions. But
if this paper has been successful, the potential of such markets should be
clear, and most of the obvious problems with such markets should have been
addressed in enough detail that we can say the idea still seems plausible
on a closer examination. If so, more serious intellectual discussion is
justified, and perhaps some small-scale experiments. We could do much
worse than having intellectual institutions as open, flexible, diverse, and
egalitarian as the stock market, with incentives as well-grounded and with
estimates on important issues as unbiased and predictive.
Acknowledgements
These ideas germinated in the fertile ground of discussions with friends
interested in similar problems, most of whom are associated in one way or
another with the company Xanadu. Eric Drexler, Mark Miller, and Phil Salin
have been particularly influential. And my wife Peggy Jackson has
influenced me in more ways than I know.
Perhaps a hundred people,more than I can list here, have provided useful
comments and criticisms on all aspects of the idea. Useful comments on
this particular paper came additionally from Amara Graps, Martin Haeberli,
and Chris Hibbert.
References
[APA] (1987) Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders Third
Edition, Revised, American Psychiatric Association, Washington D.C.
[Be] Bernal, J. (1989) "After Twenty-Five Years", Science and Public
Policy, 16:3, June, pp.143-151.
[Br] Brunner, J. (1975) The Shockwave Rider, Harper & Row, NY.
[Ci] Cialdini, R. (1988) Influence, Science and Practice, Scott, Foresman
and Co., Boston.
[De] Debus, A. (1970) Science and Education in the Seventeenth Century,
MacDonald, London.
[Dr] Drexler, K.E. (1986) Engines of Creation, Doubleday, New York.
[Do] Dowie, J. (1982) "Gambling in Education and Education in Gambling",
Proc. Fifth Intl. Conf. on Gambling and Risk Taking, ed. William
Eadington, pp.23-39.
[Ec] Economides, N., Siow, A. (1988) "The Division of Markets is Limited by
the Extent of Liquidity (Spatial Competition with Externalities)",
American Economic Review, March, pp.108-121.
[Ei] Eisenberg, E., Gale, D. (1959) "Consensus of Subjective Probabilities.
The Pari-mutuel Method" Ann. Math. Statist. 30. pp.165-168.
[Fa] Fairley, W., Meyer, M., Chernick, P. (1984) "Insurance Market
Assessment of Technological Risk", Proc. Soc. for Risk Analysis Internl.
Workshop on Uncertainty in Risk Assessment, Risk Management, and Decision
Making, Sept. 30, pp.89-102.
[Fe] Feyerabend, P., (1975) "How to Defend Society Against Science",
Radical Philosophy, 2, Summer, pp.4-8.
[Fo] Forsythe, R., Nelson, F., Neumann, G., Wright, J. (1990) "The
Explanation and Prediction of Presidential Elections: A Market
Alternative to Polls" Economics Working Paper 90-11, April 12. Univ. of
Iowa, Iowa City.
[Gal] Galileo, Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems, transl. by
Stillman Drake, 2nd ed., Berkeley, Univ. of California Press, 1967.
[Gar] Garwin, R. (1989) "Consensus on Cold fusion still elusive" Nature,
338, April 20.
[Ge] Genest, C., Zidek, J. (1986) "Combining Probability Distributions: A
Critique and Annotated Bibliography", Statistical Science 1:1, pp.114-
148.
[Gh] Ghiselin, Michael T. (1989) Intellectual Compromise: The Bottom Line,
Paragon House Publ., NY.
[Gr] Grofman, B., Owen, G. eds. (1986) Information Pooling and Group
Decision Making: Proc of the Second Univ. Cal. Irvine Conf. on Political
Economy, JAI Press, Inc. London.
[Hak] Hakansson, N., Beja, A., Kale, J. (1985) "On the Feasibility of
Automated Market Making by a Programmed Specialist", J. Finance, March.
[Hal] Hall, S. (1989) "Professor Thorne's Time Machine" California,
October, pp.68-77.
[Han88] Hanson, R. (1988) "Toward Hypertext Publishing, Issues and Choices
in Database Design", ACM SIGIR Forum, 22:1,2 Winter 1988.
[Han90] Hanson, R. (1990) "Market-Based Foresight - A Proposal", Foresight
Update, 10, publ. of Foresight Institute, P.O. Box 61058, Palo Alto, CA
94306.
[He] Henrion, M., Fischhoff, B. (1986) "Assessing Uncertainty in Physical
Constants", Am. J. Phys. 54:9, September, pp.791-798.
[Hir] Hirshleifer, J. (1971) "The Private and Social Value of Information
and the Reward to Inventive Activity", American Economics Review, 61:4,
Sept., pp. 561-74.
[Ja] Jaffray, J. (1989) "Coherent Bets Under Partially Resolving
Uncertainty and Belief Functions", Theory and Decision, 26, 99-105.
[Kad] Kadane, J., Winkler, R. (1988) "Separating Probability Elicitation
from Utilities" J. American Stat. Assoc., June, 83:402, Theory and
Methods, pp. 357-363.
[Kah] Kahneman, D., Tversky, A., eds., (1982) Judgment under uncertainty:
Heuristics and biases, Cambridge Univ. Press, NY.
[Kan] Kantrowitz, A. (1977) "The Science Court Experiment: Criticisms and
Responses", Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, April, pp.44-50.
[Ke] Kelley, J. (1988) "Compulsive Gambling in Britain", J. Gambling
Behavior, 4:4 Winter, p.291
[Ki] Kitcher P. (1990) "The Division of Cognitive Labor", J. Philosophy,
87:1, January, pp.5-22.
[La] Laffont, J.J. (1989) The Economics of Uncertainty and Information, MIT
Press.
[Led] Lederberg, J. (1989) "Does Scientific Progress Come from Projects or
People?" Current Contents, 48, November 27, pp.4-12.
[Lew] Lewis, H.W., (1989) "Fusion isn't just around the corner" San Jose
Mercury News, April 7, Opinion page.
[Li] Linstone, L., Turoff, M., ed. (1975) The Delphi Method, Addison-
Wesley, London.
[Mal] Malkiel, B. (1989) "Is the Stock Market Efficient?" Science, 243,
March 10, pp.1313-1318.
[Man] Mann, C. (1990) "Meta-Analysis in the Breech" Science 249, August 3,
pp.476-480.
[Mar] Marshall, E. (1990) "Science Beyond the Pale", Science 249, July 6,
pp.14-16.
[May] Mayer, M. (1988) Markets, Norton & Co., NY.
[Mu] Mueller, D. (1979) Public Choice, Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge.
[My] Myers, D. (1983) Social Psychology, 2nd ed., McGraw-Hill.
[NS] (1990) "Feedback Column", New Scientist, July 14. See also 2/10, 7/28.
[Pe] Pearl, J. (1988) Probabilistic Reasoning in Intelligent Systems:
Networks of Plausible Inference, Morgan Kaufmann Publ., Inc., San Mateo,
CA.
[Pol] Polinsky, M, (1983) An Introduction to Law and Economics, LittleBrown
and Co., Boston.
[Poo] Pool, R. (1989) "Bulls Outpace Bears - For Now!" Science, 244, April
28, p.421.
[Pop] Popper, K. (1985) Popper Selections, ed D. Miller, Princeton Univ.
Press.
[Pow] Power, W. (1989) "Hottest Commodity In Wall Street Pits? Georgetown
Hoyas", Wall Street Journal, March 24, p.A1.
[Pr] Price, D.J. de Solla (1963) Little Science, Big Science, and Beyond,
Colombia Univ. Press, NY.
[Re] Redner, H. (1987) "Pathologies of Science", Social Epistemology, 1:3,
pp.215-247.
[Ro] Rose, I.N. (1986) Gambling and the Law, Gambling Times Incorporated,
Hollywood.
[Se] Seidenfeld, T. (1990) "Two Perspectives on Consensus for (Bayesian)
Inference and Decisions" Knowledge Representation and Defeasible
Reasoning, H. Kyburg, et. al. eds. pp267-286.
[ShW] Sharpe, W. (1985) Investments, 3rd Ed., Prentice Hall, NJ.
[ShG] Sharpe, G. (1990) phone conversations, William Hill Org. Ltd. 19
VAlentine Pl. London SE1 8QH, July.
[Sm] Smith, V. (1986) "Experimental Methods in the Political Economy of
Exchange", Science, 234, October 10, pp.167-173.
[St] Stoll, H. (1989) "Inferring the Components of the Bid-Ask Spread:
Theory and Empirical Tests", J. Finance, 44:1, March. pp.115-134.
[Syk] Sykes, C. (1988) ProfScam, St. Martin's Press, NY.
[Syn] (1985) Synthese, "Consensus" issue, 62:1, Jan
[Th] Thayer, H. (1980) "Peirce on Truth", Two Centuries of Philosophy in
America, ed. P. Caws. Towman & Littlefield, Totowa NJ.
[Ts] Tsao, J. (1989) "Consumer preferences and funding priorities in
scientific research", Science and Public Policy, 16:5, October, pp.294-
298.
[Tu] Tullock, G. (1966) The Organization of Inquiry, Duke Univ. Press,
London.
[Ve] Verne, J. (1872) Around the World in Eighty Days
[Wh] White, F. (1946) Famous Utopias of the Renaissance, Hendricks House
Inc, Putney Vermont.
[WSJ] (1989) "Fusion Fuss Is Turning Scientists Into Gamblers" Wall Street
Journal, April 18.
[Ze] Zeckhauser, R., Viscusi, W. (1990) "Risk Within Reason", Science, 248,
May 4, pp.559-564